Hostname: page-component-69cd664f8f-84qt4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-12T16:55:25.109Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

VIRGIL AND THE RHESVS ATTRIBUTED TO EURIPIDES: AN UNNOTICED ALLUSION AT AENEID 1.25–7?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 March 2025

Basil L.P. Nelis*
Affiliation:
Leiden University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article argues that the Virgilian narrator’s account of Juno’s anger at the outcome of the Judgement of Paris at Aen. 1.25–7 contains an allusion, which seems to have gone unnoticed, to a prologue transmitted in some manuscripts of the Rhesus attributed to Euripides. It also discusses the problem of the origin of this prologue. Finally, it suggests some interpretative possibilities arising from recognition of the allusion.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

At Aen. 1.25–7, the Virgilian narrator describes Juno’s anger at the outcome of the Judgement of Paris:Footnote 1

necdum etiam causae irarum saeuique dolores

exciderant animo; manet alta mente repostum

iudicium Paridis spretaeque iniuria formae …

Nor yet had the causes of her anger and her cruel pain slipped out of her memory: the judgement of Paris, the injury of her scorned beauty, remains stored away deep inside her mind …

Scholars have observed that the Judgement of Paris is mentioned in Hom. Il. 24.25–30 (lines 29–30 were athetized by Aristarchus) and that it featured in the lost poem from the Epic Cycle entitled Cypria, seemingly towards the beginning (Arg., Procl. Chrest. 86–90 Severyns; fr. 4 Bernabé).Footnote 2 Virgil gives the story particular prominence in the opening of his own poem by listing it as one of the two main causes of Juno’s anger against the Trojans, the other being the rape of Ganymede (Aen. 1.8 causas, 1.25 causae).

In addition to these parallels in Homer and the Cypria, a further Greek text may be cited: a prologue to the Rhesus attributed to Euripides, which is spoken by Hera and in which she cites the Judgement of Paris as a reason to take revenge against the Trojans. This prologue is transmitted in an anonymous hypothesis of unknown date, Diggle’s hypothesis (b), contained in some of our manuscripts of the play.Footnote 3 The author of the hypothesis quotes eleven lines of a prologue which he reports could be found in some manuscripts (ἐν ἐνίοις δὲ τῶν ἀντιγράφων) and which he judges to be ‘banal’ and unworthy of Euripides (πϵζὸς πάνυ [sc. πρόλογος] καὶ οὐ πρέπων εὐριπίδῃ), suspecting them rather to have been interpolated by an actor (καὶ τάχα ἄν τινϵς τῶν ὑποκριτῶν διϵσκϵυακότϵς ϵἶϵν αὐτόν).Footnote 4 In this prologue, Hera enjoins Athena to avenge the slight that both of them suffered at the Judgement of Paris.Footnote 5 These are the lines of the prologue to which, I argue, Virgil is alluding (hypothesis (b), [Eur.] Rhes. 39–44 = Adesp. fr. *81.6–11 TrGF):

ἔμοι γὰρ οὐδέν ἐστιν ἄλγιον βάρος,

ἐξ οὗ γ’ ἔκρινϵ Κύπριν Ἀλέξανδρος θέαν

κάλλϵι προήκϵιν τῆς ἐμῆς ϵὐμορφίας

καὶ σῆς, Ἀθάνα, φιλτάτης ἐμοὶ θϵῶν,

ϵἰ μὴ κατασκαφϵῖσαν ὄψομαι πόλιν

Πριάμου, βίαι πρόρριζον ἐκτϵτριμμένην.

There is no more painful burden for me—ever since Alexander judged that the goddess Aphrodite surpassed my beauty and yours, Athena, dearest to me among the gods—than if I shall not see Priam’s city razed to the ground, with its foundations violently dug up.Footnote 6

It should first be considered how these lines fit into the context of the prologue and, assuming that this prologue was in fact written for the extant Rhesus (on this question, see below), how they might fit into the context of that play. The full prologue is not transmitted, but it is plausible that, in what followed, Hera and Athena plotted to thwart Rhesus’ attempt to join forces with the Trojans.Footnote 7 Athena achieves this at Rhes. 595–667, when she first persuades Odysseus and Diomedes not to return to the Greek camp immediately after slaying Dolon (595–621). Then, taking the form of Aphrodite, she allays Paris’ concerns that the Trojans are under attack and assures him that she, ‘Aphrodite’, remains mindful of the honour he paid her at the Judgement of Paris (642–67, especially 647–8). Athena’s trickery might thus be seen as the fulfilment of a plot to punish the Trojans outlined in the prologue by Hera and Athena, in which the Judgement is cited as an important motivation for the goddesses’ revenge.

Let us now consider the passage itself in more detail and how it might have influenced Virgil. The Judgement of Paris is a story which seems to have been particularly appealing to Euripides (Andr. 274–92, Hec. 629–56, Hel. 23–5, 676–8, IA 182–4, 573–89, 1283–314, Tro. 924–33, 970–82).Footnote 8 The language used in this Rhesus prologue, when compared with the other passages, looks fairly conventional: κριν- words and μορφ- words are especially common in Euripides’ versions and elsewhere, though in none of the passages just referred to is the emphasis placed specifically on Hera’s anger at the outcome of the Judgement.Footnote 9 A further sign of the conventionality of the language is the high number of allusions to fifth-century Athenian tragedy that have been noted in these lines, an observation that has been used in support of the theory that these lines are not by Euripides.Footnote 10 Where Virgil’s account of the Judgement of Paris is concerned, earlier adaptations into Latin of the episode that survive only in fragmentary condition—such as Ennius’ Alexander, a play seemingly related to Euripides’ Alexandros, in which Paris’ decision is already described as a iudicium (Inc. fr. 151.17–18 TrRF = Alexander 48–9 Jocelyn), and a hexameter poem entitled Cypria Ilias (frr. 1–2 Blänsdorf) attributed to a Naevius who is not the same man as Cn. Naevius, author of the Bellum Punicum—may also be relevant.Footnote 11

Some readers may prefer to believe that Virgil is not alluding to any specific version of the Judgement of Paris. It must also be admitted that the status of the Rhesus prologue is not unproblematic, given that it is transmitted only in one of the hypotheses to the play and not in the actual text. While there is no doubt whatsoever that Virgil knew and alluded elsewhere in the Aeneid to the Rhesus itself,Footnote 12 there is debate among scholars about whether this alternative prologue would have been known in Virgil’s time.

Let us address, therefore, the potential objections to the suggestion that at Aen. 1.25–7 Virgil is alluding to this prologue of the Rhesus attributed to Euripides. First, its provenance. The statement by the author of hypothesis (b) that the prologue in question was written by an actor is generally accepted as true.Footnote 13 The interpolation is believed to have occurred on the occasion of a reperformance of the play in the fourth or early third century b.c.e.:Footnote 14 in such contexts, prologues seem to have been particularly susceptible to interpolation by actors.Footnote 15 Much of the rest of the information provided by hypothesis (b) has, however, given rise to debate. For instance, it is unclear whether this prologue was composed for the genuine Rhesus of Euripides, listed in Aristotle’s Didascaliae as a genuine Euripidean play, or whether, assuming that the Rhesus that has come down to us is not by Euripides but by a later unknown imitator, this prologue was written for the extant inauthentic play.Footnote 16 It therefore cannot be proved with absolute certainty that the play for which this prologue was written is the same play as the one to which Virgil alludes elsewhere in the Aeneid (see footnote 12), although it is plausible that the prologue was indeed written for the extant Rhesus (see above). Furthermore, on the one hand, some scholars argue that this prologue was already known to, and cited by, the Peripatetic Dicaearchus (fl. c.320–300 b.c.e.).Footnote 17 Hypotheses on the plays of Euripides are ascribed to him and he is mentioned by the author of hypothesis (b) as the source for the quotation of the first line of another prologue to the Rhesus also preserved in this hypothesis (Eur. fr. 660a TrGF).Footnote 18 Other scholars, on the other hand, believe that our prologue was unknown to Dicaearchus and was quoted by a later source.Footnote 19 As stated above, it is not known who the author of the hypothesis was or when they were active, but those scholars who reject the idea that the source for the text of our prologue and for the negative judgement expressed about it is Dicaearchus generally hold that this information in fact probably rather derives, at least in part, from Aristophanes of Byzantium.Footnote 20 So our prologue could in theory have been quoted by Dicaearchus, by Aristophanes himself, or by a later grammarian or commentator. Some even go so far as to suggest that it may have been quoted by Arius Didymus, active during the reign of Augustus (c.65 b.c.e.–10 c.e.).Footnote 21

Two recent editors of the play, Liapis and Fries, however, argue that Aristophanes of Byzantium did not know our prologue. They do so on the grounds that, in the hypothesis explicitly assigned in our manuscripts to Aristophanes of Byzantium, Diggle’s hypothesis (c), Aristophanes writes that a chorus of Trojan guards performs the prologue to the play (ὁ χορὸς συνέστηκϵν ἐκ φυλάκων Τρωϊκῶν, οἳ καὶ προλογίζουσι, ‘the chorus is composed of Trojan guards, who also perform the prologue’, Ar. Byz. hypothesis (c), [Eur.] Rhes. 52–3).Footnote 22 On their account, this statement implies that Aristophanes did not know our prologue, because, if he had known it, he would have mentioned it, since, as both of them point out, the usual practice of Alexandrian scholars was not to omit without comment passages they deemed spurious.Footnote 23 In support of their claim, both of them adduce Pfeiffer’s explanation of the scholarly methods of Zenodotus and Aristophanes of Byzantium, without mentioning that Pfeiffer’s explanation in fact concerns not Zenodotus’ and Aristophanes’ work on Greek tragedy but their work on the text of Homer.Footnote 24 It is not obvious that the methods the Alexandrian scholars employed on the text of Homer can straightforwardly be considered identical to those that they employed on the text of a Greek tragedy.

Indeed, as Pfeiffer himself surmises, Zenodotus’ text of the Iliad may have been based on a single manuscript which he considered the best among the many available in the library of Alexandria, which presumably contained widely diverging texts.Footnote 25 One could imagine that, while Aristophanes did adopt the Alexandrian practice of not deleting from a text lines which were contained in the manuscripts of Homer, he left unmentioned a prologue added by an actor which survived only in ‘wild’ copiesFootnote 26 to which he may or may not have had access.Footnote 27 The argument of Liapis and Fries that Aristophanes of Byzantium did not know our prologue of the Rhesus based solely on the fact that he did not mention it in his hypothesis is one that is made from silence. In fact, it cannot be argued with certainty that Aristophanes did not know our prologue. And, even if he did not know it, our prologue was clearly circulating in some manuscripts at the time hypothesis (b) was written, which is likely either around the time of Aristophanes or after it.Footnote 28 It does not matter a great deal for my argument whether our prologue was originally cited by Dicaearchus, by Aristophanes or by a later grammarian. In any case, it cannot have disappeared from circulation completely before reappearing in the tradition represented by the Byzantine manuscripts of Euripides, and therefore it seems difficult to rule out the possibility that Virgil could have known and alluded to it.

Now that it has been established with a reasonable degree of plausibility that Virgil could have accessed a manuscript of the Rhesus containing this prologue, let us consider the similarities between the Greek and the Latin texts in greater detail:

necdum etiam causae irarum saeuique dolores

exciderant animo; manet alta mente repostum

iudicium Paridis spretaeque iniuria formae

ἔμοι γὰρ οὐδέν ἐστιν ἄλγιον βάρος

ἐξ οὗ ἔκρινϵ Κύπριν Ἀλέξανδρος θέαν

κάλλϵι προήκϵιν τῆς ἐμῆς ϵὐμορφίας

dolor corresponds to ἄλγιον (TLL 5.1.1837.31–2), which is also recalled by iniuria, and two words denoting emotional suffering are in both passages placed at line-end. A temporal perspective is essential to both passages: the temporal indication necdum etiam … manet corresponds to ἐξ οὗ, ‘since’ (LSJ ἐκ II), which itself is reminiscent of Il. 1.5–6 Διὸς δ’ἐτϵλϵίϵτο βουλή, | ἐξ οὗ δὴ τὰ πρῶτα …, a passage which is concerned not only with the origin of a conflict in the general context of the Trojan War but precisely with a conflict set in motion by the anger of Achilles, a theme alluded to markedly by Virgil at the beginning of the Aeneid.Footnote 29 Athena is Hera’s interlocutor in the Rhesus prologue, and she is in the Virgilian Hera’s thoughts, as will be revealed at Aen. 1.39–41 (Pallasne exurere classem | Argiuum … potuit …, ‘yet Pallas had the power to burn down the fleet of the Argives …’). Both sentences begin from negation (necdum; οὐδέν). While it may be true, as the author of the hypothesis says, that the style of this passage is ‘banal’ (πϵζός), there is one crucial point that makes the notion that Virgil is alluding specifically to this passage particularly attractive. Indeed, both passages present the Judgement of Paris as a particularly significant motive for Hera/Juno’s anger against the Trojans, emphasizing the pain caused by not having been selected as the most beautiful goddess (κάλλϵι, ϵὐμορφίας; formae). In the Greek prologue, it is actually Hera who is speaking: the Virgilian narrator proceeds ‘as if he were quoting her [sc. Juno]’.Footnote 30 Accounts of the Judgement of Paris given from the perspective of Hera/Juno are not common.

There is therefore good reason to believe that Virgil is alluding to the Rhesus prologue. Yet, to the best of my knowledge, this is a parallel which has never been cited by any Virgilian commentator. At the very least, future commentators should consider mentioning this allusion to the Rhesus prologue in their notes on Aen. 1.25–7. Furthermore, accepting this allusion may open the way to some profitable interpretative possibilities which I survey here by way of conclusion.

The striking fact that, in the Iliad, the Judgement is mentioned for the first time only in the final book of the poem (Il. 24.25–30) makes it particularly striking that Virgil should include a reference to it so early and at such a prominent position in Aeneid Book 1.Footnote 31 Indeed, as already mentioned above, the lateness of this reference in Homer, as well as the belief that Homer did not even know the story of the Judgement of Paris, led Aristarchus to athetize Il. 24.29–30, a decision rejected by most, but not all, modern editors.Footnote 32 Davies has highlighted the significance of this passage within the context of the Iliad by showing that the reference to divine strife in Iliad Book 24, at a moment when reconciliation on the human level is imminent, gains by being understood in relation to the situation in Iliad Book 1, where anger among humans is rife, but potential strife among the gods is easily quelled.Footnote 33 It would be perfectly in keeping with what we know about Virgil’s allusive technique that he should be particularly attentive to lines that had received special scrutiny in Homeric scholarship. Moreover, Virgil’s reference to the Judgement comes at the beginning of a series of allusions to what Farrell has recently called a ‘Long Iliad’, a full account of the Trojan War as told in a series of epic poems including Homer’s Iliad as well as poems from the Epic Cycle such as the Cypria.Footnote 34 That Virgil is alluding to the Cypria, as scholars have suggested (see note 2 above), is plausible, and it is particularly attractive to imagine him alluding at the beginning of his poem to an episode which not only featured towards the beginning of the Cypria but also constitutes what stands chronologically as one of the earliest causes of Juno’s anger against the Trojans. It is widely recognized that the question of possible alternative beginnings is one that Virgil thematizes again and again in Aeneid Book 1.Footnote 35

Throughout the Aeneid, Virgil also often enriches his epic material with allusions to tragedy, and in Book 1 there is evidence that he engages with tragic prologues in particular. For instance, Mac Góráin has argued that, as early as the second line of his epic, Virgil alludes to the prologue of Euripides’ Bacchae.Footnote 36 Venus’ epiphany disguised as a huntress wearing buskins in front of Aeneas (1.314–37) has been seen to echo the prologue (and ending) of Euripides’ Hippolytus,Footnote 37 and thus may potentially be seen to form a pendant with Juno’s earlier ‘tragic’ opening. And by alluding to the Rhesus so early in the epic, Virgil sets into motion a pattern of allusion which extends at least until Book 9 and the Nisus and Euryalus episode. In particular, during the description of Juno’s temple in Carthage later in Book 1, Aeneas’ tearful reaction to seeing an image depicting the fate of Rhesus, which occupies a full five lines of text (1.469–73), would gain extra point after the allusion to the Rhesus tragedy in the prologue: the Trojan hero could be perceived as misreading the scene and not understanding that he himself, as another victim of Juno’s wrath, is in a sense another Rhesus.Footnote 38 More generally, Virgil’s allusion to the Rhesus prologue fits well within what Farrell calls the ‘culminating re-integration of tragedy into a totalizing epic structure that rivals Homer’.Footnote 39

Footnotes

*

I wish to thank Francesco Busti, Joseph Farrell, Luuk Huitink and Matthew Payne for their generous and valuable comments and suggestions. I am also grateful to CQ’s two anonymous readers, as well as to its editor, Bruce Gibson, for providing advice which helped to improve this article significantly.

References

1 The text of Virgil is cited from the edition of G.B. Conte, P. Vergilius Maro Aeneis (Berlin and Boston, 20192), the text of Euripides from that of J. Diggle, Euripidis fabulae (Oxford, 1984–94), 3 vols. Translations are my own unless otherwise indicated.

2 On Homer, see G.N. Knauer, Die Aeneis und Homer. Studien zur poetischen Technik Vergils mit Listen der Homerzitate in der Aeneis (Göttingen, 19792), 371, and already F. Ursinus, Virgilius collatione scriptorum Graecorum illustratus (Antwerp, 1567), 196. On the Cypria, E.C. Kopff, ‘Virgil and the Cyclic Epics’, ANRW 2.31.2 (1981), 919–47, at 924, 927; U. Gärtner, ‘Virgil and the Epic Cycle’, in M. Fantuzzi and C. Tsagalis (edd.), The Greek Epic Cycle and its Ancient Reception (Cambridge, 2015), 543–64, at 560. On Aristarchus’ athetesis, see F. Schironi, The Best of the Grammarians: Aristarchus of Samothrace on the Iliad (Ann Arbor, 2018), 633–5 with references.

3 Diggle’s MSS VLQ (Vaticanus gr. 909, fol. 295v; Laurentianus 32.2, fol. 119r; Harleianus 5743, fol. 66v); cf. Diggle (n. 1), 3.428.

4 For this interpretation of πϵζός instead of the more common sense of ‘prosaic’, see M. Fantuzzi, The Rhesus Attributed to Euripides (Cambridge, 2020), 137–8.

5 It was Valckenaer in the eighteenth century who pointed out that the speaker can only be Hera (L.C. Valckenaer, Diatribe in Euripidis perditorum dramatum reliquias [Leiden, 1767], 94). The only known appearance of Hera in Attic tragedy (not counting this prologue) seems to have been in Aesch. fr. 168 TrGF, a fragment which has been assigned to the Wool-Carders (Ξάντριαι) or to the Semele or Water-Carriers (Ὑδροφόροι). For discussion, see M. Wright, The Lost Plays of Greek Tragedy, 2 vols. (London, 2016–19), 2.48. I am grateful to Matthew Payne for drawing my attention to this fragment.

6 Translation from Fantuzzi (n. 4), 137.

7 W. Ritchie, The Authenticity of the Rhesus of Euripides (Cambridge, 1964), 110–11; M. Fantuzzi, ‘Performing and informing: on the prologues of the [Euripidean] Rhesus’, Trends in Classics 7 (2015), 224–36, at 230–1.

8 It is unclear to what extent, if at all, the Judgement featured in Euripides’ fragmentary Alexandros (frr. 42–63, V.1.174–204 TrGF): see I. Karamanou, Euripides, Alexandros. Introduction, Text and Commentary (Berlin and Boston, 2017), 10–11.

9 On Euripides, see T.C.W. Stinton, Euripides and the Judgement of Paris (London, 1965), 60, who describes κρίσις, ἔρις and μορφή as the three ‘key-words of the action’: κρίσις and προκρίνω are used in Proclus’ summary of the Cypria, as well as νϵῖκος and κάλλος (Procl. Chrest. 86–90 Severyns). The words κρίσις and ἔρις are also found in an anonymous papyrus dated to the first century b.c.e. or first century c.e. containing a hexameter account of the Judgement seemingly given by Penelope (P.Berol. inv. 10584 = P.Schubart 8 = 952 Suppl. Hell. = 72 APHex II [forthcoming]). It would have been interesting to compare the language used in Euripides’ versions of the Judgement with those of Sophocles in a satyr drama entitled Krisis (frr. 360–1, IV.324–5 TrGF) and of the fifth-century b.c.e. dramatist Cratinus in a comedy entitled Dionysalexandros (frr. 39–51, IV.140–7 K.–A.), had these two texts survived. It is also noteworthy that the story seems to have been told by Pindar (Pae. 8a, fr. 52i(A) S.–M.).

10 Th.K. Stephanopoulos, ‘Tragica 1’, ZPE 73 (1988), 207–47, at 208–9.

11 That Naevius’ poem contained an account of the Judgement seems likely: fr. 1 Blänsdorf has been interpreted as describing Aphrodite’s preparations for the beauty contest: E. Courtney, The Fragmentary Latin Poets (Oxford, 1993), 108.

12 B.C. Fenik, ‘The influence of Euripides on Vergil’s Aeneid’ (Diss., Princeton, 1960), 54–96; A. König, Die Aeneis und die griechische Tragödie. Studien zur imitatio-Technik Vergils (Diss., Berlin, 1970), 89–109; B. Pavlock, Eros, Imitation, and the Epic Tradition (Ithaca, NY, 1990), 87–112. Cf. P.R. Hardie, Virgil Aeneid Book IX (Cambridge, 1994), 30.

13 V. Liapis, ‘An ancient hypothesis to the Rhesus, and Dicaearchus’ hypotheseis’, GRBS 42 (2001), 313–27, at 317; A. Fries, ‘The Rhesus’, in V. Liapis and A.K. Petrides (edd.), Greek Tragedy after the Fifth Century: A Survey from ca. 400 BC to ca. AD 400 (Cambridge, 2019), 66–89, at 84–5; Fantuzzi (n. 7), 231.

14 Fantuzzi (n. 7), 224.

15 See E. Hall, ‘Tragic theatre: Demetrios’ rolls and Dionysos’ other woman’, in O. Taplin and R. Wyles (edd.), The Pronomos Vase and its Context (Oxford, 2009), 159–79, at 161–2 and, more generally, P.J. Finglass, ‘The textual tradition of Euripides’ dramas’, in A. Markantonatos (ed.), Brill’s Companion to Euripides, 2 vols. (Leiden and Boston, 2020), 1.29–48, at 32.

16 Hypothesis (b), [Eur.] Rhes. 24–5 = Arist. Didascaliae fr. 428 Gigon, part.

17 So A. Kirchhoff, ‘Das Argument zum Rhesos’, Philologus 7 (1852), 559–64, at 563–4, endorsed by Wehrli (Dicaearchus fr. 81) and more recently by V. Liapis, A Commentary on the Rhesus Attributed to Euripides (Oxford, 2012), 62–5.

18 Though some scholars doubt the ascription to Dicaearchus of hypotheses on the text of Euripides: for an account of the issue, see M. van Rossum-Steenbeek, Greek Readers’ Digests? (Leiden / New York / Cologne, 1998), 1–32.

19 Scholars who subscribe to this view include Ritchie (n. 7), 31; A. Fries, Pseudo-Euripides, Rhesus. Edited with Introduction and Commentary (Berlin and Boston, 2014), 112; and Fantuzzi (n. 4), 134–5.

20 Ritchie (n. 7), 31; Fantuzzi (n. 4), 134–5. Without denying that some of the information contained in hypothesis (b) is due to Aristophanes of Byzantium, P. Carrara, ‘Dicearco e l’hypothesis del Reso’, ZPE 90 (1992), 35–44, at 37 n. 9 suggests that the hypothesis also bears traces of the scholarship of Arius Didymus.

21 Ritchie (n. 7), 31; Carrara (n. 20), 37 n. 9.

22 Liapis (n. 13), 317–18; Fries (n. 19), 26.

23 Liapis (n. 13), 318 n. 5: ‘Omission of suspect lines was not practised by the Alexandrians’ (emphasis original); Fries (n. 19), 26: ‘That Aristophanes of Byzantium did not know them [the two prologues cited in hypothesis (b)] can be deduced not only from our standard text, but also from the statement in his hypothesis [sc. Diggle’s hypothesis (c)] that the sentry chorus “delivered the prologue” […]. The Alexandrians did not as a rule omit passages they deemed spurious.’

24 R. Pfeiffer, History of Classical Scholarship, 2 vols. (Oxford, 1968–76), 1.115 (‘Zenodotus did not suppress the lines [sc. of Homer] of which he doubted the genuineness, but left them in the context, marking them, however, on the margin with the obelus; he disclosed his own opinion and enabled the reader to check it’) and 1.173–4 (‘[Aristophanes was] reluctant to delete lines or to put conjectures in the text’; ‘he and his pupils preferred to express their opinions by signs in the margin’).

25 Pfeiffer (n. 24), 1.110. Cf. M.L. West, Studies in the Text and Transmission of the Iliad (Munich and Leipzig, 2001), 33–45, especially 43: ‘Zenodotus’ text [of the Iliad] was a rhapsode’s copy, or directly descended from one. It was not a critical text constructed by him from multiple sources, but a single exemplar that he happened to own and in which he marked his atheteses: that was his διόρθωσις.’

26 The term used by Fries (n. 19), 26. See further W.S. Barrett, Euripides: Hippolytos (Oxford, 19662), 56 n. 1.

27 See the cautious approach of Fantuzzi (n. 4), 135.

28 As Finglass (n. 15), 35 points out, ‘texts of Euripides continued to circulate outside that city [sc. Alexandria], and it seems unlikely that an Alexandrian edition [sc. of Euripides] could have entirely dominated the tradition of a poet increasingly read over the Greek-speaking Mediterranean.’ For a description of the Euripidean papyri dated between the first century b.c.e. and the first century c.e. (up until 2009), the majority of which were discovered at Oxyrhynchus, see P. Carrara, Il testo di Euripide nell’antichità. Ricerche sulla tradizione testuale euripidea antica, sec. IV a.C.–sec. VIII d.C. (Florence, 2009), 211–42.

29 The Homeric half-line Διὸς δ’ἐτϵλϵίϵτο βουλή was apparently imitated by the author of the Cypria (fr. 1.7 Bernabé = Σ A Hom. Il. 1.5 van Thiel). On reminiscences of the anger of Achilles at the beginning of the Aeneid, see most recently J. Farrell, Juno’s Aeneid. A Battle for Heroic Identity (Princeton, 2021), 55–6.

30 Farrell (n. 29), 118, citing Laird’s analysis of Juno’s use of ‘free indirect discourse’ (A. Laird, Powers of Expression, Expressions of Power. Speech Presentation and Latin Literature [Oxford, 1999], 96–9). A.M. Seider, Memory in Vergil’s Aeneid: Creating the Past (Cambridge, 2013), 7 suggests that these lines offer ‘a portrait of the working of Juno’s memory’.

31 One of CQ’s anonymous readers suggests that Virgil’s mention of the Judgement of Paris from line 25 onwards in the first book of the Aeneid may constitute a stichometric allusion to Homer’s brief account of the Judgement which begins at line 25 of the twenty-fourth and final book of the Iliad: ‘the analogy could be that Virgil “worked the other way round”.’

32 M.L. West, The Making of the Iliad: Disquisition and Analytical Commentary (Oxford, 2011), 412.

33 M. Davies, ‘The Judgement of Paris and Iliad Book XXIV’, JHS 101 (1981), 56–62, at 59–60.

34 Farrell (n. 29), 116–20.

35 D.P. Nelis, ‘From didactic to epic: Georgics 2.458–3.48’, in M. Gale (ed.), Latin Epic and Didactic Poetry. Genre, Tradition and Individuality (Swansea, 2004), 73–107, at 94.

36 Verg. Aen. 1.2 uenit ∼ Eur. Bacch. 1 ἥκω (a suggestion which, however, has not convinced all readers: see J.J. O’Hara, BMCR 2014.04.10); Aen. 1.4 saeuae memorem Iunonis ob iram, 1.8 Musa, mihi causas memora, quo numine laesoBacch. 6–9: see F. Mac Góráin, ‘Virgil’s Bacchus and the Roman Republic’, in J. Farrell and D.P. Nelis (edd.), Augustan Poetry and the Roman Republic (Oxford, 2013), 124–45, at 129–30.

37 E.L. Harrison, ‘Why did Venus wear boots? Some reflections on Aeneid 1.314f’, PVS 12 (1972–3), 10–25, at 18; cf. P.R. Hardie, ‘Virgil and tragedy’, in F. Mac Góráin and C. Martindale (edd.), The Cambridge Companion to Virgil (Cambridge, 20192), 326–41, at 336 and 339 (on Juno’s ‘mental…rehears[al of] old plays as examples to imitate in her own behaviour’).

38 On Aeneas as ‘a model for the negative reader who resists the bias of the text’ in this scene, see S. Casali, ‘Nisus and Euryalus: exploiting the contradictions in Virgil’s “Doloneia”’, HSPh 102 (2004), 319–54, at 348. My thanks to Francesco Busti for suggesting this idea to me.

39 Farrell (n. 29), 37.