Italian revolutionaries were still licking their wounds in prison or exile after the armed repression of the 1848/49 revolutions, when, in October 1850, one of their number, Bertrando Spaventa (1817–1883), then in exile in Turin, received a letter from his fellow revolutionary Pasquale Villari (1826–1917). The latter, himself then in exile in Florence, urged his friend to keep teaching and studying the philosophy of Hegel. Although it was difficult to promote foreign philosophies in Turin, especially those expressed in the German language and therefore tainted by association with the Austrian ‘invader’, Hegel’s was the philosophical system best able to sustain a nation intent on developing its self-consciousness. Villari thus believed the promotion of the Hegelian philosophy to be the most urgent task facing Italy at that time:
If we could only get Italians to understand Hegel, Italy would be regenerated …. Without philosophy we cannot become a nation …. Italy needs to find a system representing the whole of its nationality, one that gathers together whatever elements of life there are in the whole peninsula; but, first of all, it needs to recover its self-consciousness, and no system is more capable of this than the Hegelian.Footnote 1
Both Spaventa and Villari were hounded by the Bourbon police on account of their active participation in the 1848 Neapolitan revolution. They were therefore obliged to flee the Kingdom of Two Sicilies and seek refuge in another Italian state. The Kingdom of Piedmont-Sardinia, in particular when under the guidance of Camillo Benso Count of Cavour (1810–1861), had become one of the most appealing destinations for Italian revolutionaries, the only Italian State to have retained its 1848 Constitution, the Statuto Albertino (Albertine Statute). The Savoyard state had undergone what Christopher Clark has termed a ‘European revolution in government’, exemplified by the promulgation of the Sicardi Law, which had eliminated privileges of clergy and alienated the former aristocratic rights.Footnote 2
The regeneration of the nation to which Villari refers was indeed a widespread preoccupation in nineteenth-century nationalisms. Italian patriots thus frequently employed the words ‘Regeneration’ and ‘Resurgence’ (Risorgimento) to indicate their common endeavour. What is crucial, though, is that the philosophy to be understood and ‘popularised’ was Hegel’s, a philosophy entirely oriented towards the understanding of the State rather than of the nation. In order to regenerate the nation, Hegel needed to be ‘translated’ for the Italian public: ‘Hegel is the Aristotle of the new civilization … but Hegel cannot be translated like Aristotle, one needs to understand him, render him intelligible without superficiality, render him popular, not vulgar.’Footnote 3 This is because Hegel’s philosophy argues that liberty is the unfolding in history of a process of self-consciousness and that the political liberty of a community is possible only through the development of the self-consciousness of the people about their past and their national character. This was the path delineated by the philosophy of Hegel, and Italians now had to creatively adapt this path to suit their own intellectual past and local philosophical tradition.
Hegel and Italian Political Thought uncovers a forgotten meaning of philosophical ideas by investigating readings of Hegel’s thought in Italy during the nineteenth century: ideas have political power when they are elaborated in connection with the historical context. By looking at the nineteenth-century Italian reception of Hegel, a practical dimension of ideas emerges, and this with a twofold meaning. First of all, Hegel’s ideas are turned into political practices by those Italians who had participated in the 1848 revolution, who then would lead the new Italian government after unification, between 1861 and 1876, and who finally would continue to play a central role in Italian political life until the end of the century. Secondly, the practical dimension of ideas refers to the peculiarities of Italian Hegelianism, which serve to distinguish it from the broader European reception of Hegel: it insisted on the historical and political dimension of Hegel’s idealism, merging Giambattista Vico’s understanding of history with Hegel’s philosophy of history; it reformed Hegel’s dialectic by providing a phenomenological reading of the categories of the Science of Logic; it engaged with the outcomes of positivism and the natural sciences by presenting a critical Hegelianism closer to realism than to idealism, to reality than to metaphysics, to history than to logic, to life than to science, to practice than to ideas. Italian Hegelianism presents itself as a continuous attempt to elaborate a reading of Hegel that highlights the union between philosophy and history, and the synthesis of idea and fact, centring Hegelianism on the historical reality of life, without however losing sight of the metaphysical and logical dimension of the German philosopher’s thought.
This book rethinks Italian political thought by taking into consideration the specific location of Italy in the imaginary map delineated by nineteenth-century Italian Hegelians in their conversation with their northern European critics and counterparts. It therefore criticises the conventional hierarchies in the study of Italian political thought, interrogating intellectual relationships within Italy as well as between Italy and the wider world. Challenging notions of centre and periphery, this book investigates the long process of transition whereby Italy ceased to be a cluster of dominated and isolated states and became a single nation-state. It does so by exploring the influence of Hegelian thought in shaping a new political vocabulary, in large part through the contribution of the Italian Hegelians. It is the story of a generation of intellectuals born at the start of the century, the majority of them from Southern Italy, who experienced the collapse of the Kingdom of Two Sicilies and the dissolution of the common cultural and political space of Southern Italy, and who helped to forge modern Italian political thought.
By uncovering this neglected intellectual inheritance, the book recovers a world characterised by multiple cultural, intellectual, and political affiliations that have since been obscured by the conventional narrative of the formation of nation-states. It thus rethinks the origins of Italian nationalism and of the Italian state, highlighting the intellectual connections between Germany, the Habsburg Empire, Switzerland, and France, and re-establishing the lost link between the changing geopolitical contexts of western and northern Europe and the Mediterranean. It shows how nations emerged from an intermingling, rather than a clash, of ideas concerning the State and liberalism, modernity and religion, history and civilization, revolution, and conservatism, South and North. Through the story of this generation of Hegelians, who began to engage with Hegel’s philosophy shortly after his death, in 1832, and continued to grapple with it until the end of the century, this work contributes to the most recent scholarly debates on Hegel and Italian Hegelianism, to the broader field of the history of political thought, as well as to the research on nineteenth-century Italian political thought.
I.1 Hegel and Italian Hegelianism
Following the classical works of the 1970s, recent years have witnessed a return to Hegel studies, and from a survey of the latest publications it seems clear that the phenomenon is currently at its peak.Footnote 4 This so-called third wave of Anglophone scholarship on Hegel has largely developed as a result of readings divided over the question of whether Hegel’s idealism should be considered as metaphysical or non-metaphysical,Footnote 5 reopening a dialogue between different fields and tendencies in philosophy while paying a particular attention to the German nineteenth-century context,Footnote 6 Hegel’s mature thought and his enduring influenceFootnote 7 as well as its relationship with German Idealism.Footnote 8 The insights contained in the various fairly recent reconstructions of Hegel’s philosophy, mostly brought about by German and American philosophers, have barely been taken up by historians or political theorists.Footnote 9 Consequently, research since the 1970s on Hegel’s moral and political ideas has tended to isolate this subject matter from his speculative concerns. In this vein, scholars have opted to examine Hegel’s ethics and politics without reference to his metaphysics.Footnote 10 This approach was initiated by Benedetto Croce (1866–1952) when attempting to distinguish what was ‘living’ from what was ‘dead’ in Hegel’s philosophy, yet the problem with this viewpoint is that it makes it difficult to integrate the disparate elements of his project.Footnote 11 Not only does it render the Logic irrelevant to his social thought, but it also makes it hard to explain the role of both the Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) and the Lectures on the Philosophy of History (1822, 1828, 1830). In addition, this strategy presupposes that ethics and metaphysics have a distinct and determinate status in speculative philosophy, and it implicitly disregards the encyclopedic ambition of the Hegelian system. At the same time, despite their major advances in scholarship, philosophers have for the most part opted not to analyse Hegel’s social, economic, and constitutional ideas. In fact, few political theorists today, and scarcely any historians, devote themselves to the study of Hegel’s thought. Admittedly, there have been a number of exceptions, such as Duncan Forbes, Douglas Moggach, and Warren Breckman, or indeed Frederick Beiser, who has combined a commitment to the history of philosophy with an interest in Hegel. Only very recently have historians of political thought, such as Richard Bourke and Elias Buchetmann, engaged with Hegel’s philosophy, insisting on a historical and contextual understanding of Hegel’s political thought and stimulating a renewal of Hegel scholarship within the field of political thought, which has in turn prompted a reconsideration of the Hegelian tradition of political philosophy.Footnote 12
Notwithstanding the intellectual significance of this revival, these works have shown little interest in important aspects of Hegel’s reception, which in their own right are crucial for recent developments in intellectual history and the history of political thought. While participants in the recent debate pay due attention to the study of the Young Hegelians and British Idealism, as well as to the American, German, and French receptions of Hegel, the Italian reception has been almost wholly neglected.Footnote 13 This is despite the relevance of Hegel both for Italian political developments and for the broader transnational landscape of Italian idealism, associated mainly with Benedetto Croce (1866–1952) and Giovanni Gentile (1875–1944), figures who greatly enriched the European understanding of Hegel’s philosophy and played a central role in the dissemination of Hegelian thought. There are a few exceptions to this general trend, such as Bruce Haddock and James Wakefield’s volume, which endeavours to rethink Gentile’s thought beyond the classical readings of his work as ‘Fascist philosophy’.Footnote 14 With the focus on differences between Croce and Gentile’s philosophies, David Roberts’s work for its part addresses wider problems surrounding politics and liberalism.Footnote 15 He also denounces the marginalisation of modern Italian political thought, relegated from the wider European canon to the field of Italian Studies, where Italy is accorded the status of a periphery that passively received the discoveries and novelties of German, French, and British political thought. Relatively few works have resisted this general trend towards marginalisation, emphasising instead the originality and the relevance of Hegel’s Italian reception within a broader range of European political thinkers and highlighting the transnational dimension of Italian political thought and its peculiarities.Footnote 16
Considering the intellectual prominence of Giovanni Gentile and Benedetto Croce in Italy and their central role in bringing to light the majority of books, letters, and manuscripts by the nineteenth-century Italian Hegelians, it does not come as a surprise that, within Italian scholarship, the understanding of the phenomenon of Hegel’s reception in nineteenth-century Italy has been dominated by their two different interpretations, left unchallenged for almost fifty years. While Gentile had traced a direct line between nineteenth-century Italian Hegelianism and his own Actualism, Croce tried to trace the thread of the Italian liberal tradition from the Neapolitan Revolution of 1799 to the Italian Risorgimento. The historiographical debate was reopened in the 1950s and the 1960s by a group of Marxist scholars who criticised both approaches. Thanks to the publication of the correspondence between Bertrando Spaventa and his pupil, the Marxist Antonio Labriola, intellectuals such as Palmiro Togliatti and Giuseppe Berti, as well as Giuseppe Vacca and Domenico Losurdo later on, tried to identify a line of development of Italian historicism from Spaventa and Labriola to the work of Antonio Gramsci.Footnote 17
The very diverse attempts to reconstruct a unitary vision of the development of Hegelianism in Italian political thought were contested by a number of different scholars in the 1980s. In this period, the focus on the historical context of nineteenth-century Italy and the political experience of the Risorgimento was enhanced by the availability of new archival sources that were published in the course of the following decades (correspondence, lectures, manuscripts, etc.), offering a fruitful ground for those seeking to avoid ideological approaches and univocal interpretations.Footnote 18 Some critics have concentrated on the ethical and political aspects of Italian HegelianismFootnote 19, while others have highlighted the contribution made to the theoretical and philosophical debate or to the understanding of the general historical context.Footnote 20
In very recent years, German and Italian scholarship has witnessed a revival of interest in Hegel’s reception in Italy in the nineteenth century, partly on account of the bicentenary of the birth of both its most prominent figures, Bertrando Spaventa (1817–1883) and Francesco De Sanctis (1817–1883).Footnote 21 Although this revival has fostered a renewed engagement with the recent debate in the history of philosophy and the history of literature, it remains within the categories of interpretation developed during the 1980s and very closely related therefore to internal German and Italian academic debates and by the same token at odds with the most recent – and, indeed, highly fruitful – tendency in intellectual history, which considers Italy in the broader transnational and global context.Footnote 22
This book on the contrary engages with the most recent debates in intellectual history and with the international scholarship on Italian political thought, combining it with new archival sources that offer fresh perspectives on the topic. Fredrick Beiser has summarised the dilemma facing scholars of Hegel and of Hegel’s reception in terms of a choice between a metaphysical or non-metaphysical understanding of the German philosopher, insisting that accurate historical research has to confront Hegel with his metaphysical concerns, which are ‘alien to the spirit of contemporary philosophical culture, which mistrusts metaphysics’.Footnote 23 However, a non-metaphysical understanding of Hegel would be less historically accurate, as it would appear more as ‘a construction of our contemporary interests than the real historical school’.Footnote 24 It is at this juncture that historians, concerned with past issues for their own sake, move away from political theorists and political philosophers, preoccupied as they are with contemporary controversies. There is indeed at this point an opportunity for historians of political thought to close the gap, the study of nineteenth-century Italian Hegelianism offering a fresh perspective on this problem.
Italian Hegelians investigated and discussed both the metaphysical and the non-metaphysical Hegel, moving confidently from the most difficult pages of the Science of Logic to the Phenomenology of Spirit, which Silvio Spaventa called ‘the book with the seven seals’ (Il libro dai sette sigilli): as intellectual historians, they explored Hegel’s texts and analysed his ideas in depth, while reconstructing his context and German intellectual debates; as philosophers, they selected and reshaped those ideas within Hegel’s philosophy that answered to their contemporary political concerns; as politicians, they tried to enhance their political practice, deriving inspiration from their reformulation of Hegelian ideas. While accurately reconstructing the Italian context and this network of intellectuals, the present book reflects on the prominent place that philosophy assumed in nineteenth-century political debates and the key role that ideas played in the political arena.
I.2 The History of Political Thought
Rather than reading political statements as facts, as was customary in most of the idealist accounts of Italy’s national resurgence, which established a teleological straitjacket of idealised standard accounts of national history, more recent, critical approaches tend to read them as speech acts within a complex framework of contextual references, where the representation of social and political realities had aimed to achieve specific political outcomes.Footnote 25 Many of these contextual references are embedded in international and sometimes global debates, which themselves require careful analysis, such as a comparison of the relationship between the history of political thought and the political cultures of the different countries within which it has been practised.Footnote 26 Despite a long and erudite tradition in Italy of studying these ideas as ‘storia delle dottrine politiche’ (history of political thought), a more analytical and theoretically informed approach based on methodological engagement with, for instance, Anglo-American studies of political theory, the so-called Cambridge school, or a Koselleckian history of concepts has emerged only relatively recently.Footnote 27 Since then, the history of Italian political thought has rapidly developed into a vibrant field of research.Footnote 28
This book’s approach to Italian political thought actively engages with recent broader debates in the history of political thought, while also entering into a dialogue with the scholarship on the intellectual history of the Mediterranean. It does so by enlarging the range of sources usually deployed by intellectual historians, following the invitation that histories of ideas should encompass a broader understanding of context by reconstructing ‘the complete range of the inherited symbols and representations that constitute the subjectivity of an age’, both through immersion in the archives and by grappling with philosophical, legal, and political texts.Footnote 29 This research relates to the trends in the field that integrate the analysis of philosophical and political texts with biographical information;Footnote 30 explore the circulation of books and translation of classical texts;Footnote 31 and reconstruct national and international networks of intellectuals by focussing on correspondence, exile, as well as on relevant periodicals and journals.Footnote 32 Combining these different approaches to the field, this book reveals unexpected paths to the identification of one of the bodies of political thought, in which ideas are closely connected to the practical experiences of authors, the circulation of intellectual flows, and the access variously granted to texts.
If, as Pocock affirmed, a body of political thought can only be said to exist when a context ‘lasts long enough to give discourse some command over itself’, and if conversations within and between cultures must be stable and durable in order to produce significant bodies of political thought, then the Italian Hegelians had indeed represented a body of political thought in modern Italy.Footnote 33 But how is it that this body of nineteenth-century political thought did not enter the main surveys in the field when by contrast Niccolo Machiavelli or Antonio Gramsci loom so large? There are hidden intellectual hierarchies that structure and constrain the field: very recent research in the history of political thought, in particular on the twentieth century, is indeed now presenting alternative bodies of political thought, very influential in their own contexts. These works explore the connections between theory and political practice by highlighting the ‘power of political ideas’, such as Shruti Kapila’s recent monograph on modern Indian political thought, as well as collective efforts to reconstruct a ‘democratic canon’, such as the edited volume on African-American political thought by Melvin Rogers and Jack Turner.Footnote 34 The present book assumes the social and political influence of ideas ‘since people’s behaviour is deeply influenced by what they think, and especially by what they believe firmly’.Footnote 35
These recent studies are the result of the efforts that have shaped the field in the last few decades in order to present a multiplicity of bodies of political thought, paying attention to a broader field of intellectual production.Footnote 36 The different sub-fields have contributed greatly to this approach. Those engaged in writing the history of international and legal political thought have thus attempted to highlight the contested, fruitful, and shifting nature of classical works. The reshaping of classical authors by a wide range of actors, who might have different intentions, is often the site of negotiation of ideas. This book is interested in the way Hegel had been reinvented by nineteenth-century Italian thinkers, ‘emphasising the personal, institutional, social, and political dynamics that underpinned the posthumous trajectory’ of Hegel’s philosophy ‘and what these dynamics tell us about their goals, priorities, and world views’.Footnote 37 This different context might also offer a reading of the author that is quite far from their original intentions. The sub-field of comparative political thought would appear to have been moving in a similar direction. Indeed, some of its practitioners have gone so far as to highlight the potential theoretical (not historical) value of creative misreadings of thinkers from the past.Footnote 38
A very interesting criticism of the established bodies of political thought has emerged in particular from the studies on women’s intellectual production, an interest that has crossed the diverse sub-fields, proposing exciting studies in international political thought, in intellectual history, as well as in political theory.Footnote 39 These works uncover stories of female political thinkers and philosophers who have contributed to the development of political thought in traditional or less traditional ways, aiming at presenting alternative views of political thought. This book recovers the work of the female philosopher Marianna Bacinetti, better known by her married name of Marianna Florenzi Waddington, who greatly contributed to the history of Italian Hegelianism.
Exciting new works on Italian political thought highlight how asymmetries in relations of power, which often produced revolutions, diasporas, or exiles, have affected the identification of bodies of political thought and recast relationships between centre and peripheries.Footnote 40 Most of these works appeared within the wider field of the intellectual history of the modern Mediterranean.Footnote 41 Studies in modern intellectual history of the Mediterranean have reconstructed the entanglement of interactions and shared experiences in the Mediterranean in the long nineteenth century, highlighting the capacity of local authors, scholars, and intellectuals to use foreign ideas for their own purposes and shedding new light on the creative amalgamation with local cultural and political traditions.Footnote 42 Moreover, they have investigated how the peoples of Southern Europe and the Ottoman Empire, which all experienced diverse forms of subordination to northern ‘great powers’, had to struggle with broader changes in ideas about states while striving to maintain their political and cultural autonomy.Footnote 43 Nineteenth-century Italian political thought is no exception.
The renewed interest in modern Italian political thought within the field of intellectual history of the Mediterranean has produced very interesting works as well as new challenges to the identification of alternative bodies of political thought. New research that investigates Italian political thought within the scholarship on Mediterranean history has also insisted on the ‘connectivity’, a dimension embodied in the biographies of intellectuals who travelled across the Mediterranean space, often following revolutionary moments, in the networks they created and in the ideas they exchanged.Footnote 44
The reconstruction of network-based liberalism at a specific moment, such as the 1820s or 1848 revolutions, and the mapping of ramifying connections among liberals across Europe and the World (especially Latin America or the Indian Ocean) help little in identifying an alternative body of political thought. However, liberals from Southern Europe were in a particular predicament (compared, for example, to liberals in Britain): they endured various moments of political oppression that forced them into exile, and there was a constant flux of streams of exiles.Footnote 45 These moments of exile were certainly moments of reflection, writing, and exchange of ideas with the local contexts hosting them, but then these people returned to their own countries and most of them subsequently occupied key roles in governments and parliaments. The peculiarity of these moments of ‘pause’ (and sometimes fight) as well as moments of real politics becomes even more interesting if tracked across a longer timespan, which allows us to recognise the interactions between ideas and political practices, identifying then a particular body of political thought, one that was especially relevant in modern Italy.
Intellectual historian working on the Mediterranean invite us also to consider more seriously the role of space in the history of political thought. Intellectual history for a long time resisted a reflection on space. However, more recently, scholars have suggested that space be considered a key element in the understanding of intellectual history, even going so far as to define space as ‘the final frontier for intellectual history’.Footnote 46 If we then consider space not as a mere context but as ‘a mode of intellectual production deserving of interpretation in its own right’, taking it seriously and, therefore, reading ‘deliberately against the grain’,Footnote 47 we have to agree with Antonio Gramsci when in his Prison Notebooks he notes that North, South, East, and West, although ‘arbitrary and conventional [historical] constructions’, more or less explicitly ‘expressed (and still express) a value-judgement’ with very real intellectual and political consequences.Footnote 48 Engaging with the history of political thought by including the specificities of spaces and entanglements that characterised the Mediterranean region in modern times means that we consider also these ‘value-judgements’ that provide a new understanding of Italian political thought. This book investigates the history of Italian political thought also by reflecting on the wider spatial and intellectual context of the Mediterranean in the nineteenth century and its place in the intellectual and political hierarchies at the time. It explores how engagement with a classical and influential thinker such as Hegel from the margins of its geo-philosophical borders (nineteenth-century Italy) has produced an alternative body of political thought, which was equally influential in its own context. Rather than a passive reception of ideas thought elsewhere, nineteenth-century Italian Hegelianism represents a creative amalgamation of different intellectual flows, local and international, offering an original and interesting reading of Hegel. Rethinking Italian political thought through the lens of Hegel’s ‘presence’ in Italy means also to recenter the Peninsula in modern historical time. As Franco Cassano argued:
For a long time the south has been seen like an error, a negation, or a delay. To reverse this picture, the first thing that is required is to give back to the south the ancient dignity of being a subject of thought, rather than being thought of from the standpoint of others. In a similar manner, the Mediterranean has long been regarded as a sea of the past. It is in fact a central place of contemporary history – a place in which the north and the west meet the east and the south of the world.Footnote 49
Re-establishing the dignity of subjects of thought for the Italians and recovering the ‘thread of their philosophical tradition’ in order to develop the self-consciousness of the Italian nation were indeed the main aims of the Italian Hegelians, who in the first instance engaged with Hegel’s philosophy of history as a history of liberation from intellectual and political oppression.
I.3 Italian Political Thought and the Risorgimento
Since the first translation of one of Hegel’s works into Italian, the Philosophy of History (Filosofia della storia) published in 1840 and translated by Giambattista Passerini (1793–1864) during his exile in Switzerland, Hegel was presented to Italian readers almost as a historian, whose philosophy of history, due to the certainty of future political freedom, seemed directly relevant to the revolutionary tremors leading to 1848, at the height of which Antonio Turchiarulo translated Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (Filosofia del diritto). In his introduction, Turchiarulo highlighted the relevance of Hegel’s political thought for Italy’s national emancipation, describing it as a path to political freedom and civilisation.
What the first Italian Hegelians found so attractive in Hegel’s philosophy of history was both the notion of freedom as the liberation of humanity through the struggle of Spirit in its historical existence and the ideas of progress and liberation addressed to all nations. At this early stage, Italian Hegelianism was open to receiving the revolutionary potential of Hegel’s philosophy. Against Hegel’s own express warning, the dialectical philosophy of history now helped those studying it to look into the future, confirming the promise of a new age to come. Responding to Hegel’s call for liberation, Italy would once again be part of European culture – as it had been during the Renaissance.Footnote 50
While the political implications of Hegel’s thought seemed obvious, there were important differences in its reception between the North and the South of the peninsula. The diffusion of Hegel’s thought in northern Italy before 1848 was not based on direct knowledge of Hegel’s original texts in German but on their mediation through Victor Cousin’s French school of Eclecticism, which itself had followers in the South of the peninsula, including Stanislao Gatti (1820–1870) and Stefano Cusani (1815–1846). This book begins in 1832, when the first work on Hegel appeared in Italian, written by Giandomenico Romagnosi (1761–1835) in the Florentine journal Antologia, with the title Alcuni pensieri sopra un’ultra-metafisica filosofia della storia (Some Thoughts on an Ultra-Metaphysical Philosophy of History), commenting very critically on Hegel’s Philosophy of History, his account being based on Eugène Lerminier’s (1803–1857) exposition of Hegel’s philosophy in his Introduction générale à l’histoire du droit (General Introduction to the History of Right, 1829).Footnote 51 It was in the South, however, that Hegelianism assumed the role of a proper philosophical movement, commonly referred to as Neapolitan Hegelianism, which over the years also came to assume an important role on the national stage.
It was at the Neapolitan school of the Kantian Ottavio Colecchi (1773–1847), who had studied in Königsberg, that the group of liberals subsequently at the heart of Italian Hegelianism, gained access to German texts in the original language and became familiar with the language of German idealism and the scholarly debates in Germany. As a more systematic intellectual current, Neapolitan Hegelianism lasted for approximately forty years, from 1841, when Stanislao Gatti and Stefano Cusani founded the periodical Il Museo, up to the beginning of the 1880s, when its main exponents died. In the last two decades of the nineteenth century, that tradition was reshaped and reinterpreted by a number of different Italian intellectuals, and in particular it was adapted by Antonio Labriola (1843–1904) to the new intellectual challenges posed by the then current reflections on socialism. This book ends with Labriola’s re-elaboration of this tradition in his ‘philosophy of praxis’, presented in a series of three Marxist essays appearing between 1895 and 1898 with the title Saggi intorno alla concezione materialistica della storia (Essays on the Materialistic Conception of History) and in his fourth and last essay Da un secolo all’altro (From One century to the Next), written between 1897 and 1903 and published posthumously by his young friend Benedetto Croce.
The protagonists of Neapolitan Hegelianism at the beginning of the movement were for the most part young scholars who, while fighting for the national cause, endeavoured to read, translate, and interpret Hegel’s philosophy in direct relation to their political concerns. Before 1848, they had largely worked as a clandestine group, hiding from the Bourbon police. After the revolution of 1848 and its subsequent repression, its advocates continued their studies in prison or in exile, mostly in Piedmont, Switzerland, or France. It was only after Italy’s political unification in 1861 – when De Sanctis became Minister of Public Education, Silvio Spaventa was appointed vice secretary of Internal Affairs, and Bertrando Spaventa was elected a deputy to the national Parliament – that Neapolitan Hegelianism became officially part of Italy’s national canon of political thought. It was largely due to Labriola, who as a pupil of Bertrando Spaventa was closely connected to the Neapolitan Hegelians, and his vigorous resistance to materialism that towards the turn of the century a younger generation of thinkers developed a new interest in Hegel’s philosophy. In the case of Benedetto Croce and Giovanni Gentile, Labriola’s own anti-materialist Marxism came to form the basis for their engagement with Hegel’s thought, in Croce’s case assuming the guise of a new historicism and in Gentile’s case that of a neo-idealism.
From the perspective of a Hegel scholar, much of the Italian reading of Hegel might seem a distortion of the German philosopher’s thought. Most of the debates in which Italians placed their understanding of Hegel were fundamentally different from the German context of political thought at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The Neapolitan Hegelians’ quests and needs were closely related to the political context of the Risorgimento, with the result that Hegel’s philosophy of history was drawn closer to the anti-metaphysical overtones of Vichian historicism. Within this context, Hegel’s understanding of the Protestant Reformation as the key event in the making of the modern world is deprived of its theological element and turned into the earthly and philosophical experience of the Renaissance. Hegel’s ideas regarding civil society were reshaped beyond economic and corporative relations to become the embodiment of society’s cultural dimension. Hegel’s marginalisation of the role of the nation in favour of that of the State was overturned by adopting a new concept of ‘nationality’, which included a cultural (though not an ethnic) dimension as the basis of the rule of law. Hegel’s ‘Dialectic’ and his Logic were reinterpreted from the perspective of the Phenomenology of Spirit. Italian Hegelians redefined Hegel’s concept of parties in terms of electoral organisations affecting the relationship between the State and civil society. Therefore, understanding Italian Hegelianism implies a readiness to hear Hegel’s philosophy in a different voice. This entails a willingness to consider the amalgamation of Hegelian thought with Italy’s own fruitful intellectual ground, including the legacy of Vico’s Scienza Nuova and the rediscovery of Giordano Bruno and Tommaso Campanella’s philosophy.
Beyond the study of particular intellectual currents, the importance of Italy’s political context is one of the present book’s main concerns. As Eugenio Garin asserted, Hegel’s Italian reception was never a matter of purely academic debate or of ‘scientific neutrality’. Instead, Hegelianism has always constituted a central aspect of Italy’s political culture, where Hegel’s philosophy was constantly rethought and reshaped according to different moments of the nation’s political development.Footnote 52 As Norberto Bobbio noted, in Italian political history ‘all roads lead to Hegel, or, rather, all roads begin from Hegel’.Footnote 53 On a similar note, Sergio Landucci has argued that, in Italy, Hegelianism always represented an ‘element of the nation’s civil life’, a ‘civil force’ in support of national unification.Footnote 54 Therefore, unlike certain strands of interpretation elsewhere in Europe, in Italy Hegel retained a revolutionary potential. Thus, by looking at Italian political thought through the lens of Hegel’s ‘presence’ in Italy, this book not only fills a gap in philosophical scholarship but also sheds new light on Italian political thought.
The focus on Italian Hegelianism exemplifies an approach to the history of political thought that accentuates different modes of reception and the amalgamation of ideas into new intellectual contexts. It also helps to place the study of Italian Hegelianism within a wider context of recent historiographical approaches to Risorgimento political thought. Italian engagement with Hegel was a direct response to Italians’ own experiences of a dramatic change in the semantics of historical time since the end of the Seven Years’ War, followed shortly after by the American and French Revolutions. Due to its transnational perspective, the interest in Italian Hegelianism shares important ground with other fields of modern Italian history that over the last few decades have examined, for instance, the impact of European romanticism on Italy’s cultural and intellectual developmentFootnote 55 or the role of international experiences in shaping ideas in the Italian peninsula.Footnote 56
A central purpose of this book is to understand this shift from the intellectual reconstruction of the Italian national narratives during the Risorgimento to the political movement leading to Italian unification. The ‘nation’, is a continuous process of historical and cultural reconstruction and political negotiation that was far from being a straightforward or self-evident entity. The prevailing understanding of the idea of nation during the Risorgimento is linked to the debate on ‘national character’, a term that, as highlighted by Georgios Varouxakis, was often used by nineteenth-century European historians as an ‘explanatory category’.Footnote 57 Emphasising the Risorgimento’s many different political voices means highlighting Italy’s intellectual diversity during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries but also its close connection with wider European thought and with multiple political experiences.
The term ‘regeneration’ had been most current during the ‘revolutionary triennium’ (1796–1799) in Italy, when the influence of French republicanism was at its height. As Lucien Jaume has recently pointed out, the discourse on the French Revolution continually refers to the principle of regeneration (régénération).Footnote 58 Scrutiny of French dictionaries suggests that during the Enlightenment and, indeed, up until the French Revolution, the term ‘régénération’ was used only with a religious meaning and was not deployed in the political arena. After 1789, this term passed from the religious domain, to which it had previously been restricted, to the political, moral, and social domains.Footnote 59 The myth of the regeneration of the nation is indeed also connected with the widespread attempt among nineteenth-century historians to reconstruct the various ‘national characters’, related to the diverse narratives concerning the origins of the nation. The political culture of the national movement in the first half of the nineteenth century in Italy was far from uniform, and the different definitions offered of the Italian national character were connected to the diverse interpretations of the origins of the nation – such as the debate on the antiquity of the Italian nation, or the myth of the Catholic roots of Italian culture, as well as the narrative tracing the origins of the Italian nation back to the ‘communal age of freedom’ and the early medieval comuni.Footnote 60 The idea of the regeneration of the nation implies therefore the return to a human essence, forgotten or suppressed, and this is possible only through a revolution. Revolution, in short, offers the promise of emancipation, which has shifted from the religious to the political sphere, involving as it does what Jaume calls a transfert de religiosité(s).Footnote 61 This definition highlights the inner, subjective tensions within the general aspiration towards regeneration, entailing something other than the merely external dimension of ceremonies and symbols related to the new cults. In Italian, the two terms ‘regeneration’ (rigenerazione) and ‘resurgence’ (risorgimento) coexisted during the first half of the nineteenth century, while in its latter half the word ‘Risorgimento’ took precedence.Footnote 62
During the nineteenth century, Italian political language underwent a radical transformation: while the term Risorgimento had generally indicated a specific period of modern history (approximately from the fourteenth to the sixteenth centuries), by the end of the century that term began to be identified with the Italian struggles for national emancipation.Footnote 63 At the same time, the word Renaissance began to be used to indicate the period of early modern history between the fourteenth and the sixteenth centuries, also identified with the birth of ‘Modernity’. This change in the language represents a shift from an interpretation that highlights the religious and moral dimensions of the principle of Italian modernity to one that stresses its historical characteristics. Such a shift from an ethical-political meaning to a historiographical one consists of an interpretative transformation of the origins of modern national culture: initially the Renaissance was considered a political and moral model, to emulate or to condemn, but it then assumed the role of a historiographical category.
That transformation in the language represents a change of ideas or rather, in this case, of the way the intellectual and political leaders of the Risorgimento interpreted the failed religious and moral reformation in Italy of the early modern period. While recent scholarship has highlighted how the term Risorgimento came to mark a ‘symbolic repositioning from the religious to the political’ dimension of the term, it was still confused with the Renaissance as then understood.Footnote 64 Linguistic studies have traced a semantic history of the two terms, Risorgimento and Rinascimento, illustrating how political and ideological factors conditioned their use and the meanings they carried.Footnote 65 This book investigates this change in the political language, proving that it was also a consequence of a deeper study and understanding of the Renaissance as a historical period and its main protagonists, such as Giordano Bruno, Tommaso Campanella, or Niccolo’ Machiavelli, promoted by the Italian Hegelians.
The idea of the need for a regeneration (or resurgence) of the moral and intellectual life of Italians was connected to the widespread assumption among European and Italian intellectuals that the Italian character suffered from a backwardness, laziness, and indolence.Footnote 66 In order to assume a new role as a modern nation, the Italians needed first, or so it was supposed, a moral and intellectual revolution: the incessant references to the regeneration of the nation in Italian political discourse, from the republicans to the most conservative political groups, demonstrate a process of self-othering among the national elites. As Lucy Riall has emphasised: ‘nationalism in Italy was born from a sense of weakness: of resistance to Napoleon’s conquests; of inferiority towards Italy’s neighbours, and of loss relative to a glorious past …. Even nationalism’s appeal in Italy comes from a feeling of failure, offering as it does the dream of regeneration (risorgimento), against which the squalid state of the present-day nation is judged and found lacking’.Footnote 67 Historians, philosophers, and publicists played a fundamental role in readapting and reshaping collective memories, as well as in creating a national narrative.Footnote 68 This book contributes to the understanding of these narratives by engaging with the scholarly debates regarding the role of the Italian South in the Risorgimento.
The process of Italian unification has often been portrayed in the historiography as a process of royal conquest, whereby its principal architect, Cavour, together with the King Vittorio Emanuele, imposed Piedmontese rule on the rest of the Peninsula. Moreover, the representation of Southern Italy in many Northern Italian accounts as a backward and uncivilised land has led historians in recent years to portray the South through the ‘logic of coloniality’.Footnote 69 Studies by Jane Schneider, John Dickie, Nelson Moe, and Silvana Patriarca have thus explored the widespread proliferation of stereotypes representing Southern Italy in the aftermath of unification, in the process often going beyond the analysis of the so-called Southern Question – which investigates instead the economic and political differences between the North and the South of the Peninsula.Footnote 70
Very recently, scholars such as Roberto Dainotto, Luigi Carmine Cazzato, and Claudio Fogu have considered the process of Italian nation-building through the lens of postcolonial critical studies, applying the logic of Edward Said’s Orientalism to Southern Europe, and Southern Italy, and so proposing a discursive construction of the ‘Souths’ of Europe dubbed ‘Meridionism’.Footnote 71 Although the key role of Piedmont in the unification process is beyond dispute, these approaches tend to overshadow local and popular participation, in particular within the Kingdom of Two Sicilies, as well as the work of Southern Italian political representatives in the new Parliament.
This book explores the contribution of the political thought and political practices of Italian Hegelians, most of whom were from the South, to the building of the new Italian State. Many of them had first served the Kingdom of Italy in the Southern provinces during the delicate transition period, then in the central government and parliament in the early years of state-building, between 1861 and the 1880s, serving as representatives in both of the main parties, the Historical Right (Destra Storica), and the Historical Left (Sinistra Storica). They reshaped the Hegelian theory of the State to serve the new Italian political context and contributed to the understanding and designing of the new Italian State. In the history of Italian Hegelianism, Naples and the South played a particularly prominent role. This work will therefore present a critique of conventional hierarchies in the study of Risorgimento political thought.
Within the history of Italian Hegelianism, the pre-eminent role assumed by Naples and the South was never quite matched by North Italian interest in the German philosopher. This discrepancy constitutes the basis for a key argument in this book and addresses a central issue of historiographical debates on modern Italy, namely, the relationship between North and South and the South’s role in Italy’s relationship to the wider world. In this context, it is important to note that the stereotyping of the Italian South as backward and different from the North emerged early in the history of Risorgimento political thought. Since the late eighteenth century, various thinkers associated with the Neapolitan Enlightenment, Antonio Genovesi and Gaetano Filangieri among them, had identified a number of social and cultural problems that allegedly were specific to the Italian South and made it difficult to reform the Kingdom of Naples. Many of their arguments were then reiterated by the protagonists of the Neapolitan revolution of 1799, the men and women around Vincenzo CuocoFootnote 72, and subsequently by the Napoleonic administration in Naples.Footnote 73 After 1815, political thinkers from the North used this debate on the South to define what it was that made their own realms allegedly more progressive. Writing in the 1840s, Carlo Cattaneo argued that the South lacked most of the features his native Lombardy shared with Central and Northern Europe, due to its arbitrary and oppressive system of government. He describes an entirely foreign country, one whose culture contrasts dramatically with the cosmopolitan spirit that characterises the middle classes of Northern Europe.Footnote 74 Whereas Cattaneo, relying upon this analysis, and as a matter of principle, would for a long time question the rationale of politically unifying the Italian peninsula into a single nation-state, other political thinkers concluded that the North was under an obligation to lead the South into political modernity.
The study of Italian Hegelianism presents us with a very different image of the South. Taking account of its flourishing tradition of philosophical debate, it becomes obvious that the Italian South in no way represented an intellectual periphery of Europe – an argument that can easily be extended to the South’s role in the history of European art and music or in the history of science. There is a long tradition of Anglophone historiography from Patrick Chorley, Oil, Silk and Enlightenment. Economic Problems in XVIIIth-Century Naples to the works of John Robertson, such as The Case for the Enlightenment. Scotland and Naples, 1680–1760 and John Davis’ Naples and Napoleon. Southern Italy and the European Revolutions, 1780–1860, that has attempted to raise the profile of the Southern contribution to Italian intellectual history of the late eighteenth and the early nineteenth century.Footnote 75 The transnational orientation of its cultural and intellectual life bears witness to the centrality of its position within the Italian peninsula and within Europe. As a consequence, the South also assumes a particularly prominent role when the history of Italy’s political emancipation is placed in the context of larger transnational debates and of Italy’s multiple imperial connections.Footnote 76 Moreover, Italians were conscious of their own contribution to the ideas and the political institutions of the world’s most progressive nations.
As recent studies on the representations of the ‘margins’ of Europe, from Ireland to the Balkans, have indicated, these lands have undergone a process of Othering since the eighteenth century in connection with Europe’s attempts to define its identity and with the rise of nationalism.Footnote 77 This book aspires to rethink Italian political thought by focussing on how the creative amalgamation of Hegel’s ideas with Italian culture led to a rethinking of historical and political concepts that greatly influenced the intellectual history of modern Italy and, indeed, of Europe as a whole.
The narrative offered by Italian Hegelians was intended to shape the idea of a modern Italian State regenerated by the encounter of their own fruitful intellectual traditions with the most advanced European philosophy, namely the Hegelian. As clearly described by Axel Körner in his recent work America in Italy, the process of amalgamation is never simply a matter of passive reception but is rather a translation into a new context, a complex process that leads to results that often bear little similarity to the original.Footnote 78 Analysing Italian Hegelianism allows us to reject the idea that engagement with foreign ideas describes a process of passive learning, in the sense of adopting supposedly more advanced ideas from abroad; and the same applies to intellectual flows within the Italian peninsula. As Marta Petrusewicz has explained, North and South exist in a relationship of otherness, where self-perceptions of the North depend on the image of an Other in the South, which in turn is then internalised by Italians from all over the peninsula.Footnote 79 Such processes of internalisation are foundational of hegemonic relationships and teleological distortions, whereby the South supposedly needs the North in order to leave its position of self-imposed inferiority. Rather than accepting such intellectual hierarchies, this book tries to identify original acts of creative amalgamation. Each of the five chapters of this book analyses one of these acts of amalgamation.
In Chapter 1, ‘The Vico-Effect’, this research explores how, in different parts of the Peninsula, Hegel’s thought circulated in the guise of translations and commentaries from 1832 up to 1848. It then reconstructs the intellectual context of Naples and the Kingdom of Two Sicilies, paying particular attention to how the interpretation of the philosophy of Giambattista Vico (1668–1744), often viewed in relation to Victor Cousin’s (1792–1867) reading of the Neapolitan philosopher, was combined with the study first of the philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and then of G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831). Key figures in this process are Ottavio Colecchi, Stanislao Gatti, Stefano Cusani, and Francesco De Sanctis. Finally, it defines the context in which the school of Neapolitan Hegelianism arose, highlighting the novelty of the ‘principle of nationality’ as a product of this amalgamation. The elaboration in 1848 of the idea of ‘nationality’ characterising an organicist view of the law and the State, connected to the unitary aspirations and endeavours of the Risorgimento, would transform Neapolitan Hegelianism from a local tradition of thought into a national experience. By engaging with Hegel’s ideas, the Neapolitan intellectuals developed their political revolutionary practice in 1848. After the revolution, while in prison or exile, Italian Hegelians further refine the reflection on Italian philosophy in order to enhance that process of self-consciousness of the nation.
Chapter 2, ‘The Renaissance’, illustrates how Italian Hegelians, and in particular Marianna Florenzi Waddington and Bertrando Spaventa, between 1848 and the 1860s, contributed to the understanding of the philosophical tradition of the Italian Renaissance by rediscovering the works of Giordano Bruno. They traced a line of continuity between the Italian Renaissance and German Idealism by arguing that ‘the last disciple of Bruno was Hegel’. They challenged the myth of the Hegelian ‘Protestant Supremacy’, amalgamating the widespread criticism regarding Italian Catholicism, and presented an alternative path to ‘Modernity’ traced by the Italian philosophers of the Renaissance. Bruno insisted on the autonomy of conscience and the infinite value of human dignity by reformulating existing notions of moral and political liberty. They affirmed the peculiar bond between historiography, philosophy, and politics that characterised Italian culture during the nineteenth century.
This connection is also at the heart of Chapter 3, ‘The Risorgimento’, in which it is the key figure of Niccolo’ Machiavelli that allows Italian Hegelians, and in particular Francesco De Sanctis, Francesco Fiorentino, and Pasquale Villari, to challenge the idea of an Italian ‘missed Reformation’, recasting the Renaissance as ‘the Italian version of the Reformation’. The rediscovery of Machiavelli’s work is connected to the radical change that nineteenth-century Italian political language underwent regarding the nexus of Rinascimento–Risorgimento. This chapter demonstrates that the change in the language represents a shift from an interpretation that highlights the religious and moral dimensions of the principle of Italian modernity to one that stresses its historical characteristics.
It is in Chapter 4, ‘The Ethical State’, that the context of the Risorgimento is explored more closely while scrutinising Hegel’s political thought and comparing his texts with Italian Hegelians’ commentaries and interpretations of Hegel’s philosophy. It focuses in particular on Marianna Florenzi Waddington, Bertrando Spaventa, and Silvio Spaventa. It then examines how nineteenth-century interpretations of Hegel were rehearsed and redeployed by the main Italian scholars of Idealism in the twentieth century, Benedetto Croce and Giovanni Gentile.
Chapter 5, ‘Hegelians in Charge’, extends further the key argument of the book, exploring the contribution of the political thought and political practices of Italian Hegelians, to the building of the new Italian State. This chapter focuses in particular on Silvio Spaventa and Francesco De Sanctis and how they reshaped the Hegelian theory of the State to serve the new Italian political context and to contribute to the understanding and designing of the nascent Italian State. It investigates the laws they proposed, the Parliamentary speeches they delivered, and the political pamphlets they wrote, discussing contemporary political issues often addressed by having recourse to Hegel’s ideas reshaped to respond to the challenges presented by their own time. The chapter concludes by exploring the influence of Italian Hegelianism on Antonio Labriola’s ‘philosophy of praxis’, which is an original reading of Marxism and one that preserves some of the key traits of the Italian Hegelian reading of Hegel. Italian Hegelianism was shaped by a ‘practical’ understanding of Hegel’s philosophy, whereby it insisted on the historical, ethical, and political dimensions of Hegel’s metaphysics and attempted to realise Hegelian political ideas in the practice of political life. This critical approach would be passed on to the Italian Hegelians’ dearest pupil, Labriola, and would persist as a trait of Italian engagement with Marx’s political thought.
The Epilogue focuses on the influence and legacy of nineteenth-century Italian Hegelianism by investigating how Benedetto Croce, Giovanni Gentile, and Antonio Gramsci re-elaborated this tradition at the turn of the new century in order to develop their own philosophical systems, their interpretation of Hegel, Marx, and the relationship between politics and ethics, as well as their understanding of Italian history and of the role of intellectuals in the formation of the Italian state.
By presenting the story of this generation of intellectuals who engaged with Hegel’s philosophy while actively participating in Italian political life in the nineteenth century, this book contributes to the scholarly debates on Hegel and Italian Hegelianism, on the history of political thought and intellectual history, and on Italian political thought and the Risorgimento. It traces the development through the century of the political and philosophical ideas of a group of scholars and politicians who from the Southern periphery of Europe engaged with the philosophy of Hegel and raised them as subjects of thought. It offers a perspective on a time of radical political and intellectual transformation undergone by one of the most spectacular instances of nation- and state-building of nineteenth-century Europe by presenting one of the many bodies of political thought, certainly one of the most influential in modern Italy. It is in history that philosophy acquires its political relevance.