Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T16:39:10.578Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Critical reflections on psychiatry: Could Thomas Szasz still have relevance in modern medical practice?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Janaki Bansal*
Affiliation:
ST6 Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, Tavistock and Portman NHS Foundation Trust, London, UK; email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an open-access article published by the Royal College of Psychiatrists and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 The Author

Tony B. Benning provides a considered review of the main arguments proposed by Thomas Szasz and explores their relevance in the present day. Reference Benning1 On the surface, many of Szasz's arguments are easy to refute: Benning cites Kendell, Reference Kendell and Schaler2 who draws attention to areas of similarity between medical and psychiatric diagnoses – for example, the importance of distress and impairment of function in the definition of illness. Szasz's criticism of the nature of boundaries between mental health and illness can also be applied to physical health conditions such as type 2 diabetes and hypertension, in which pathology is determined to occur at the extremes of continuous variables. As with psychopathology, the cut-off point at which it is believed there is a risk to well-being significant enough to justify intervention is to some extent arbitrary, as evidenced by intermittent changes in international definitions of the thresholds for diagnosing and treating these conditions.

However, as Benning points out, psychiatrists might do well to bear in mind some of Szasz's concerns, particularly those around the interlinking themes of personal responsibility and psychiatric power. It may be clear to those who have witnessed the deviation from the authentic self (encountered in severe mental illness) that sufferers lack capacity for meaningful autonomous decision-making and that a duty exists for doctors to treat in their best interests as they would for any critical illness. At the same time, it is widely acknowledged that a diagnosis of mental illness does not necessarily entail incompetence, as acknowledged by the Mental Health Act's consideration of patients deemed to have the capacity to refuse treatment while detained. Reference Jones3 I would argue that where clinicians believe an individual retains the capacity for autonomy, exercising their legal power to detain and compulsorily treat against the individual's wishes goes against the fundamental tenets of medical ethics and violates the doctor-patient relationship. Szasz's dismissal of psychiatrists as agents of a therapeutic state appears to have some traction here.

Another area of continuing relevance is Szasz's condemnation of the pathologisation of human experience. It is, arguably, beneficence that drives the profession to try to alleviate – through diagnosis and therapeutic intervention – suffering that in part originates from the experience of social adversity. Delgadillo et al highlight the increased prevalence of mental ill health in more economically deprived areas and the lower rates of recovery found in these populations; Reference Delgadillo, Asaria, Ali and Gilbody4 clinical commissioning groups responsible for the local provision of psychological therapies are categorised as underperforming with regards to the latter.

However, when health services are blamed for patients failing to improve, society effectively abdicates from its responsibility to address the inequalities and social ills that may explain distress better than any medical nosology, as Szasz contended. Under these circumstances the psychiatric profession may not be pursuing its own political agenda so much as being caught up in a greater one, which might potentially overwhelm its capacity to function in the current climate of financial constraint. Ironically, Szasz's criticism of the pathologising of day-to-day life also serves to draw further parallels between physical and mental illness. Take, for example, obesity, which the medical profession are being increasingly held responsible for addressing, despite there being clear social determinants. Reference Loring and Robertson5 An awareness of professional boundaries and limitations could avoid compromising the delivery of care in areas that are clearly within the medical sphere, and challenge any attempt to avoid responsibility for societal well-being by other sectors such as welfare and housing.

Thus, while Benning sets out many arguments that demonstrate how Szasz might be wrong, he is pertinent in recommending the consideration of his writings as a moral exercise, challenging ourselves to reflect on the ways in which he might be right.

References

1 Benning, TB. No such thing as mental illness? Critical reflections on the major ideas and legacy of Thomas Szaz. BJPsych Bull 2016; 40: 292–5.Google Scholar
2 Kendell, RE. The myth of mental illness. In Szasz Under Fire: The Psychiatric Abolitionist Faces his Critics (ed Schaler, JA). Open Court, 2004.Google Scholar
3 Jones, R. Code of Practice Mental Health Act 1983. In Mental Health Act Manual (11th edn): p. 695. Sweet and Maxwell, 2008.Google Scholar
4 Delgadillo, J, Asaria, M, Ali, S, Gilbody, S. On poverty, politics and psychology: the socioeconomic gradient of mental healthcare utilisation and outcomes. Br J Psychiatry 2016; 209: 429–30.Google Scholar
5 Loring, B, Robertson, A. Obesity and inequities. Guidance for addressing inequities in overweight and obesity. World Health Organization, 2014.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.