Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T09:01:05.708Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Our values and our historical understanding of psychiatrists

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2023

Claire Hilton*
Affiliation:
Royal College of Psychiatrists, London, UK; Birkbeck University of London, London, UK
*
Correspondence to Claire Hilton ([email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Summary

Many people like to perceive themselves as better than previous generations: more knowledgeable, moral, tolerant and humane. Values associated with these aspects of ourselves may affect how we understand our professional forebears. In the early 20th century, some psychiatrists adopted new biomedical theories, including focal sepsis and eugenics, which resulted in inestimable harm. Detrimental clinical practices arose and were perpetuated in the context of societal values, medical ethics and other forces within and outside the medical profession. Historical understanding of the processes by which these things took place may help inform debate concerning current and future challenges of providing psychiatric care. The methods by which psychiatrists consider their predecessors may also have a bearing on how psychiatrists of the future will perceive us, the psychiatrists of the 2020s.

Type
Cultural Reflections
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Royal College of Psychiatrists

Many people, including in the medical profession, like to perceive themselves as better than previous generations: more knowledgeable, more moral, more tolerant and more humane. The assumption that we are better than our forebears may foster complacency about present-day psychiatry and discourage learning from our predecessors’ decisions and actions. In consequence, we may deprive ourselves of insights that could help inform our approach to challenges we encounter in the course of our work.Reference Ash, Hilton, Freudenthal, Stephenson and Ikkos1 As Peter Lepping and Rob Poole wrote recently: ‘The process of analysing and accepting psychiatry's past can help our profession to get closer to its real self and on a path to a better future’.Reference Lepping and Poole2 This sense of self and identity with our forebears, as psychiatrists and through our professional institutions, can make balanced historical analyses all the harder.

The Royal College of Psychiatrists is one of many organisations seeking to understand its history without whitewashing the unfavourable. This task is far from straightforward. The College has recently debated whether we should ‘judge’ the past by past or present values.Reference Rees3 I would argue that although the present can assist us to probe the past, by providing new perspectives and tools to help us to formulate our questions about it,Reference Braun4 the present cannot provide a benchmark against which we can ‘judge’ our predecessors. If we use present-day values in this way, we create an uneven playing field whereby we disadvantage past generations, who could not have foreseen our frames of reference today.

The claim that we might critique our predecessors by current values and standards also assumes that we possess a single, uniform set of them. Political regimes and freedom of speech suggest otherwise. The ‘golden rule’, the ethical principle of treating others as one wants to be treated, found in most religions and cultures is also interpreted variably through legal, cultural, religious and other values-based frameworks that shape its practice. Consequently, ethics, values and behaviours today may differ between neighbours and colleagues on issues such as the sanctity of human life, including abortion and assisted dying. Rather than uniform, our values may be personalReference Jordanova5,Reference Carr6 and hardly create a firm foundation for considering the actions of our predecessors.

Codes of medical ethics are also interpreted variably and in dialogue with the context of the time, including ideologies, science and other contemporary concerns. Regarding, for example, principles of beneficence and non-maleficence, some clinicians today acknowledge that medicine cannot be practised without harm, whether idiosyncratic reactions, side-effects or human error, when treating individual patients, or broader risks relating to environmental sustainability.Reference Abbasi7,Reference Page and Krzanowski8 Since medical ethical codes are contextualised, our predecessors’ words and actions would likewise have been determined by their own eras. Regarding psychiatry, it is also risky to consider its practice outside the legal frameworks that inevitably influenced past clinical decision-making, diagnosis and care: well into the 20th century in England, homosexual acts, attempts at suicide and admitting a person to a public mental hospital without a magistrate's order were all crimes.

As with all research, investigators need to adopt the most appropriate methodology to achieve the most meaningful answers: standard academic historical methods attempt to investigate the past from within it, as objectively as data will allow, rather than with hindsight. In our world of ‘woke’ awareness of racial prejudice and discrimination, culture, memory and commemoration, and the current and important widespread interest in historical rights and wrongs, we need to attempt to understand our forebears in their own setting. This essay explores aspects of this, not just who did what, but also how their actions came about and were promulgated. To do this, I have drawn on some controversial practices of early 20th century psychiatrists in the context of biomedical discoveries prominent at that time. I also consider how future generations may regard us, the psychiatrists of the turbulent early 2020s.

Psychiatrists and the early 20th century biomedical context

Around the early 20th century, biomedical discoveries of invisible causes of disease, including micro-organisms, genetics, hormones and vitamins, plus new technologies, such as X-rays and blood transfusion, became established in medical practice. Psychiatrists, alongside their physician and surgeon colleagues, hoped that new discoveries would reveal aetiologies, prophylaxes and cures, especially concerning intractable and fatal disorders. Lacking rigorous codes of ethics regarding human experimentation, and with medical statistics in its infancy,Reference Norton9 medical practitioners in many specialties attempted new treatments compatible with the standards and knowledge of their day.Reference Graves10 Desperate diseases attracted desperate remedies, but reports by clinicians who introduced new treatments tended to magnify successes and obscure failures. This could perpetuate ineffective or detrimental practices.Reference Young11,Reference Visick12

Focal sepsis

Henry Cotton, psychiatrist and medical director of the State Mental Hospital at Trenton, New Jersey, sought to provide humane and ‘proper care of the insane’.Reference Cotton13 He seized upon a widely accepted theory derived from microbiology: ‘focal sepsis’. Its proponents claimed that bacteria, their toxins or metabolic by-products in one organ of the body could cause damage in another. Against a background of knowledge that fevers caused delirium, poor oral hygiene was associated with endocarditis, and tetanus and diphtheria bacteria acted through toxins, it was not too far-fetched to suppose that similar mechanisms might cause mental disorders. Within the boundaries of accepted medical science, to eradicate focal sepsis, Cotton prescribed surgical removal of patients’ teeth and various organs. A complex multifaceted scenario ensued. This included external scientific reviews of Cotton's work which discredited it, indicating that his data were flawed and the surgery caused excessive harm. The generally well-respected Baltimore Professor of Psychiatry Adolph Meyer was involved in the analysis of the data, but there is evidence that he also helped conceal its conclusions, and Cotton continued with his surgical procedures.Reference Scull14 The combination of Cotton's hubris, the covering up of research findings and continuation of the surgical procedures with the approval of the institution's administrative leadership, showed a profound disregard of humanity both within and outside the medical profession.

Around the same time, medical practitioners other than psychiatrists were encouraging surgical procedures that aimed to eradicate focal sepsis from organs and tissues suspected of harbouring it. That included removing tonsils in which focal sepsis was assumed to be lurking, since the effects of focal sepsis were considered detrimental to children's physical and mental development. With the axiom of prevention being better than cure, ‘routine’ tonsillectomy became commonplace, acceptable to both public and professionals.Reference Capps15 In the UK in the 1920s, around 80 000 children underwent the procedure annually, and some died from it. Although Cotton is narrated as a historical pariah,Reference Scull14,Reference Scull, Murray and Turner16 the historiography of routine tonsillectomy largely lets its advocates off the hook.Reference Dwyer-Hemmings17 It would be surprising if the reality was quite so clear-cut. Rather, these contrasting scenarios suggest the need for honest and accurate historical contextualisation of past happenings and avoiding preconceived perspectives such as those of ‘anti-psychiatry’ or the ‘great men’ narratives common in the history of medicine more broadly. We need to explore the factors around when, how and why ‘the road to hell is paved with good intentions’ regarding patients’ lives.

Eugenics

Another public and professional medical interest during the early 20th century was eugenics. Eugenicists, whose statistical methodology did not distinguish causal and associated factors, or nature and nurture, assumed the primacy of genetics for many disorders. They therefore aimed ‘to improve the biological quality of a population’ by influencing human reproduction through education, legal and physical means justified by their scientific knowledge.Reference Roelcke18 Concerning mental function, internationally, eugenicists proposed sterilising people with mental disability or chronic mental illness deemed to be inherited, to prevent similar conditions occurring in future generations. They also proposed sterilisation when they considered that the person's mental state made them incapable of bringing up their own children. However, medical, societal and governmental forces in different places created different practices. For example, in the USA, the state of Indiana passed the country's first eugenics-based sterilisation law in 1907.Reference Stern19 In the UK, a Sterilisation Bill proposed in Parliament in 1931 failed to become law.20 By contrast, in Sweden, from 1935 until 1975, the law allowed sterilisation on the advice of the medical profession and without the patient's consent.Reference Lennerhed21

The scene was also different in Germany, where, in 1920, Professor of Psychiatry Alfred Hoche and Karl Binding, a lawyer, proposed ‘the destruction of life unworthy of life’ for people considered a burden on the state.Reference Binding, Hoche and Modak22 Although debated, their call fell on fertile soil – including within psychiatry – and germinated in the context of social, political and economic turmoil after the First World War.Reference Mueller and Beddies23 In 1937, Ernst Rüdin, also a Professor of Psychiatry in Germany, addressed an international psychiatry congress about eugenics. He justified compulsory sterilisation for people with chronic mental conditions, since ‘The hereditary health of the people must come first and upon the mental specialist devolves an absolute duty to recognize this’. The audience opposed Rüdin with ‘unanimity of opinion’, citing scientific and societal arguments.Reference Blaisdell24 Nevertheless, under the Nazi regime, Rüdin's scheme morphed into a process of annihilation, aligned with Hoche and Binding's ideas and to which other psychiatrists contributed.Reference Schneider25,Reference Sheffer26

Forces shaping clinical practice

In magnitude, the ultimate deleterious effects of Rüdin's and Cotton's actions are incomparable. However, for both, forces outside the medical profession influenced implementation of their methods, the state for Rüdin and the hospital authorities for Cotton. Also, both psychiatrists appeared to reject outright their peers who opposed them based on conflicting scientific evidence. The uncritical continuation of practices long after they have been shown to be detrimental is arguably more unethical than the misinformed but logically argued and seemingly well-intentioned introduction of new methods in the context of their times. Insulin coma treatment for schizophrenia provides another example of this: the practice continued, including in the UK, long after research indicated much harm with no benefit.Reference Bourne27Reference Freudenthal and Moncrieff29 How our forebears dealt with criticism and opposing evidence, and weighed up their theories and actions in the light of scientific and clinical observations,Reference Jowett30 may give us pointers to an individual's medical ethical values, humility and humanity regarding clinical undertakings, contributing to how we should regard them today.

Other examples of societal and political forces shaping psychiatric practice included designating homosexuality as a mental disorder requiring ‘treatment’Reference Dickinson31 and the relationship between political dissidence and ‘sluggish schizophrenia’ in the former Soviet Union.Reference Wilkinson32 Currently, in the USA, at the interface of psychiatry and physical medicine, we have the ‘opioid crisis’, attributed to the confluence of doctors’ efforts to improve pain management and aggressive marketing and pecuniary interests of the pharmaceutical industry.Reference DeWeerdt33 These episodes indicate the murkier side of medical practice, psychiatry in particular. Psychiatry, politics, law, science, ethics and societal values all interplayed in the past and continue to influence the realities of clinical practice. We ignore them at our peril.

Conclusions: past, present and future

A short, history-based paper necessitates some degree of selection of illustrative examples. Those in this paper have been chosen to provoke thought rather than to be representative. Space does not allow further exploration of the complexities of the issues or the historical methodologies involved, but more details of these can be found in many of the references already cited. The situations discussed are extreme and, fortunately, rare but the principles and issues associated with them recur in less dramatic ways. Without historical understanding of how beneficial and detrimental clinical practices arose and were perpetuated, we will not learn from them in ways that could help us frame questions and inform debate, and generate and evaluate possible solutions concerning current challenges. It cannot be assumed that biomedical and other practices appropriate to clinical specialties in physical illness translate meaningfully into psychiatry, and just because practices become established does not mean that they are fit for purpose clinically, scientifically or ethically. That includes the current use of remote clinical consultations, appropriate for pandemic circumstances but requiring evaluation to ensure the greatest benefit and the least harm as circumstances change.Reference Galvin, Desselle, Gavin, Quigley, Flear and Kilbride34 A further current ethical consideration is the proposal for whole-genome sequencing of every UK newborn:Reference Devlin35 reflection on the relationship between genetics and eugenics in the past may inform debate today on genetics and genetic engineering, alternatively known as ‘modern eugenics’.

Psychiatrists often generalise negatively about the practices of their forebears, many of whom, a century ago, worked in ‘asylums’, grappling with patients’ mental and physical disorders with inadequate illness classification systems, limited treatment options and constraints of under-resourcing, bureaucracy and a Lunacy Act unfit for purpose. Not all medical practice today is as good as it should be, and people suffer as a result. Every time we say ‘it is the best under the circumstances’ we imply that we are not treating our patients as we would wish.

The practice of psychiatry has always been complex and multifactorial, and understanding the past may help us better appreciate the diversity of perceptions and conceptions affecting contemporary, and future, goals. Future generations of psychiatrists, unless they understand the context and dilemmas of our clinical endeavours today, may well view us negatively as we might generalise about our predecessors, perpetuating the idea that they are better than their forebears and therefore writing off the possibility of learning from our mistakes alongside our successes. Hypothetically, future generations may one day write about us, the psychiatrists of the 2020s, that:

‘Morale in many of their multidisciplinary teams was dreadful, with high staff turnover. They admitted patients out of area miles from home. People with schizophrenia died years before their mentally well peers. The reality of care ‘in’ the community was care ‘by’ the community. They also kept changing their consensus-based, unscientific classifications of mental disorders. Much of what they did was wrong or harmful.’

These uncomplimentary perceptions might reflect the reality of practice for many National Health Service clinicians today, but they hardly reflect what we strive to achieve or the external constraints that gnaw at us, or how we try to overcome them. Future generations might be less critical if they adopt a nuanced, contextualised view of political, policy, economic, social, scientific, legal, COVID-19 and other influences on clinical services.Reference Turner, Hayward, Angel, Fulford, Hall and Millard36 For us today, by grasping the contextual elements, we are in the privileged position of being better able to understand and learn from our predecessors and, possibly, also to shape the history that future generations may write about us.

About the author

Claire Hilton, FRCPsych, FRHistS, is historian in residence at the Royal College of Psychiatrists and an Honorary Research Fellow at Birkbeck University of London, London, UK.

Data availability

Data availability is not applicable to this article as no new data were created or analysed in this study.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Dr Peter Carpenter and Professors Anne Harrington, Matthew Broome and Ilana Crome for their comments and discussion.

Funding

This work received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Declaration of interest

C.H. is a member of BJPsych Bulletin editorial board and did not take part in the review or decision-making process of this paper.

References

Ash, G, Hilton, C, Freudenthal, R, Stephenson, T, Ikkos, G. History of psychiatry in the curriculum? History is part of life and life is part of history: why psychiatrists need to understand it better. Br J Psychiatry 2020; 217: 535–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lepping, P, Poole, R. Psychiatry's need for Vergangenheitsbewältigung: ‘culture wars’, cognitive dissonance and coming to terms with the past. BJPsych Open 2022; 8(6): e202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rees, P, Wessely S, Poole R. 180th Anniversary Webinar: Debate ‘Should psychiatrists from history be judged by today's standards?’. Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2021 (https://www.rcpsych.ac.uk/events/free-webinars/free-webinars-for-members).Google Scholar
Braun, B. Person and ethics of a psychiatrist during National Socialism: Friedrich Meggendorfer (1880–1953). Hist Psychiatry 2020; 31: 93104.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jordanova, L. History in Practice (2nd edn). Bloomsbury Academic, 2006.Google Scholar
Carr, EH. What is History? Penguin, 1990.Google Scholar
Abbasi, K. First do no harm: the impossible oath. BMJ 2019; 366: l4734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, L, Krzanowski, J. The College's work to promote sustainability. Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2022 (https://www.rcpsych.ac.uk/improving-care/working-sustainably/about-sustainability-in-mental-health-care).Google Scholar
Norton, BJ. Karl Pearson and statistics: the social origins of scientific innovation. Soc Stud Sci 1978; 8: 334.10.1177/030631277800800101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graves, TC. Discussion on focal sepsis as a factor in disease: focal sepsis as a factor in the causation of mental disorder. Proc R Soc Med 1926; 19: 16–8.Google ScholarPubMed
Young, RE. The history of breast cancer surgery: Halsted's radical mastectomy and beyond. Aust Med Stud J 2013; 24 Jul (https://www.amsj.org/archives/3019).Google Scholar
Visick, AH. Measured radical gastrectomy: review of 505 operations for peptic ulcer. Lancet 1948; 251: 551–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotton, H. The Defective Delinquent and Insane: The Relation of Focal Infections to their Causation, Treatment and Prevention. Oxford University Press, 1921.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scull, A. Madhouse: A Tragic Tale of Megalomania and Modern Medicine. Yale University Press, 2005.Google Scholar
Capps, FCW. The faucial tonsils and accessory sinuses of the nose in relation to focal sepsis. Postgrad Med J 1940; 16: 3441.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scull, A. Desperate remedies: a gothic tale of madness and modern medicine. In Lectures on the History of Psychiatry (eds Murray, RM, Turner, T): 144–69. Gaskell, 1990.Google Scholar
Dwyer-Hemmings, L. A wicked operation”? Tonsillectomy in twentieth-century Britain. Med Hist 2018; 62: 217–41.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Roelcke, V. Eugenic concerns, scientific practices: international relations in the establishment of psychiatric genetics in Germany, Britain, the USA and Scandinavia, c.1910-60. Hist Psychiatry 2019; 30: 1937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, AM. Sterilized in the name of public health: race, immigration, and reproductive control in modern California. Am J Public Health 2005; 95: 1128–38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
House of Commons. House of Commons debate: Sterilization (1931 Jul 21, vol 255 cols 1249–57 (https://api.parliament.uk/historic-hansard/commons/1931/jul/21/sterilization).Google Scholar
Lennerhed, L. Sterilisation on eugenic grounds in Europe in the 1930s: news in 1997 but why? Reprod Health Matters 1997; 5: 156–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binding, K, Hoche, A. Allowing the Destruction of Life Unworthy of Life: Its Measure and Form (trans Modak, C). Suzeteo Enterprises, 2012.Google Scholar
Mueller, T, Beddies, T. “The destruction of life unworthy of living” in national socialist Germany. Int J Ment Health 2006; 35: 94104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaisdell, RE. Resumé of papers presented at the International Congress on Mental Hygiene held at Paris, July 19–24, 1937. Psychiatr Q 1938; 12: s2634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schneider, F. Psychiatry under National Socialism: remembrance and responsibility. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 2011; 261(suppl 2): s111–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sheffer, E. Asperger's Children: The Origins of Autism in Nazi Vienna. Norton, 2018.Google Scholar
Bourne, H. The insulin myth. Lancet 1953; 265: 964–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ackner, B, Harris, A, Oldham, AJ. Insulin treatment of schizophrenia; a controlled study. Lancet 1957; 272: 607–11.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Freudenthal, R, Moncrieff, J. ‘A landmark in psychiatric progress’? The role of evidence in the rise and fall of insulin coma therapy. Hist Psychiatry 2021; 33: 6578.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jowett, R. Sinus sepsis and mental disorder. J Ment Sci 1936; 82: 2837.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dickinson, T. ‘Curing Queers’: Mental Nurses and their Patients, 1935–74. Manchester University Press, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkinson, G. Political dissent and “sluggish” schizophrenia in the Soviet Union. BMJ (Clin Res Ed) 1986; 293: 641–2.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DeWeerdt, S. Tracing the US opioid crisis to its roots. Nature 2019; 573: S10–2.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Galvin, E, Desselle, S, Gavin, B, Quigley, E, Flear, M, Kilbride, K, et al. Patient and provider perspectives of the implementation of remote consultations for community-dwelling people with mental health conditions: a systematic mixed studies review. J Psychiatr Res 2022; 156: 668–78.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Devlin, H. What are pros and cons of whole-genome sequencing for every UK baby? Guardian 2021; 2 Dec (https://www.theguardian.com/science/2021/dec/02/what-are-pros-and-cons-of-whole-genome-sequencing-for-every-uk-baby).Google Scholar
Turner, J, Hayward, R, Angel, K, Fulford, B, Hall, J, Millard, C, et al. The history of mental health services in modern England: practitioner memories and the direction of future research. Med Hist 2015; 59: 599624.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.