Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T00:11:49.698Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Witnessing flows in arithmetic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 September 2024

Amirhossein Akbar Tabatabai*
Affiliation:
Institute of Mathematics, Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague, Czechia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

One of the elegant achievements in the history of proof theory is the characterization of the provably total recursive functions of an arithmetical theory by its proof-theoretic ordinal as a way to measure the time complexity of the functions. Unfortunately, the machinery is not sufficiently fine-grained to be applicable on the weak theories, on the one hand and to capture the bounded functions with bounded definitions of strong theories, on the other. In this paper, we develop such a machinery to address the bounded theorems of both strong and weak theories of arithmetic. In the first part, we provide a refined version of ordinal analysis to capture the feasibly definable and bounded functions that are provably total in $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha } \textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$, the extension of Peano arithmetic by transfinite induction up to the ordinals below $\alpha$. Roughly speaking, we identify the functions as the ones that are computable by a sequence of $\textrm{PV}$-provable polynomial time modifications on an initial polynomial time value, where the computational steps are indexed by the ordinals below $\alpha$, decreasing by the modifications. In the second part, and choosing $l \leq k$, we use similar technique to capture the functions with bounded definitions in the theory $T^k_2$ (resp. $S^k_2$) as the functions computable by exponentially (resp. polynomially) long sequence of $\textrm{PV}_{k-l +1}$-provable reductions between $l$-turn games starting with an explicit $\textrm{PV}_{k-l +1}$-provable winning strategy for the first game.

Type
Special Issue: WoLLIC 2022
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

One of the elegant achievements in the history of proof theory is the witnessing techniques connecting the provability of a formula of a certain form to the existence of a computational entity (algorithm (Troelstra Reference Troelstra1998), function (Fairtlough and Wainer Reference Fairtlough and Wainer1998), term in a type theory (Avigad and Feferman Reference Avigad and Feferman1998), etc.) that witnesses the truth of the formula. These connections identify the power of the theories, and they are useful to establish the unprovability of a formula by showing the nonexistence of the corresponding witness. As an example, consider the ordinal analysis as one of the well-known witnessing techniques that among many other things provides a characterization for the provably total recursive functions of some mathematical theories (Buss Reference Buss1994; Fairtlough and Wainer Reference Fairtlough and Wainer1998; Kreisel Reference Kreisel1952). (For a comprehensive high-level explanation, see Rathjen Reference Rathjen1999.) It connects the provability of the totality of a $\Sigma ^0_1$ -definable function to its time complexity, measured by the proof-theoretic ordinal of the theory. The characterization then leads to some independence results for the formulas in the form $A=\forall x \exists y B(x, y)$ , where $B \in \Sigma ^0_1$ is a definition of a function with a faster growth rate and hence higher time complexity than what the theory can actually reach (Fairtlough and Wainer Reference Fairtlough and Wainer1998).

There are, however, some settings in which the witnessing techniques and especially the one based on ordinal analysis break down. Sometimes, we are only interested in the formulas with no existential quantifiers to witness (e.g., $A=\forall x B(x)$ , where $B$ is a quantifier-free formula). Other times, the theory is so weak that even the basics of the witnessing machinery goes beyond the power of the theory. Even working with powerful theories, there can be some problematic situations. For instance, one may be interested in bounded formulas (e.g., $\forall x \exists y \leq t(x) B(x, y)$ , where all quantifiers in $B$ are also bounded) provable in Peano arithmetic, denoted by $\textrm{PA}$ . Here, what the usual witnessing methods provide is rather weak or even useless. For instance, using ordinal analysis for $\textrm{PA}$ , the best thing we can learn in the bounded setting is the existence of an algorithm to compute $y$ using a huge amount of time measured by $\varepsilon _0$ , the ordinal of the theory. This is much weaker than what we started with, that is, the provability of the totality of the function with a bounded definition. The reason roughly is that the algorithm leads to the existence of the definition $\exists w C(x, w, y)$ for the function, where $w$ encodes the computation and $\textrm{PA}$ proves $\forall x \exists yw C(x, w, y)$ . However, the computation $w$ can be huge and hence unbounded by the terms in the language and in this sense proving the totality of a bounded function with a bounded definition is stronger than the existence of such an algorithm.

To solve this type of issues and to address both weak theories and low complexity formulas, many new witnessing techniques were designed, from witnessing the universal provable formulas by short propositional proofs (Buss Reference Buss1997; Cook Reference Cook1975; Krajíček and Pudlák Reference Krajíček and Pudlák1990; Paris and Wilkie Reference Paris and Wilkie1981) to witnessing provable bounded formulas in first-order bounded theories of arithmetic in special cases (Buss Reference Buss1986; Buss and Krajíček Reference Buss and Krajíček1994; Krajíček et al. Reference Krajíček, Skelley and Thapen2007) and then in general cases (Beckmann and Buss Reference Beckmann and Buss2010; Skelley and Thapen Reference Skelley and Thapen2011; Thapen Reference Thapen2011), using game reductions and different versions of local search problems. A similar technique is also developed for second-order bounded theories of arithmetic (Beckmann and Buss Reference Beckmann and Buss2017, Reference Beckmann and Buss2014; Buss et al. Reference Buss, Krajíček and Takeuti1993; Kołodziejczyk et al. Reference Kołodziejczyk, Nguyen and Thapen2011) and even for Peano arithmetic (Beckmann Reference Beckmann2009). In this paper, we will continue this line of research by providing a general witnessing machinery to witness the low-complexity theorems both in strong and weak theories of arithmetic using a computational entity that we call a flow. Flows are meant to formalize the idea of flowing information and they formally are uniform suitably long sequences of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between formulas in a suitable class, where $\textrm{PV}$ is Cook’s theory for polynomial time functions. We will work with two different types of flows in this paper, ordinal flows and $k$ -flows.

Ordinal flows

An ordinal flow is a transfinite uniform sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between universal formulas. We use ordinal flows to witness low-complexity theorems of the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha } \textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ , where $\alpha$ is an ordinal with a certain polynomial time representation and $\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ means the transfinite induction up to the ordinal $\beta$ . More precisely, we witness the provability of an implication between two universal formulas in $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha }\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ by a uniform sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications of length $\beta \prec \alpha$ . Using Herbrand’s theorem for $\textrm{PV}$ , we push the witnessing further to witness the $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha }\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ -provable formulas in the form $A=\forall \bar{x}\exists \bar{y} B(\bar{x},\bar{y})$ , where $B$ is a polynomial time computable predicate by an algorithm to compute $\bar{y}$ by a sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable polynomial time modifications on an initial polynomial time value, where the computational steps are indexed by the ordinals below $\alpha$ , decreasing by the modifications. Our result generalizes the main theorem of Beckmann (Reference Beckmann2009) that developed a similar characterization for $\textrm{PA}$ . However, as we will explain below, even for that special case, we use a simpler and easier to generalize methodology.

To compare our result to the existing literature on ordinal analysis, it is important to focus on the role of the polynomial time computable functions and the theory $\textrm{PV}$ in our contribution. First, note that changing the polynomial time functions and $\textrm{PV}$ in our characterization to the elementary or primitive recursive functions and $\textrm{ERA}$ or $\textrm{PRA}$ , respectively, makes the characterization an easy consequence of the known facts in the ordinal analysis literature. For instance, one can use the powerful witnessing theorems in Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995), Avigad (Reference Avigad2002) or the interesting algebraic presentation of the ordinals in Beklemishev (Reference Beklemishev2004). What is not trivial, though, is providing a low-complexity version suitable to witness the low-complexity theorems of arithmetic. To reach such a version, we have two options. The first, as followed in the above-mentioned paper (Beckmann Reference Beckmann2009), rewrites the continuous cut elimination technique (Buchholz Reference Buchholz1991, Reference Buchholz1997), replacing all primitive recursive functions by more careful polynomial time computable operations (Beckmann et al. Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003). The second as an indirect approach uses the known results in ordinal analysis as a black-box and rewitness them in a feasible manner to circumvent redoing the tedious ordinal analysis argument. This option is what we follow in the present paper. More precisely, we first use the refined ordinal analysis in Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995) to show that a $\Pi ^0_2$ -formula is provable in the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha }\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ iff it is provable in an extension of $\textrm{PRA}$ with a weak form of transfinite induction. Then, using a suitable polynomial time representation for the ordinals below $\alpha$ , we will transform a proof in the weaker theory to a sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable polynomial time modifications described above. Our technique of using ordinally long sequence of easy modifications is similar to what used in Avigad (Reference Avigad2002), although its machinery has a more model-theoretic character and also implements the ordinal analysis from the scratch. Roughly speaking, Avigad (Reference Avigad2002) provides a similar witnessing theorem using elementary functions rather than polynomial time functions in its ordinal flows. However, to have a verifiablity criterion, it insists on having the whole witnessing process provable inside the meta-theory $\textrm{PRA}$ . The witnessing machinery of Avigad (Reference Avigad2002) cannot be directly used to prove the low-complexity version we are interested in here. The reason is its use of $\textrm{PRA}$ -formalized Herbrand’s theorem for first-order logic that uses cut elimination, and it is extremely costly to be directly formalizable in $\textrm{PV}$ . To solve the issue, as Avigad (Reference Avigad2002) also suggests, one must witness the Herbrand’s theorem part by a sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -verifiable modifications or equivalently witness the first-order logic by such modifications, directly. This is one of the things we do in the present paper. Therefore, although our work is inspired by Beckmann (Reference Beckmann2009) and the witnessing theorems in bounded arithmetic and hence its technique was developed independent from Avigad (Reference Avigad2002), one can interpret our contribution as a generalization of Avigad (Reference Avigad2002) making its machinery applicable even in the low-complexity settings.

$k$ -flows

A (polynomial) $k$ -flow is a uniform (polynomially) exponentially long sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas. Recall that $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ - ( $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -formulas) are roughly the formulas with $k$ -many bounded quantifier blocks starting with a universal (existential) block and followed by a quantifier-free formula over the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ that has a term for any polynomial time computable function. We will witness the provability of an implication between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas in $T^k_2$ (resp. $S^k_2$ ) by a $k$ -flow (resp. polynomial $k$ -flow). To push the witnessing further, we can use Herbrand’s theorem again for the universal theory $\textrm{PV}$ . However, this time the formulas are in $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and hence we have $k$ -many layers of quantifier to peel off. To control the number of layers, we intend to remove, and we will follow a relative approach. We fix a number $l \leq k$ and only peel off the outmost $l$ many quantifier blocks. More precisely, we first move the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications from $\textrm{PV}$ to $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ , a universal theory for the functions in the $(k-l+1)$ -th level of the polynomial hierarchy. This way we can pretend that all the formulas in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-l} \cup \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-l}$ are quantifier-free. Therefore, only $l$ many quantifier blocks are left to witness. Using Herbrand’s theorem for the theory $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ and reading any quantifier-free formula in the language of $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ as an $l$ -turn game (Skelley and Thapen Reference Skelley and Thapen2011), we can then witness any $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implication by an explicit $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ -verifiable reduction between $l$ -turn games. These reductions are somewhat nondeterministic mapping their input values to some possible instances, where one of the options may work, (see the second part in Theorem 2 to see what we mean by nondeterminism in this context). Finally, using these reductions, we show that a formula in the form $\forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y)$ , where $B \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-l} \cup \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-l}$ is provable in $T^k_2$ (resp. $S^k_2$ ) iff there is a uniform (polynomially) exponentially long sequence of $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ -verifiable reductions between $l$ -turn games, starting from an explicit $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ -verifiable winning strategy for the first game. We will only spell out the details for $l=1,2$ . For $l=1$ , we show that our witnessing theorem reproves some of the well-known witnessing theorems for $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ including the usual witnessing of $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -definable functions of $S^k_2$ by $\square ^p_k$ -functions (Buss Reference Buss1986) and $\hat{\Sigma }^b_1$ -definable multifunctions of $T^1_2$ by polynomial local search problems Buss and Krajíček (1994). For $l=2$ , we provide new witnessing theorems. For $T^k_2$ , there are other witnessing methods providing similar characterizations as ours based on better (i.e., deterministic) game reductions (Skelley and Thapen Reference Skelley and Thapen2011; Thapen Reference Thapen2011). The theory of flows can also prove these stronger characterizations. However, it needs to work with more involved notions of a $k$ -flow than what we have here. We leave such investigations to another paper. For $S^k_2$ , however, our result, to the best of our knowledge, is the only characterization in the same style of the original witnessing theorems (Buss Reference Buss1986) that reduce the provability in $S^k_2$ to a polynomially long sequence of feasible modifications. Of course, one can use the conservativity of $S^k_2$ over $T^{k-1}_2$ for $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}$ -formulas and then using the witnessing for $T^{k-1}_2$ by the deterministic game reductions (Skelley and Thapen Reference Skelley and Thapen2011; Thapen Reference Thapen2011) or any other characterization (Beckmann and Buss 2009, 2010), find a witnessing theorem for $S^k_2$ . Using this approach, the characterizations provide an exponentially long sequence of deterministic reductions while we provide a polynomially long sequence of more complex nondeterministic reductions. These two different approaches can be seen as an instance of the usual phenomenon of simulating the huge power of the deterministic exponential time with polynomial time nondeterminism, where the latter, if possible, is more informative than the former.

Finally, to compare our witnessing method to the rich literature on witnessing theorems in bounded arithmetic, let us emphasize two points that we find unique to our characterization. First, unlike the methods used in Buss and Krajíček (Reference Buss and Krajíček1994), Krajíček et al. (Reference Krajíček, Skelley and Thapen2007), Skelley and Thapen (Reference Skelley and Thapen2011), Thapen (Reference Thapen2011), Beckmann and Buss (2009, 2010), our machinery is sufficiently general to directly witness bounded theories arising from practically any type of bounded induction Akbar Tabatabai (Reference Tabatabai2018). For instance, for any $m \geq 2$ , consider the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}} \cup \{\#_m\}$ , where $x\#_2 y=2^{|x||y|}$ and $x \#_{i+1} y=2^{|x| \#_i |y|}$ and define the class $\hat{\Pi }^b_k(\#_m)$ and the theory $\textrm{PV}(\#_m)$ over the new language similar to $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $\textrm{PV}$ over $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . Now, for any $n \geq 0$ , $m \geq n+2$ , and $k \geq 1$ , define the theory $R^k_{m, n}$ as the extension of a basic universal theory to handle the function symbols, by the induction axiom

\begin{equation*} A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(x+1)) \to \forall x A(|x|_n) \end{equation*}

where $A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k(\#_m)$ , $|x|_0=x$ , and $|x|_{j+1}=||x|_j|$ . It is easy to imitate our technique in the present paper to witness $R^k_{m,n}$ -provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k(\#_m)$ -formulas by a uniform sequence of $\textrm{PV}(\#_m)$ -provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k(\#_m)$ -formulas with the length $|t|_n$ , for some term $t$ . This can be even more generalized to any type of induction satisfying some basic properties Akbar Tabatabai (Reference Tabatabai2018).

The second point is that the length of our witnessing flows honestly reflects the type of the induction we use. For instance, for $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ , we use polynomially long and exponentially long $k$ -flows, respectively, and more generally, in $R^k_{m, n}$ where the induction is up to $|x|_n$ , the length of the witnessing flow is $|t|_n$ , for some term $t$ , see Akbar Tabatabai (Reference Tabatabai2018). This honest correspondence is not typical with the above-mentioned characterizations. For instance, the polynomially long adaptation of the known characterizations for $T^k_2$ (Skelley and Thapen Reference Skelley and Thapen2011; Thapen Reference Thapen2011), that is, polynomially long sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -verifiable deterministic reductions between $k$ -turn games, does not witness $S^k_2$ -provable implications. The reason is that any polynomially long iteration of a deterministic reduction is again a deterministic reduction itself. Therefore, if such a witnessing theorem holds, one can witness the implications in $S^k_2$ between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas by a polynomially long sequence of reductions and hence only one reduction. Thus, the $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -definable functions of $S^k_2$ must be all polynomial time computable and as all the functions in $\square ^p_k$ are $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -definable in $S^k_2$ , the polynomial hierarchy must collapse. This simple observation shows that the nondeterminism we use in our reductions is essential to have an honest characterization. Moreover, it shows that our characterization for $S^k_2$ is not a simple consequence of the methodologies used for $T^k_2$ in Skelley and Thapen (Reference Skelley and Thapen2011), Thapen (Reference Thapen2011) or even in Beckmann and Buss (2009, 2010).

Here is the structure of the paper. In Section 2, we recall the basic definitions of different languages and arithmetical systems we use in this paper. In Section 3, we introduce our version of polynomial time ordinal representation and we recall the one introduced in Beckmann et al. (Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003) for $\varepsilon _0$ . In Section 4, we present ordinal flows and the witnessing technique to reduce the provability of the low complexity statements in the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \prec \alpha }\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ . Finally, in Section 5, we introduce $k$ -flows to witness the provability of the low complexity statements in the theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ .

2. Preliminaries

For any first-order language $\mathcal{L}$ , by an $\mathcal{L}$ -formula, we mean any expression constructible by the connectives $\{\wedge, \vee, \forall, \exists \}$ from the atomic formulas (including $\bot$ and $\top$ ) and their negations. The formula $\neg A$ is defined via de Morgan laws and $A \to B$ is an abbreviation for $\neg A \vee B$ . By an $\mathcal{L}$ -term, we simply mean a term in the language $\mathcal{L}$ . By $\bar{t}$ , we mean a sequence of terms in the language and $\bar{x}$ means a sequence of variables.

To introduce the system $\textrm{PV}$ , let us recall Cobham’s machine-independent characterization of polynomial-time computable (ptime, for short) functions (Cobham Reference Cobham1965). It states that a function is ptime iff it is constructible from certain basic functions by composition and a weak sort of recursion called the bounded recursion on notation. Any such construction provides an algorithm to compute the corresponding ptime function. Let $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ be a first-order language with a function symbol for any such algorithm. In Cook (Reference Cook1975), Cook introduced an equational theory over the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ to reason about ptime functions. The theory essentially consists of the defining axioms for the function symbols together with a sort of induction rule. Later, a conservative first-order extension of $\textrm{PV}$ , denoted by $\textrm{PV}_1$ , was introduced by Krajíček et al. (Reference Krajíček, Pudlák and Takeuti1991). The theory has the polynomial induction axiom scheme denoted by $\textrm{PInd}$

\begin{equation*} A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(\lfloor \frac {x}{2} \rfloor ) \to A(x)) \to \forall x A(x), \end{equation*}

for any quantifier-free formula $A(x)$ and is universally axiomatizable (Krajíček et al. Reference Krajíček, Pudlák and Takeuti1991). In this paper, we will only use the theory $\textrm{PV}_1$ and not $\textrm{PV}$ . Therefore, by abuse of notation, we will use the name $\textrm{PV}$ to denote its first-order extension $\textrm{PV}_1$ .

In any language extending $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ , by a bounded quantifier, we mean a quantifier in the form $\forall x (x \leq t \to A(x))$ or $\exists x (x \leq t \wedge A(x))$ , abbreviated by $\forall x \leq t \, A(x)$ and $\exists x \leq t \, A(x)$ , respectively. For any sequence of variables $\bar{x}=(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$ and terms $\bar{t}=(t_1, \ldots, t_n)$ , by $Q \bar{x} \leq \bar{t} \, A(\bar{x})$ , we mean $Q x_1 \leq t_1 Q x_2 \leq t_2 \ldots A(x_1, \ldots, x_n)$ , for any $Q \in \{\forall, \exists \}$ .

By recursion on $k$ , define the classes $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ and $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas in the following way:

  • $\hat{\Pi }^b_0=\hat{\Sigma }^b_0$ is the class of all quantifier-free formulas,

  • $\hat{\Sigma }_k^b \subseteq \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k+1}$ and $\hat{\Pi }^b_k \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_{k+1}$ ,

  • $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ are closed under conjunction and disjunction,

  • If $B(x) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ , then $\exists x \leq t \; B(x) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ and $\forall x \leq t \; B(x) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k+1}$ and

  • If $B(x) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ , then $\forall x \leq t \; B(x) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $\forall x \leq t \; B(x) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k+1}$ .

Define $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{\infty }=\hat{\Pi }^b_{\infty }$ as $\bigcup _{k=0}^{\infty } \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}$ that is the same as $\bigcup _{k=0}^{\infty } \hat{\Pi }^b_{k}$ . For the sake of simplicity, we suppressed the free variables in our notation in the above definition while they are also allowed to be used in the formulas.

By the axiom scheme $\hat{\Pi }^b_k-\textrm{PInd}$ , we mean

\begin{equation*} A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(\lfloor \frac {x}{2} \rfloor ) \rightarrow A(x)) \rightarrow \forall x A(x), \end{equation*}

for any $A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and by $\hat{\Pi }^b_{k}-\textrm{Ind}$ , we mean

\begin{equation*} A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \rightarrow A(x+1)) \rightarrow \forall x A(x), \end{equation*}

for $A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . The schemes $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}-\textrm{PInd}$ and $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}-\textrm{Ind}$ are defined similarly. For any $k \geq 1$ , define the theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ as $\textrm{PV}+\hat{\Pi }^b_k-\textrm{PInd}$ and $\textrm{PV}+\hat{\Pi }^b_k-\textrm{Ind}$ , respectively. It is known that $S^k_2$ (resp., $T^k_2$ ) proves $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}-\textrm{PInd}$ (resp., $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k}-\textrm{Ind}$ ). It is also useful to mention that the following axiom scheme, denoted by $\hat{\Pi }^b_k-\textrm{LInd}$

\begin{equation*} A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \rightarrow A(x+1)) \rightarrow \forall x A(|x|), \end{equation*}

where $A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ , is provable in $S^k_2$ . The same also holds for $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k-\textrm{LInd}$ , where we replace $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ by $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). The following theorem is true for theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ Krajíček (Reference Krajíček1995).

Theorem. (Parikh) Let $T$ be either $S^k_2$ or $T^k_2$ , for some $k \geq 1$ and $A(\bar{x}, y)$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{\infty }$ . Then, if $T \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y A(\bar{x}, y)$ , then there exists an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $t(\bar{x})$ such that $T \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq t(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ .

It is possible to define a universal theory for any level in the polynomial hierarchy, similar to what $\textrm{PV}_1$ does for the polynomial time computable functions. More precisely, for any $k \geq 2$ , one can define a universal theory $\textrm{PV}_{k}$ over an extended language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ that has a term for any function in the $k$ th level of the polynomial hierarchy, denoted by $\square ^p_k$ (Krajíček et al. Reference Krajíček, Pudlák and Takeuti1991). We do not spell out the details of these theories. The only thing we need to know is that $\textrm{PV}_k$ has an explicit term for the characteristic functions of $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -formula and its term construction allows defining functions by bounded recursion on notation (Krajíček et al. Reference Krajíček, Pudlák and Takeuti1991; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). As $\textrm{PV}_k$ is universal, it enjoys Herbrand’s theorem (Buss Reference Buss1998b; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995):

Theorem. (Herbrand) Let $A(\bar{x}, y)$ and $B(\bar{x}, y, z)$ be two quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formulas. Then:

  • If $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \exists y A(\bar{x}, y)$ , then there exists an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $f(\bar{x})$ such that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash A(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}))$ .

  • If $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \exists y \forall z B(\bar{x}, y, z)$ , then there are $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms $f_0(\bar{x}), f_1(\bar{x}, z_0), f_2(\bar{x}, z_0, z_1), \ldots,$ $f_m(\bar{x}, z_0, z_1, \ldots, z_{m-1})$ such that $ \bigvee _{i=0}^m B(\bar{x}, f_i(\bar{x}, z_0, \ldots, z_{i-1}), z_{i})$ is provable in $\textrm{PV}_k$ .

It is possible to generalize this theorem to a generalized Herbrand’s theorem to cover more alternations of quantifiers. However, in this paper, one can restrict oneself only to these two levels (Buss Reference Buss1998b).

The system $\textrm{PV}_k$ proves the scheme $\textrm{PInd}$ for any quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula. As any $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term can be defined by an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ , it is possible to represent any quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula by two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas, one in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ and one in $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Using this fact, one can interpret $\textrm{PV}_k$ inside the theory $S^k_2$ .

Going beyond bounded theories of arithmetic, in a similar fashion to $\textrm{PV}$ and using the construction of primitive recursive functions by composition and primitive recursion on certain basic functions, it is possible to extend the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ by a fresh function symbol for any primitive recursive function. Denote this new language by $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ and set the first-order theory $\textrm{PRA}$ over $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ as $\textrm{PV}$ extended by the defining axioms for the new functional symbols and the induction axiom $A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(x+1)) \to \forall x A(x)$ , for any quantifier-free formula in the new language. This is of course different from the usual definition of $\textrm{PRA}$ as its language is extended by the ptime function symbols in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ , and the theory itself is extended by the theory $\textrm{PV}$ . Moreover, the formula in the induction axiom of $\textrm{PRA}$ may contain the symbols from $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . However, as the functions in the Cobham calculus are constructible as primitive recursive functions, it is clear that the separation of the primitive recursive function symbols and ptime function symbols is just a technical point and is totally immaterial. In fact, our presentation of $\textrm{PRA}$ is a conservative extension of the usual $\textrm{PRA}$ and hence has nothing essentially different from the usual $\textrm{PRA}$ .

By Peano arithmetic, denoted by $\textrm{PA}$ , we mean the theory $\textrm{PV}$ extended by full induction axiom scheme $A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(x+1)) \to \forall x A(x)$ , for any formula $A(x)$ . This is also different from the usual definition of $\textrm{PA}$ . However, as all of the function symbols in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ are definable in the usual language of $\textrm{PA}$ and their functionality and totality are provable in the usual $\textrm{PA}$ , it is easy to see that our $\textrm{PA}$ is a conservative extension of the usual $\textrm{PA}$ .

By $\Pi ^0_2$ , we mean the class of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas in the form $\forall \bar{x} \exists \bar{y}A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ , where any quantifier in $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ is bounded. For two theories $T$ and $S$ and a class of formulas $\Phi$ , by $T \equiv _{\Phi } S$ , we mean $T \vdash A$ iff $S \vdash A$ , for any $A \in \Phi$ .

Finally, let us recall some basics of the ordinal arithmetic. Apart from addition, multiplication, and exponentiation of the ordinals, it is also possible to define subtraction $\dot{-}$ from left such that $\alpha \dot{-} \beta =0$ , if $\alpha \prec \beta$ and $\alpha \dot{-} \beta =\gamma$ , if $\beta \preceq \alpha$ , where $\gamma$ is the unique ordinal with the property that $\beta + \gamma =\alpha$ . Similarly, it is possible to define the division $d$ from left such that if $\beta \neq 0$ , then $d(\alpha, \beta )$ is the unique $\gamma$ such that $\alpha =\beta \gamma + \delta$ , for some $\delta \prec \beta$ .

3. Polynomial-Time Ordinal Representations

In this section, we will introduce polynomial time ordinal representations and recall the concrete representation for the ordinal $\varepsilon _0$ provided in Beckmann et al. (Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003). Both parts will be of essential use in Section 4.

Definition 1. Let $\alpha$ be an infinite ordinal closed under addition, multiplication, and the operation $\beta \mapsto \omega ^{\beta }$ . We call the tuple

\begin{equation*} \mathfrak {O}=(\mathcal {O}, \prec, +, \cdot, \dot {-}, d(\cdot, \cdot ), o, x \mapsto \omega ^{x}, \textbf {0}, \textbf {1}, \omega ) \end{equation*}

a polynomial time representation with a primitive recursive exponentiation (ptime representation, for short) for the ordinal $\alpha$ , if:

  • $\mathcal{O}$ is a unary polynomial time relation on the natural numbers represented as a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula. Its intended meaning is the set of all the representations of the ordinals below $\alpha$ . We use small Greek letters to denote the elements of $\mathcal{O}$ . For instance, by $\forall \beta \, A(\beta )$ , we actually mean $\forall x (\mathcal{O}(x) \to A(x))$ .

  • $\prec$ is a binary polynomial time relation on the natural numbers, represented as a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula. Its intended meaning is the order over the ordinals below $\alpha$ . We define the relation $(\gamma \preceq \beta )$ as $(\gamma \prec \beta ) \vee (\gamma =\beta )$ .

  • $+, \cdot, \dot{-}$ and $ d(\cdot, \cdot )$ are binary polynomial time functions, represented as $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms. Their intended meaning is the ordinal addition, multiplication, subtraction from left, and division from left, respectively.

  • $o$ is a unary polynomial time function represented as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term. Its intended meaning is the function that maps the natural numbers to the representation of their order-types below $\alpha$ . For instance, $o(0)$ is the least element of $\mathcal{O}$ while $o(1)$ is its second least element.

  • $\omega ^{x}$ is a primitive recursive unary function represented as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ -term. Its intended meaning is the function that maps the ordinal $\beta \prec \alpha$ to the ordinal $\omega ^{\beta } \prec \alpha$ .

  • $\textbf{0}$ , $\textbf{1}$ and $\omega$ are three numbers representing the ordinals zero, one and $\omega$ , respectively.

  • The structure $(\mathfrak{O}, \prec )$ is isomorphic to $(\alpha, \prec _{\alpha })$ , where $\prec _{\alpha }$ is the order on $\alpha$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves that $\prec$ is a total ordering on $\mathcal{O}$ with the minimum $\textbf{0}$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves that $\prec$ is discrete over $\mathcal{O}$ , that is, for all $\beta, \gamma \in \mathcal{O}$ , if $\gamma \prec \beta +\textbf{1}$ , then either $\gamma \prec \beta$ or $ \gamma =\beta$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves the associativity of the addition and multiplication, the left distributivity of multiplication over the addition, the neutrality of $\textbf{0}$ for the addition, the neutrality of $\textbf{1}$ for the multiplication and the identity $\textbf{0}\beta =\beta \textbf{0}=\textbf{0}$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves that the addition and the nonzero multiplication from left respect the order $\prec$ , that is, if $\delta \prec \gamma$ then $\beta + \delta \prec \beta + \gamma$ and if we also have $\beta \neq \textbf{0}$ , then $\beta \delta \prec \beta \gamma$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves that the addition and multiplication from right respects $\preceq$ , that is, if $\delta \preceq \gamma$ then $\delta +\beta \preceq \gamma + \beta$ and $\delta \beta \preceq \gamma \beta$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves the defining axioms of $\dot{-}$ , that is, if $\alpha \prec \beta$ then $\alpha \dot{-} \beta =\textbf{0}$ and if $\alpha \succeq \beta$ then $\alpha =\beta +(\alpha \dot{-} \beta )$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves the defining axioms of $d$ , that is, if $\beta \neq \textbf{0}$ , then $\beta d(\alpha, \beta ) \preceq \alpha$ and $\alpha \dot{-} \beta d(\alpha, \beta ) \prec \beta$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}$ proves that $o$ is an order-isomorphism between the natural numbers and the ordinals below $\omega$ , mapping $0$ and $1$ to $\textbf{0}$ and $\textbf{1}$ , respectively, that is, $\textrm{PV}$ proves $o(0)=\textbf{0}$ , $o(1)=\textbf{1}$ , $\forall x [\mathcal{O}(o(x)) \wedge o(x) \prec \omega ]$ , $\forall \beta \prec \omega \exists ! y \, o(y)=\beta$ , and $\forall xy (x \lt y \leftrightarrow o(x) \prec o(y))$ . Where there is no risk of confusion, we will use the numbers and their ordinal reinterpretations, interchangeably. For instance, we use $1$ for $\textbf{1}$ .

  • $\textrm{PRA}$ proves that $\omega ^{\textbf{0}}=1$ and $\omega ^{\textbf{1}}=\omega$ . It also proves that $\omega ^{\beta }$ respects $\preceq$ and maps the addition to the multiplication.

  • If there is no $\gamma \in \mathcal{O}$ such that $\beta =\gamma +1$ , then $\omega ^{\beta }$ is the supremum of the set $\{\omega ^{\gamma } \mid \gamma \prec \beta \}$ , that is, for any $\delta \in \mathcal{O}$ , if $\omega ^{\gamma } \preceq \delta$ , for any $\gamma \prec \beta$ , then $\omega ^{\beta } \preceq \delta$ .

  • $\textrm{PRA}$ proves that for every $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ , there is a unique expansion $\beta =\omega ^{\gamma _1}+ \ldots + \omega ^{\gamma _n}$ such that $\gamma _n \preceq \gamma _{n-1} \preceq \ldots \preceq \gamma _1$ .

Remark 2. Here are some remarks. First, notice that the relations of being a successor and a limit ordinal are both definable by the predicates $\exists \gamma (\beta =\gamma +1)$ and $\forall \gamma \prec \beta (\gamma +1 \prec \beta )$ , respectively. It is also easy to see that $\textrm{PV}$ can prove the dichotomy that for any $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ , it is either a successor or a limit. Second, using the compatibility of the order with the addition and the multiplication, one can easily prove in $\textrm{PV}$ that if $\beta =\gamma +\delta =\gamma +\eta$ , then $\beta \dot{-} \gamma =\delta =\eta$ . This observation proves that for any $\gamma \prec \beta$ , the interval $(\textbf{0}, \beta \dot{-} \gamma )$ in $\mathcal{O}$ is in one-to-one correspondence with the interval $(\gamma, \beta )$ , via the map $\delta \mapsto \gamma +\delta$ . Similarly, $\textrm{PV}$ proves that if $\gamma \neq \textbf{0}$ , then $\beta =\gamma \delta =\gamma \eta$ implies $d(\beta, \gamma )=\delta =\eta$ . Therefore, $d(\gamma \delta, \gamma )=\delta$ , for $\gamma \neq \textbf{0}$ . Third, let us explain the discrepancy between the polynomial time character of the order, addition, multiplication, subtraction, and division and the primitive recursive character of the function $x \mapsto \omega ^{x}$ in our definition. For that purpose, first, pretend that our definition uses the primitive recursive functions and predicates and $\textrm{PRA}$ everywhere when it actually uses polynomial time functions and predicates and $\textrm{PV}$ . Then, one can easily see that this primitive recursive version of our representation is just a mild extension of the primitive recursive (even elementary) ordinal representation employed in Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995). (Their conditions are different, but it is easy to show that our axioms imply theirs.) As we use a proof-theoretic result of Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995), using the primitive recursive version of our definition is completely justified. However, there is another role for our ordinal representation. As it is clear, in this paper, we intend to address the lower complexity formulas and for that purpose, some basic ordinal arithmetic (up to addition and multiplication and hence subtraction and division from left) is required to be implemented in polynomial time. Therefore, we are forced to lower the complexity of some parts of the representation. However, as the use of the exponentiation is only restricted to the result from Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995) that we use as a black box here, we decided to lower the complexity up to the point we need and let the exponentiation parts intact. This way we can accept more ptime representations.

Let $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ . By the axiom scheme $\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ , we mean the transfinite induction up to $\beta$ , that is

\begin{equation*} \forall \gamma \prec \beta [\forall \delta \prec \gamma A(\delta ) \to A(\gamma )] \to \forall \gamma \prec \beta A(\gamma ), \end{equation*}

where $A$ can be any formula in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . In Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995), a refined method of ordinal analysis is provided showing that the $\Pi ^0_2$ -consequences of the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}} \textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ are actually provable in a smaller theory extending $\textrm{PRA}$ with a weak form of transfinite induction stating that for any $\beta \prec \alpha$ , there is no primitive recursive decreasing sequence of ordinals below $\beta$ . For more, see Friedman and Sheard (Reference Friedman and Sheard1995), Rathjen (Reference Rathjen1999).

Theorem. Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal and $\mathfrak{O}$ be its ptime representation. Then,

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal {O}}\textrm {TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \equiv _{\Pi ^0_2} \textrm {PRA}+ \bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal {O}} \textrm {PRWO}({\prec_{\beta}}), \end{equation*}

where $\textrm{PRWO}({\prec_{\beta}})$ is the scheme $ \forall \bar{x} \exists y [f(\bar{x}, y+1) \nprec f(\bar{x}, y) \vee \neg \mathcal{O}(f(\bar{x}, y)) \vee f(\bar{x}, y) \nprec \beta ]$ , for any function symbol $f$ in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ .

3.1 A polynomial-time representation for $\varepsilon _0$

In this subsection, we will recall the basics of the ptime notation system for the ordinal $\varepsilon _0$ , introduced in Beckmann et al. (Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003). Define $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ and $\prec _{0}$ inductively and simultaneously in the following way: $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ is the least set of expressions containing the empty string $\textbf{0}$ and is closed under the operation $(\alpha _1, \ldots, \alpha _n) \mapsto \omega ^{\alpha _1}a_1+ \ldots +\omega ^{\alpha _n}a_n$ , where $a_i \neq 0$ are natural numbers and $\alpha _n \prec _{0} \ldots \prec _{0} \alpha _2 \prec _{0} \alpha _1$ and set $\omega ^{\alpha _1}a_1+ \ldots +\omega ^{\alpha _n}a_n \prec _{0} \omega ^{\beta _1}b_1+ \ldots +\omega ^{\beta _m}b_m$ , if there exists $i \leq \min\{m,n\}$ such that $\alpha _j=\beta _j$ and $a_j=b_j$ , for any $j \leq i$ and one of the following takes place:

  • $i=n\lt m$ ,

  • $i \lt \min\{m,n\}$ and $\alpha _{i+1} \prec _{0} \beta _{i+1}$

  • $i \lt \min\{m,n\}$ and $\alpha _{i+1} = \beta _{i+1}$ and $a_i \lt b_i$ .

Using some efficient method of sequence encoding, it is possible to arithmetize the set $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ and the predicate $\prec _{0}$ . It is also possible to implement the arithmetization in a way that the length of the Gödel number of $\alpha \in \mathcal{O}_{0}$ is proportional to the number of symbols in the expression $\alpha$ . By this fact, Beckmann et al. (Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003) shows that both $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ and $\prec _{0}$ are polynomial time computable and hence formalizable in $\textrm{PV}$ . (Technically, it uses a conservative extension of $\textrm{PV}$ , but the difference does not affect us here.) We fix quantifier-free predicates $\mathcal{O}_{0}(x)$ and $x \prec _{0} y$ to denote the formalized versions in the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . In Beckmann et al. (Reference Beckmann, Pollett and Buss2003), it is shown that $\textrm{PV}$ proves that $\prec$ is a total ordering on $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ . It is clear that $\textrm{PV}$ also proves that $\textbf{0}$ is the minimum element of $\mathcal{O}_{0}$ . Define $\textbf{1}$ as $\omega ^{\textbf{0}}1$ and for $o$ , consider the function that maps the number $n$ to $\omega ^{\textbf{0}}n$ . Denote $\omega ^{o(1)}$ by $\omega$ . Then, we have $\omega ^{\textbf{0}}=\textbf{1}$ and $\omega ^{\textbf{1}}=\omega$ . The map $o$ is ptime, and it is easy to prove in $\textrm{PV}$ that $o$ is an order-isomorphism, that is, $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall x [\mathcal{O}_{0}(o(x)) \wedge o(x) \prec \omega ]$ , $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \alpha \prec \omega \exists ! y \, o(y)=\alpha$ and $\textrm{PV} \vdash x \lt y \leftrightarrow o(x) \prec _{0} o(y)$ . For $x \mapsto \omega ^x$ , use the evident function mapping the expression $\beta$ to the expression $\omega ^{\beta }$ and note that it is clearly primitive recursive.

In the rest of this subsection, we will explain how to formalize the basic ordinal arithmetic in $\textrm{PV}$ , using the aforementioned representation. For that purpose, first consider the following equalities over the real ordinals below $\varepsilon _0$ . We assumed that the inputs are nonzero as the operations with one zero input are trivial. These equalities make the computation of the addition, multiplication, subtraction from left and division from left possible, using the Cantor normal form of the ordinals. We will not provide a proof for these equalities as they are just simple computations, see Takeuti and Zaring (Reference Takeuti and Zaring1982).

\begin{equation*} { \bigg(\sum _{i=1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i\bigg)+\bigg(\sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j\bigg)= \begin {cases} \sum _{i=1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i+\sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j & \alpha _n \succ \beta _1 \\ \sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j & \alpha _1 \prec \beta _1\\ \sum _{i=1}^{k} \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i+ \sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j & \alpha _{k+1} \prec \beta _1 \prec \alpha _{k}\\ \sum _{i=1}^{k-1} \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i+\omega ^{\alpha _k}(a_k+b_1) +\sum _{j=2}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j & \alpha _{k}=\beta _1 \end {cases} } \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} { \bigg(\sum _{i=1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i\bigg)\dot {-}\bigg(\sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j\bigg)= \begin {cases} 0 & \alpha _{k+1} \prec \beta _{k+1} \\ \sum _{i=k+1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i & \alpha _{k+1} \succ \beta _{k+1}\\ \omega ^{\alpha _{k+1}}(a_{k+1}-b_{k+1})+\sum _{i=k+2}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i & \alpha _{k+1} = \beta _{k+1}, a_{k+1}\gt b_{k+1}\\ 0 & \alpha _{k+1} = \beta _{k+1}, a_{k+1}\lt b_{k+1} \end {cases} } \end{equation*}

where $k$ is the maximum $i$ such that $\alpha _i=\beta _i$ and $a_i=b_i$ , if there is any and otherwise $k=0$ ,

\begin{equation*} { \bigg(\sum _{i=1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i\bigg)\bigg(\sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j\bigg)= \begin {cases} \sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\alpha _1+\beta _j}b_j & \beta _m \succ 0 \\ \sum _{j=1}^{m-1} \omega ^{\alpha _1+\beta _j}b_j+\omega ^{\alpha _1}a_1b_m+\sum _{i=2}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i & \beta _m = 0, m \gt 1\\ \omega ^{\alpha _1}a_1b_1+\sum _{i=2}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i & \beta _m = 0, m=1 \end {cases} } \end{equation*}
\begin{equation*} { d\bigg(\sum _{i=1}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i,\sum _{j=1}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j\bigg)= \begin {cases} 0 & \alpha _1 \prec \beta _1 \\ \sum _{i=1}^k \omega ^{\alpha _i \dot {-} \beta _1}a_i & \alpha _1 \succeq \beta _1, \alpha _{k} \neq \beta _1\\ \sum _{i=1}^{k-1} \omega ^{\alpha _i \dot {-} \beta _1}a_i+d(a_k,b_1) & \alpha _1 \succeq \beta _1, \alpha _{k} = \beta _1, (*)\\ \sum _{i=1}^{k-1} \omega ^{\alpha _i \dot {-} \beta _1}a_i+(d(a_k,b_1)-1) & \text {otherwise} \end {cases} } \end{equation*}

where $k$ is the greatest $i$ such that $\alpha _i \succeq \beta _1$ , $d(a_k,b_1)$ is the quotient of $a_k$ divided by $b_1$ and $(*)$ is the condition that $\sum _{i=k}^n \omega ^{\alpha _i}a_i \succeq \omega ^{\alpha _k}b_1d(a_k,b_1)+\sum _{j=2}^m \omega ^{\beta _j}b_j$ . Note that to compute any of the operations, it is enough to do constant many comparisons and basic numerical computations, a search to find the maximum index that takes at most as long as the length of the inputs and at most $m$ or $n$ many applications of a ptime function. Hence, all the operations are ptime and hence representable in $\textrm{PV}$ . It is easy to see but tedious to show that all the claimed properties in Definition 1 hold. Therefore, the described data in this subsection defines a ptime representation for $\varepsilon _0$ that we denote by $\mathfrak{O}_{0}$ .

4. Ordinal Flows and Arithmetic

Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal and $\mathfrak{O}$ be its ptime representation. In this section, we develop a witnessing method for the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{{O}}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ . The section consists of three parts. First, in Subsection 4.1, we will introduce an auxiliary theory $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ with a transfinite induction on the universal formulas in the language of $\textrm{PV}$ . The system is powerful enough to interpret $\textrm{PRA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}} \textrm{PRWO}({\prec_{\beta}})$ and hence proves all $\Pi ^0_2$ -theorems of $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{{O}}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ . Then in Subsection 4.2, we will provide a witnessing method for $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ that transforms the provability between two universal formulas in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ to an ordinal-length sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications. Finally, in Subsection 4.3, we use Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2, to witness the implications in $\textrm{PV}$ to provide a characterization for the low complexity theorems of $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{{O}}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ .

4.1 The system $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$

This subsection is devoted to the introduction and investigation of the auxiliary theory $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ .

Definition 3. Define $\forall _1$ (resp., $\exists _1$ ) as the least set of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas containing all atomic formulas and their negations and closed under conjunction, disjunction, and universal (resp. existential) quantifiers.

Let $I\forall _1$ (resp. $I\exists _1$ ) be the theory extending $\textrm{PV}$ by the $\forall _1$ -induction (resp. $\exists _1$ -induction) scheme, that is, $A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(x+1)) \to \forall x A(x)$ , for any $A(x) \in \forall _1$ (resp. $A(x) \in \exists _1$ ). Note that $I\exists _1=I\forall _1$ . The proof uses the usual technique of using $\forall _1$ -induction on $B(x)=\neg A(y \dot{-} x)$ to prove $\exists _1$ -induction on $A(y)$ and similarly for the other direction, see Buss (Reference Buss1998).

Lemma 4. For any primitive recursive function $f: \mathbb{N}^k \to \mathbb{N}$ , there is a $\exists _1$ -formula $D_f(\bar{x}, y)$ such that $I\exists _1 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists ! y D_f(\bar{x}, y)$ and $\mathbb{N} \vDash D_f(\bar{n},m)$ iff $f(\bar{n})=m$ , for any $\bar{n}, m \in \mathbb{N}$ .

Proof. For any primitive recursive function $f$ , we provide a quantifier-free formula $C_f(\bar{x}, w, y) \in \mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ encoding that $w$ is a computation of $f$ with the input $\bar{x}$ and the output $y$ . To that aim, we use recursion on the construction of $f$ . The cases for the basic functions and composition are easy. For the recursion case, if $f(\bar{x}, y)$ is defined via recursive equations $f(\bar{x}, 0)=g(\bar{x})$ and $f(\bar{x}, y+1)=h(\bar{x}, y, f(\bar{x}, y))$ , define $C_f(\bar{x}, y, \langle u, v \rangle, z)$ as $C_g(\bar{x}, u_0, v_0) \wedge \forall i \leq l(v) C_h(\bar{x}, i, v_i, u_{i+1}, v_{i+1}) \wedge v_{l(v)}=z$ , where $v$ encodes the sequence $\{f(\bar{x}, i)\}_{i=0}^{l(v)}$ , the number $l(v)$ is the length of this sequence and $u$ encodes the sequence of computations $\{u_{i}\}_{i=0}^{l(v)}$ , where $u_0$ reads $\bar{x}$ and computes $v_0=f(\bar{x}, 0)$ and $u_{i+1}$ reads $\bar{x}$ , $i$ and $f(\bar{x}, i)$ and computes $f(\bar{x}, i+1)$ via the function $h$ . Note that the predicate $\forall i \leq l(v) C_h(\bar{x}, i, v_i, u_i, v_{i+1})$ is polynomial computable, as $l(v) \leq |v|$ , where $|v|$ is the binary length of $v$ . Hence, there exists a polynomial time function symbol in $\textrm{PV}$ like $F$ such that $\textrm{PV}$ proves that $F(\bar{x}, u, v)=1$ iff $\forall i \leq l(v) C_h(\bar{x}, i, v_i, u_i, v_{i+1})$ . Therefore, $C_f$ can be written in a quantifier-free form. Now, set $D_f(\bar{x}, y)=\exists w C_f(\bar{x}, w, y)$ . It is clear that $D_f \in \exists _1$ and $\mathbb{N} \vDash D_f(\bar{n},m)$ iff $f(\bar{n})=m$ , for any $\bar{n}, m \in \mathbb{N}$ . Finally, the proof of the claim that $I\exists _1 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists ! y D_f(\bar{x},y)$ is similar to the similar claim in the representation of primitive recursive functions in $I\Sigma _1$ .

Definition 5. Define the theory $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ over $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ as the theory $\textrm{PV}$ extended by the transfinite induction scheme $\forall \delta (\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma ) \to A(\delta )) \to A(\theta )$ , for any $A(\gamma ) \in \forall _1$ and any constant $\theta \in \mathcal{O}$ .

Note that $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ extends the theory $I\forall _1$ as $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ proves $\forall \delta \prec \omega (\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma ) \to A(\delta )) \to \forall \delta \prec \omega A(\delta )$ , for any $A \in \forall _1$ . Using the function $o$ and the fact that it is an order-isomorphism between the numbers and the ordinals below $\omega$ , we will have $\forall x (\forall y \lt x \; A(y) \to A(x)) \to \forall x A(x)$ which implies $A(0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(x+1)) \to \forall x A(x)$ . Therefore, by Lemma 4, $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ represents any primitive recursive function with an $\exists _1$ -definition. As it is routine in arithmetic (Buss Reference Buss1998), this provides both $\forall _1$ and $\exists _1$ definitions for any atomic formula in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ . Hence, it is possible to interpret any $\forall _1$ -formula in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PRA}}$ as an $\forall _1$ -formula in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . Using that interpretation, we can pretend that $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ has a fresh function symbol for any primitive recursive function and the $\forall _1$ -formulas in the new language are allowed in the transfinite induction. Moreover, we can also pretend that $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ extends the theory $\textrm{PRA}$ . The reason simply is that the equational defining axioms in $\textrm{PRA}$ are all provable in $I\forall _1=I\exists _1$ and hence in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ , as they are actually encoded in the definition $D_f$ of $f$ . For the quantifier-free induction of $\textrm{PRA}$ , as we have seen before, it is possible to use the isomorphism $o$ to prove the induction in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ .

Lemma 6. If $\textrm{PRA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}} \textrm{PRWO}({\prec_{\beta}}) \vdash A$ then $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash A$ , for any $A \in \mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ .

Proof. Pretend $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ has a function symbol for any primitive recursive function, allowed in the $\forall _1$ -formulas. As $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ extends $\textrm{PRA}$ , it is enough to prove $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \textrm{PRWO}({\prec_{\beta}})$ , for any $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ . For the sake of contradiction, assume $\forall y [f(\bar{x}, y+1) \prec f(\bar{x}, y) \wedge \mathcal{O}(f(\bar{x}, y)) \wedge f(\bar{x}, y) \prec \beta ]$ . Set $B(\gamma, \bar{x})= \forall y (f(\bar{x}, y) \neq \gamma )$ and note that $B(\gamma, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ . By transfinite induction, we prove $\forall \gamma \prec \beta \,B(\gamma, \bar{x})$ . For that purpose, assume $\forall \delta \prec \gamma [\delta \prec \beta \to B(\delta, \bar{x})]$ . Then, to prove $[\gamma \prec \beta \to B(\gamma, \bar{x})]$ , if $f(\bar{x}, y) = \gamma$ , for some $\gamma \prec \beta$ , as $f(\bar{x}, y+1) \prec f(\bar{x}, y)$ , we have $f(\bar{x}, y+1) \prec \gamma \prec \beta$ . On the other hand, by $\forall \delta \prec \gamma [\delta \prec \beta \to B(\delta, \bar{x})]$ , we know that none of the ordinals $\delta$ below $\gamma$ is in the form of $f(\bar{x}, z)$ , which contradicts with $f(\bar{x}, y+1) \prec \gamma$ . Hence, $[\gamma \prec \beta \to B(\gamma, \bar{x})]$ . Therefore, $\forall \delta \prec \gamma [\delta \prec \beta \to B(\delta, \bar{x})]$ implies $[\gamma \prec \beta \to B(\gamma, \bar{x})]$ . Hence, by transfinite induction, we have $\forall \gamma \prec \beta \, B(\gamma, \bar{x})$ which for $\gamma =f(\bar{x}, 0) \prec \beta$ implies $\forall y (f(\bar{x}, y) \neq f(\bar{x}, 0))$ which is a contradiction.

Corollary 7. $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \equiv _{\Pi ^0_2} \textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ .

Proof. One direction is a consequence of the fact that $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ proves the transfinite induction for any formulas and hence extends the theory $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ . The other direction is a consequence of Theorem 3 and Lemma 6.

4.1.1 A proof system for $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$

We now present a sequent calculus for the theory $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ . By a sequent over $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ , we mean an expression in the form $S=\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta$ , where $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$ are multisets of formulas in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . Define $\textbf{LPV}$ as the usual system $\textbf{LK}$ augmented with the equality axioms for atomic formulas and their negations and all quantifier-free theorems of $\textrm{PV}$ as the initial sequents:

Axioms:

\begin{align*} \overline{\bot \Rightarrow } \qquad \overline{ \Rightarrow \top } \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \overline{P \Rightarrow P} \qquad \overline{\neg P \Rightarrow \neg P} \qquad \overline{P, \neg P \Rightarrow } \qquad \overline{ \Rightarrow P, \neg P} \qquad \overline{\Rightarrow A} \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \overline{ \Rightarrow t=t} \qquad \overline{s_1=t_1, \ldots, s_n=t_n \Rightarrow f(\bar{s})=f(\bar{t})}\qquad \overline{s_1=t_1, \ldots, s_n=t_n, Q(\bar{s}) \Rightarrow Q(\bar{t})} \end{align*}

where $P$ ranges over all atomic formulas, $f$ ranges over all function symbols in the language, $Q$ ranges over all atmoic formulas or their negations, and $A$ ranges over all quantifier-free theorems of $\textrm{PV}$ .

Structural Rules:

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A, A \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, A \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny Lc} \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A, A, \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow A, \Delta }\,{\tiny Rc} \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, A \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny Lw} \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow A, \Delta }\,{\tiny Rw} \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A, \Delta \qquad \Pi, A \Rightarrow \Lambda }{\Gamma, \Pi \Rightarrow \Delta, \Lambda }\,{\tiny cut} \end{align*}

Logical Rules:

\begin{align*}{\tiny i \in \{0, 1\}}\frac{\Gamma, A_i \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, A_0 \wedge A_1 \Rightarrow \Delta }{\tiny L \wedge } \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A, \Delta \qquad \Gamma \Rightarrow B, \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow A \wedge B, \Delta }\,{\tiny R \wedge } \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A \Rightarrow \Delta \qquad \Gamma, B \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, A \vee B \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny L \vee } \qquad{\tiny i \in \{0, 1\}}\,\frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A_i, \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow A_0 \vee A_1, \Delta }\,{\tiny R \vee } \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A(t) \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, \forall x A(x) \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny L \forall } \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A(y), \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow \forall x A(x), \Delta }\,{\tiny R \forall } \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A(y) \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, \exists x A(x) \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny L \exists } \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A(t), \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow \exists x A(x), \Delta }\,{\tiny R \exists } \end{align*}

In the rules $(R\forall )$ and $(L\exists )$ , the variable $y$ should not appear in the consequence. Adding the rule

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, \forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma ) \Rightarrow \Delta, A(\delta )}{\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta, A(\theta )}\,{\tiny Ind_{\alpha }} \end{align*}

to $\textbf{LPV}$ , we get $\textbf{G}_0$ . Note that in $(Ind_{\alpha })$ , the variable $\delta$ should not appear in the consequence. Moreover, the constant $\theta \in \mathcal{O}$ is arbitrary and can take any value. For more on the proof theory of first-order theories and specially arithmetic, see Buss (Reference Buss1998a,Reference Bussb).

By the usual cut reduction method (Buss Reference Buss1998a,Reference Bussb), it is easy to prove that for any $\Gamma \cup \Delta \subseteq \forall _1$ , if $\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta$ is provable in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ (resp., $\textrm{PV}$ ), then it has a $\textbf{G}_0$ -proof (resp. $\textbf{LPV}$ -proof) consisting only of $\forall _1$ -formulas. For some practical reasons, we simplify the system $\textbf{G}_0$ by changing the cut and the induction rules to the weak cut and weak induction rules, respectively:

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A\qquad A \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny wCut} \qquad \frac{\Gamma, \forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma ) \Rightarrow \forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \; A(\gamma )}{\Gamma \Rightarrow A(\theta )}{\tiny wInd_{\alpha }} \end{align*}

Denote this system by $\textbf{G}_1$ . Note that the difference between $(Ind_{\alpha })$ and $(wInd_{\alpha })$ is that in the latter $\Delta$ is omitted and $A(\delta )$ is replaced by $\forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \; A(\gamma )$ .

Lemma 8. For any $\Gamma \cup \Delta \subseteq \forall _1$ , if $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta$ , then $\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta$ has a $\textbf{G}_1$ -proof only consisting of $\forall _1$ -formulas.

Proof. By a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{G}_1$ (resp. $\textbf{LPV}$ ), we mean a proof in $\textbf{G}_1$ (resp. $\textbf{LPV}$ ) consisting only of $\forall _1$ -formulas. We show that the cut rule and the induction rule (over $\forall _1$ -formulas) are derivable in $\textbf{G}_1$ (by a $\forall _1$ -proof). We only investigate the harder case of $\forall _1$ -proofs. The other is the same omitting the restrictions everywhere.

For cut, consider the following proof-tree in $\textbf{G}_1$ , where the double lines mean simple omitted proofs in $\textbf{G}_1$ . The tree proves $\Gamma, \Sigma \Rightarrow \Lambda, \Delta$ from $\Gamma \Rightarrow A, \Delta$ and $\Sigma, A \Rightarrow \Lambda$ .

Note that the simulation of the cut rule in $\textbf{G}_1$ implies that $\textbf{G}_1$ is as powerful as $\textbf{LPV}$ . It also transforms a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{LPV}$ to a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{G}_1$ . For the induction rule, consider the following proof-tree proving $\Gamma \Rightarrow A(\theta ), \Delta$ from $\Gamma, \forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma ) \Rightarrow A(\delta ), \Delta$ :

where $(*)$ is the result of a cut with the sequent $\forall \gamma \prec \delta \, [A(\gamma ) \vee \bigvee \Delta ] \Rightarrow [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma )] \vee \bigvee \Delta$ which has a proof in $\textbf{LPV}$ and hence a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{LPV}$ and by the observation we have just made, a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{G}_1$ . Note that the use of cut is allowed as we showed its derivability in $\textbf{G}_1$ . Moreover, $(**)$ is the result of a cut with the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable sequent $[A(\delta ) \vee \bigvee \Delta ], \forall \gamma \prec \delta \, [A(\gamma ) \vee \bigvee \Delta ] \Rightarrow \forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \, [A(\gamma ) \vee \bigvee \Delta ]$ . The latter is provable in $\textbf{LPV}$ . Therefore, it has a $\forall _1$ -proof in $\textbf{LPV}$ and hence in $\textbf{G}_1$ . Finally, $\dagger$ is the result of a cut with $ A(\theta ) \vee \bigvee \Delta \Rightarrow A(\theta ), \Delta$ that has a trivial $\forall _1$ -proof.

4.2 Ordinal flows

In this subsection, we will witness $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ -provable implications between $\forall _1$ -formulas by a sequence of $\beta$ many $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications, for some $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ .

Definition 9. Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ . A pair $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ of a $\forall _1$ -formula and $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ such that $\beta \succeq 1$ is called an $\alpha$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ , if:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash A(\bar{x}) \leftrightarrow H(0, \bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar{x})]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(\beta, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow B(\bar{x})$ .

We denote the existence of an $\alpha$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ by $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ . For any multisets $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$ of $\forall _1$ -formulas, by $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ , we mean $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \bigvee \Delta$ .

In order to use $\alpha$ -flows to witness the proofs in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ , we will develop a high-level calculus for this new notion, implemented in the following series of lemmas.

Lemma 10. Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}), C(\bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ . Then:

  1. (i) If $\textrm{PV} \vdash A(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ .

  2. (ii) If $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \circ C(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x}) \circ C(\bar{x})$ , for any $\circ \in \{\wedge, \vee \}$ .

Proof. For $(i)$ , set $\beta =1$ and $H(\gamma, \bar{x})=(\gamma =0 \to A(\bar{x})) \wedge (\gamma =1 \to B(\bar{x}))$ . It is clear that $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow A(\bar{x})$ and $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(1, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow B(\bar{x})$ . As $\textrm{PV} \vdash A(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x})$ , we can see that $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ .

For $(ii)$ , we only prove the conjunction case. The disjunction case is similar. Since $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ , by Definition 9, there exist an ordinal $\beta \succeq 1$ and a formula $H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ satisfying the conditions in Definition 9. Set $I(\gamma, \bar{x})=H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \wedge C(\bar{x})$ and note that $I(\gamma, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ . It is easy to see that the pair $(I(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $A(\bar{x}) \wedge C(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x}) \wedge C(\bar{x})$ , as the $\textrm{PV}$ -provability of $\forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar{x})]$ implies the $\textrm{PV}$ -provability of $\forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; (H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \wedge C(\bar{x})) \rightarrow (H(\delta, \bar{x}) \wedge C(\bar{x}))]$ .

In the next lemma, we glue $\alpha$ -flows together to construct longer $\alpha$ -flows. Notice that the proof heavily uses the fact that the operations $\{+, \dot{-}, \cdot, d\}$ and their basic properties are representable in $\textrm{PV}$ .

Lemma 11.

  1. (i) If $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ and $ B(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } C(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } C(\bar{x})$ .

  2. (ii) If $\Gamma, \forall \gamma \prec \delta \; A(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ , then $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A(\theta, \bar{x})$ , for any $\theta \in \mathcal{O}$ .

Proof. For $(i)$ , as $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\bar{x})$ , there exists an $\alpha$ -flow $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ . Similarly, as $B(\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } C(\bar{x})$ , there is an $\alpha$ -flow $(H'(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta ')$ from $B(\bar{x})$ to $C(\bar{x})$ . Set $\beta ''=\beta +\beta '$ and $H''(\gamma, \bar{x})=[\gamma \preceq \beta \to H(\gamma, \bar{x})] \wedge [\beta \prec \gamma \preceq \beta +\beta ' \to H'(\gamma \dot{-} \beta, \bar{x})]$ . We claim that the pair $(H''(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta '')$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $C(\bar{x})$ . First, note that $H''(0, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $A(\bar{x})$ . Similarly, as $(\beta +\beta ')\dot{-} \beta =\beta '$ is provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , we know that $H''(\beta +\beta ', \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H'(\beta ', \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $C(\bar{x})$ . To prove $ \textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta '' \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H''(\delta, \bar{x})],$ note that if $\delta \preceq \beta$ , then the claim reduces to the same claim for $H(\gamma, \bar{x})$ which is provable. If $\beta \prec \delta \preceq \beta +\beta '$ , assume $\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ to prove $H''(\delta, \bar{x})$ or equivalently $H'(\delta \dot{-} \beta, \bar{x})$ . Note that $\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ implies $\forall \beta \preceq \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ . As the interval $(0, \delta \dot{-} \beta )$ is isomorphic to $(\beta, \delta )$ , by the map $\gamma \mapsto \beta +\gamma$ , then $\forall \beta \preceq \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ implies $\forall 0 \prec \gamma \prec \delta \dot{-} \beta \; H''(\beta +\gamma, \bar{x})$ which implies $\forall 0 \prec \gamma \prec \delta \dot{-} \beta \; H'(\gamma, \bar{x})$ . On the other hand, $\forall \beta \preceq \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ implies $H''(\beta, \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(\beta, \bar{x})$ , by definition. As $H(\beta, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(\bar{x})$ which is also $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H'(0, \bar{x})$ , we can claim that $H(\beta, \bar{x})$ and $H'(0, \bar{x})$ are $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent. Hence, $\forall \beta \preceq \gamma \prec \delta \; H''(\gamma, \bar{x})$ implies $\forall \gamma \prec \delta \dot{-} \beta \; H'(\gamma, \bar{x})$ which also implies $H'(\delta \dot{-} \beta, \bar{x})$ , as $(H'(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta ')$ is an $\alpha$ -flow.

For $(ii)$ , as $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \delta \, A(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ , by Lemma 10, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \delta \, A(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \delta +1 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ . Set $B(\delta, \bar{x})=\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \delta \, A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ . Therefore, $B(\delta, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\delta +1, \bar{x})$ . Let $(H(\eta, \delta, \bar{x}), \beta )$ be the $\alpha$ -flow from $B(\delta, \bar{x})$ to $B(\delta +1, \bar{x})$ . Note that $H(0, \delta, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(\delta,\bar{x})$ and $H(\beta, \delta, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, \delta +1, \bar{x})$ , as both are $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(\delta +1)$ . Define $\beta '=\beta (\theta +1)$ and $I(\tau, \bar{x})=H(\tau \dot{-} \beta d(\tau, \beta ), d(\tau, \beta ), \bar{x})$ and note that $I(\tau, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ . We show that $(I(\tau, \bar{x}), \beta ')$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $B(0, \bar{x})$ to $B(\theta +1, \bar{x})$ . Note that $(I(\tau, \bar{x}), \beta ')$ is nothing but the result of gluing the $\alpha$ -flows $(H(\eta, \delta, \bar{x}), \beta )$ , for all $\delta \prec \theta +1$ , one after another as depicted in the following figure (for simplicity, in the figures, we drop the free variables $\bar{x}$ ).

First, as $d(0,\beta )=0$ and $0 \dot{-} \beta d(0,\beta )=0$ , provably in $\textrm{PV}$ , we know that $I(0, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, 0, \bar{x})$ which is itself $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(0, \bar{x})$ . Second, as $d(\beta (\theta +1), \beta )=\theta +1$ and $\beta (\theta +1) \dot{-} \beta d(\beta (\theta +1), \beta )=0$ , provably in $\textrm{PV}$ , we know that $I(\beta (\theta +1), \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, \theta +1, \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(\theta +1, \bar{x})$ . For the middle condition, we must prove $ \textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \tau \preceq \beta (\theta +1) \; [\forall \zeta \prec \tau \; I(\zeta, \bar{x}) \rightarrow I(\tau, \bar{x})]$ . There are two cases to consider, either $\beta d(\tau, \beta ) \prec \tau$ or $\beta d(\tau, \beta )= \tau$ . If $\beta d(\tau, \beta ) \prec \tau$ , then $\beta d(\tau, \beta )+1 \preceq \tau$ which implies $\tau =\beta d(\tau, \beta )+\mu$ for $\mu =\tau \dot{-} \beta d(\tau, \beta ) \succeq 1$ . As for any $\eta \prec \mu$ , we have $\beta d(\tau, \beta ) + \eta \prec \tau$ , we know that $\forall \zeta \prec \tau \; I(\zeta, \bar{x})$ implies $\forall \eta \prec \mu \; H(\eta, d(\tau, \beta ), \bar{x})$ . As we have $\mu \succeq 1$ , the latter proves $H(\mu, d(\tau, \beta ), \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $I(\tau, \bar{x})$ .

For the other case, if $\beta d(\tau, \beta )=\tau$ , we should use $\forall \zeta \prec \tau \; I(\zeta, \bar{x})$ to prove the formula $I(\tau, \bar{x})=H(0, d(\tau, \beta ), \bar{x})$ . Again, there are two cases to consider: either $d(\tau, \beta )$ is a successor or a limit ordinal. If $d(\tau, \beta )=\rho +1$ , for some $\rho$ , as $H(0, \rho +1, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(\beta, \rho, \bar{x})$ , it is enough to prove $H(\beta, \rho, \bar{x})$ . As $\beta \rho +\eta \prec \beta \rho +\beta =\beta (\rho +1)=\tau$ , for any $\eta \prec \beta$ , we know that $\forall \zeta \prec \tau \, I(\zeta, \bar{x})$ implies $\forall \eta \prec \beta \, H(\eta, \rho, \bar{x})$ which implies $H(\beta, \rho, \bar{x})$ .

If $d(\tau, \beta )$ is a limit ordinal, then $\forall \zeta \prec \beta d(\tau, \beta ) \, I(\zeta, \bar{x})$ implies the formula $\forall \delta \prec d(\tau, \beta ) \, H(0, \delta, \bar{x})$ which implies $\forall \delta \prec d(\tau, \beta ) B(\delta, \bar{x})$ . The latter is $\forall \delta \prec d(\tau, \beta ) [\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \delta \, A(\gamma, \bar{x})]$ that implies $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec d(\tau, \beta ) \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ , as $d(\tau, \beta )$ is a limit ordinal. The latter is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, d(\tau, \beta ), \bar{x})=I(\tau, \bar{x})$ . This completes the proof of the claim and shows that $B(0, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } B(\theta +1, \bar{x})$ . Now, as $\textrm{PV} \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma \to (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec 0 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x}))$ and $\textrm{PV} \vdash (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \theta +1 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})) \to A(\theta, \bar{x})$ , by Lemma 10, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec 0 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x})$ and $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge \forall \gamma \prec \theta +1 \; A(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } A(\theta, \bar{x})$ . Hence, by part $(i)$ , we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A(\theta, \bar{x})$ which completes the proof.

Lemma 12. (Conjunction and Disjunction Rules)

  1. (i) If $\Gamma, A \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ or $\Gamma, B \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ , then $\Gamma, A \wedge B \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ .

  2. (ii) If $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A, \Delta$ and $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } B, \Delta$ , then $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A \wedge B, \Delta$ .

  3. (iii) If $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A, \Delta$ or $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } B, \Delta$ , then $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } A \vee B, \Delta$ .

  4. (iv) If $\Gamma, A \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ and $\Gamma, B \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ , then $\Gamma, A \vee B \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta$ .

Proof. For $(i)$ and $(iii)$ , as the implications $[(\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge (A \wedge B)) \to (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge A)]$ , $[(\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge (A \wedge B)) \to (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge B)]$ , $[(\bigvee \Delta \vee A) \to (\bigvee \Delta \vee (A \vee B))]$ and $[(\bigvee \Delta \vee B) \to (\bigvee \Delta \vee (A \vee B))]$ are all provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , using Lemmas 10 and 11, we reach what we wanted. For $(ii)$ , if $\Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta, A$ then $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \bigvee \Delta \vee A$ , by definition. By Lemma 10, we reach $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } (\bigvee \Delta \vee A) \wedge \bigwedge \Gamma$ . Similarly, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \bigvee \Delta \vee B$ and by Lemma 10, we reach $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge (\bigvee \Delta \vee A) \rhd _{\alpha } (\bigvee \Delta \vee B) \wedge (\bigvee \Delta \vee A)$ . Therefore, $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } (\bigvee \Delta \vee B) \wedge (\bigvee \Delta \vee A)$ , by part $(i)$ in Lemma 11. Finally, as $(\bigvee \Delta \vee B) \wedge (\bigvee \Delta \vee A) \to \bigvee \Delta \vee (A \wedge B)$ is provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , by Lemmas 10 and 11, we reach $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _{\alpha } \bigvee \Delta \vee (A \wedge B)$ . The proof for $(iv)$ is similar.

Having the required lemmas, we are now ready to prove the following theorem as the main extraction technique that witnesses the proofs in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ by $\alpha$ -flows.

Theorem. Let $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \cup \Delta (\bar{x}) \subseteq \forall _1$ . Then, $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ iff $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta (\bar{x})$ .

Proof. We first prove the easier direction. Assume $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta (\bar{x})$ and the pair $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x})$ to $\bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ . As $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar{x})]$ and $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ extends $\textrm{PV}$ , we have

\begin{equation*} \textrm {TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar {x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar {x})]. \end{equation*}

Then, as $H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ , by the transfinite induction in $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec )$ , we reach $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\beta, \bar{x})$ . Finally, using the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable equivalences $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \leftrightarrow H(0, \bar{x})$ and $H(\beta, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ , we reach $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ .

For the other direction, assume $\textrm{TI}(\forall _1, \prec ) \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ . By Lemma 8, $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \Rightarrow \Delta (\bar{x})$ has a $\textbf{G}_1$ -proof only consisting of $\forall _1$ -formulas. By induction on this proof, we show that for any sequent $\Sigma \Rightarrow \Lambda$ in the proof, we have $\Sigma \rhd _{\alpha } \Lambda$ .

For the axioms, as they are provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , using Lemma 10, there is nothing to prove. The case of structural rules (except for the weak cut) is easy. Weak cut and weak induction are addressed in Lemma 11. The conjunction and disjunction rules are proved in Lemma 12. For the right universal quantifier rule, if $\Sigma (\bar{x}) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x}), \forall z B(\bar{x}, z)$ is proved from $\Sigma (\bar{x}) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, z)$ , then by induction hypothesis, $\Sigma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \Lambda (\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, z)$ . Therefore, there exists an $\alpha$ -flow $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}, z), \beta )$ from $\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x}, z) \vee \bigvee \Lambda (\bar{x})$ . Define $I(\gamma, \bar{x})=\forall z H(\gamma, \bar{x}, z)$ and note that $I(\bar{x}, z) \in \forall _1$ . It is easy to see that $(I(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $\forall z [\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x})]$ to $\forall z [B(\bar{x}, z) \vee \bigvee \Lambda (\bar{x})]$ , as $\textrm{PV}$ -provability of $\forall \gamma \prec \delta H(\gamma, z, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, z, \bar{x})$ implies the $\textrm{PV}$ -provability of $\forall \gamma \prec \delta \forall z H(\gamma, z, \bar{x}) \rightarrow \forall z H(\delta, z, \bar{x})$ . Finally, as $z$ does not occur as a free variable in $\Sigma (\bar{x}) \cup \Lambda (\bar{x})$ , we have the $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalence between $\forall z [\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x})]$ and $\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x})$ and similarly between $\forall z [B(\bar{x}, z) \vee \bigvee \Lambda (\bar{x})]$ and $\bigvee \Lambda (\bar{x}) \vee \forall z B(\bar{x}, z)$ . Using Lemmas 10 and 11, we can prove $\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \bigvee \Lambda (\bar{x}) \vee \forall z B(\bar{x}, z)$ . For the left universal quantifier rule, if $\Sigma (\bar{x}), \forall z B(\bar{x}, z) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x})$ is proved from $\Sigma (\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x})) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x})$ , then by induction hypothesis $ \Sigma (\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x})) \rhd _{\alpha } \Lambda (\bar{x})$ . Since $\textrm{PV} \vdash \bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x}) \wedge \forall z B(\bar{x}, z) \rightarrow \bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x}) \wedge B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x}))$ , by Lemmas 10 and 11, we reach $\Sigma (\bar{x}), \forall z B(\bar{x}, z) \rhd _{\alpha } \Lambda (\bar{x})$ .

Corollary 13. Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal with the ptime representation $\mathfrak{O}$ . Then, $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}(\prec _\beta ) \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ iff $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\alpha } \Delta (\bar{x})$ , for $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \cup \Delta (\bar{x}) \subseteq \forall _1$ .

Proof. As any implication in the form $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ is logically equivalent to a $\Pi ^0_2$ -formula, the claim is a consequence of Theorem 4 and Corollary 7.

Corollary 14. Let $\mathfrak{O}_{0}$ be the ptime representation for $\varepsilon _0$ introduced in Subsection 3.1 . Then, $\textrm{PA} \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ iff $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd _{\varepsilon _0} \Delta (\bar{x})$ , for $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \cup \Delta (\bar{x}) \subseteq \forall _1$ .

4.3 Ordinal local search programs

In this subsection, we will first introduce the notion of an ordinal local search program as a formalized version of the transfinite ptime modifications over an initial ptime value that we explained before. We will then use these programs to witness some provable statements in the theory $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ .

Definition 15. Let $T$ be a theory over the language $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ . A total search problem of $T$ is a quantifier-free formula $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ such that $T \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists \bar{y} A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ . A total search problem is called an $\textrm{NP}$ -search problem, if there are sequences of polynomials $\bar{r}$ such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \to |\bar{y}| \leq \bar{r}(|\bar{x}|)$ , where $|\bar{y}| \leq \bar{r}(|\bar{x}|)$ is an abbreviation for $\bigwedge _i (|y_i| \leq r_i(|\bar{x}|))$ . We denote the class of all these total search (resp., $\textrm{NP}$ -search) problems of $T$ by $\textrm{TSP}(T)$ (resp. $\textrm{TFNP}(T)$ ).

Definition 16. Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal, $\mathfrak{O}$ be its ptime representation, $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ be a quantifier-free formula in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ and $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ . By an $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -program for $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ , we mean the following data: an initial sequence of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms $\bar{i}(\bar{x})$ , a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula $G(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , a sequence of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms $\bar{N}(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $q(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , a sequence of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms $\bar{p}(\bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , such that:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash G(\beta, \bar{x}, \bar{i}(\bar{x}))$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \gamma \neq 0 \to q(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \prec \gamma$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \gamma \neq 0 \to [G(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \to G(q(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}), \bar{x}, \bar{N}(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}))]$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash G(0, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \to A(\bar{x}, \bar{p}(\bar{x}, \bar{z}))$ .

By $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ , we mean the class of all formulas $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ for which there exists a $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -program. By $\textrm{PLS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ , we mean the class $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta }) \cap \textrm{TFNP}(Th(\mathbb{N}))$ .

Membership $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \in \textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ implies $\forall \bar{x} \exists \bar{y}A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ and the $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -program actually provides an algorithm to compute $\bar{y}$ from $\bar{x}$ . To see this, denote $G(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ by $G_{\gamma }$ . The algorithm starts at the level $\beta$ with an initial value $\bar{i}(\bar{x})$ satisfying the property $G_{\beta }$ . Then, using the feasible function $q$ , it finds a lower level to go to and uses the modification $\bar{N}$ to update any value with the property $G_{\gamma }$ to a value satisfying the property $G_{q(\gamma )}$ . Finally, reaching the zeroth level, the algorithm uses $\bar{p}$ to compute $\bar{y}$ satisfying $A$ from any value with the property $G_0$ .

The next theorem uses $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -programs ( $\textrm{PLS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -programs) to witness the total search ( $\textrm{NP}$ -search) problems of $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}})$ . The idea is using Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2, applied on $\textrm{PV}$ to push the data extraction of Corollary 13 a bit further to reach an ordinal local search program for total search problems.

Theorem. Let $\alpha$ be an ordinal with the ptime representation $\mathfrak{O}$ . Then $\textrm{TSP}(\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}))= \bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}} \textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ and $\textrm{TFNP}(\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}))= \bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}} \textrm{PLS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ .

Proof. We only prove the first equality. The second is just a consequence. For the first direction, assume that $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ has a $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -program. Set $H(\gamma, \bar{x})=\forall \bar{z} \neg G(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \wedge \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ and note that $H \in \forall _1$ . We claim that $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $\forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ to $\bot$ . First, as $\textrm{PV} \vdash G(0, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \to A(\bar{x}, \bar{p}(\bar{x}, \bar{z}))$ , we have $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \to \forall \bar{z} \neg G(0, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ and hence $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \leftrightarrow H(0, \bar{x})$ . Second, as $\textrm{PV} \vdash G(\beta, \bar{x}, \bar{i}(\bar{x}))$ , we reach $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \bar{z} \neg G(\beta, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \leftrightarrow \bot$ and hence $\textrm{PV} \vdash \bot \leftrightarrow H(\beta, \bar{x})$ . Finally, using $\textrm{PV} \vdash \gamma \neq 0 \to q(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \prec \gamma$ , and

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \gamma \neq 0 \to [G(\gamma, \bar {x}, \bar {z}) \to G(q(\gamma, \bar {x}, \bar {z}), \bar {x}, \bar {N}(\gamma, \bar {x}, \bar {z}))], \end{equation*}

it is easy to see that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\neg G(q(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z}), \bar {x}, \bar {N}(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z})) \rightarrow \neg G(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z})] \end{equation*}

and hence we reach

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; \forall \bar {z} \neg G(\gamma, \bar {x}, \bar {z}) \rightarrow \forall \bar {z} \neg G(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z})]. \end{equation*}

The latter implies $ \textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar{x})]$ . Therefore, $(H(\gamma, \bar{x}), \beta )$ is an $\alpha$ -flow from $\forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ to $\bot$ . Hence, $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \vdash \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \to \bot$ , by Corollary 13 and thus, we reach $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists \bar{y} \, A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ . For the converse, assume that $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists \bar{y} A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ , where $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \in \mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ is quantifier-free. As $\textrm{PA}+\bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}}\textrm{TI}({\prec_{\beta}}) \vdash \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \to \bot$ , by Corollary 13, $\forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \rhd _{\alpha } \bot$ . Hence, there exist $H(\gamma, \bar{x}) \in \forall _1$ and $\beta \in \mathcal{O}$ such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall \bar{y} \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y}) \leftrightarrow H(0, \bar{x})$ , $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(\beta, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow \bot$ and

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \forall \; 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [\forall \gamma \prec \delta \; H(\gamma, \bar {x}) \rightarrow H(\delta, \bar {x})]. \end{equation*}

As $H \in \forall _1$ , there exists a quantifier-free formula $I(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ such that $H(\gamma, \bar{x})$ and $\forall \bar{z} I(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ are equivalent over $\textrm{PV}$ . On the other hand, as the implications are provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , we can witness the existential quantifiers by ptime functions. Hence, there are $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms $\bar{Y}(\bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , $\bar{Z}(\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , $\Delta (\gamma, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ , and $\bar{W}(\bar{x})$ such that

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{Y}(\bar{x}, \bar{z})) \rightarrow I(0, \bar{x}, \bar{z})$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash I(\beta, \bar{x}, \bar{W}(\bar{x})) \rightarrow \bot$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall 1 \preceq \delta \preceq \beta \; [[(\Delta (\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \prec \delta \rightarrow I(\Delta (\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z}), \bar{x}, \bar{Z}(\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z}))] \rightarrow I(\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z})]$ .

Define $G(\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z})=\neg I(\delta, \bar{x}, \bar{z}) \wedge (\delta \preceq \beta )$ ,

\begin{equation*} q(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z})= \begin {cases} \Delta (\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z}) & \neg I(\delta, \bar {x}, \bar {z}) \wedge (\delta \preceq \beta ) \\ 0 & \text {otherwise} \end {cases} \end{equation*}

$\bar{i}(\bar{x})= \bar{W}(\bar{x})$ and $\bar{p}(\bar{x}, \bar{z})=\bar{Y}(\bar{x}, \bar{z})$ . It is easy to see that this new data is an $\textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ -program for $A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})$ .

Applying Theorem 5 to $\alpha =\varepsilon _0$ , we reach the following Corollary, originally proved in Beckmann (Reference Beckmann2009).

Corollary 17. Let $\mathfrak{O}_{0}$ be the ptime representation of the ordinal $\varepsilon _0$ introduced in Subsection 3.1 . Then $\textrm{TSP}(\textrm{PA})= \bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}_{0}} \textrm{LS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ and $\textrm{TFNP}(\textrm{PA})= \bigcup _{\beta \in \mathcal{O}_{0}} \textrm{PLS}(\preceq _{\beta })$ .

5. $k$ -Flows and Bounded Arithmetic

In this section, we will modify the method developed for the strong theories of arithmetic in Section 4 to also cover the bounded and hence weaker theories of arithmetic. The structure of the present section is similar to that of Section 4. After recalling the usual sequent calculi for the theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ in Subsection 5.1, the next subsection, Subsection 5.2 will be devoted to investigate a suitable version of a flow for bounded arithmetic called a $k$ -flow. Roughly speaking, a $k$ -flow is an exponentially long uniform sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas in the class $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . After proving some basic properties of $k$ -flows, we will conclude the subsection by proving a witnessing theorem, transforming the proofs of the implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas in $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ to some types of $k$ -flows. Finally, in Subsection 5.3, we will introduce the appropriate notion of a local search program to witness the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications further and find a complete witnessing for the theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ .

5.1 Sequent calculi for bounded arithmetic

To recall the usual sequent calculi for $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ , introduced in Buss (Reference Buss1986), first consider the following rules:

Bounded Quantifier Rules:

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A(s) \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, s \leq t, \forall y \leq t \; A(y) \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny L\forall ^{\leq }} \qquad \frac{\Gamma, z \leq t \Rightarrow A(z), \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow \forall y \leq t \; A(y), \Delta }\,{\tiny R\forall ^{\leq }} \end{align*}
\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, z \leq t, A(z) \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma, \exists y \leq t \; A(y) \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny L\exists ^{\leq } } \qquad \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A(s), \Delta }{\Gamma, s \leq t, \Rightarrow \exists y \leq t \; A(y), \Delta }\,{\tiny R\exists ^{\leq }} \end{align*}

Induction Rules:

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma, A(\lfloor \frac{z}{2} \rfloor ) \Rightarrow A(z), \Delta }{\Gamma, A(0) \Rightarrow A(t), \Delta }\,{\tiny \textrm{PInd}_k} \qquad \frac{\Gamma, A(z) \Rightarrow A(z+1), \Delta }{\Gamma, A(0) \Rightarrow A(t), \Delta }\,{\tiny \textrm{Ind}_k} \end{align*}

In the rules $(R\forall ^{\leq })$ and $(L\exists ^{\leq })$ as well as in the induction rules, the variable $z$ should not appear in the consequence of the rule. Moreover, in the induction rules $(\textrm{PInd}_k)$ and $(\textrm{Ind}_k)$ , the index $k$ means that the formula $A(z)$ is restricted to the class $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ .

The system $\textbf{LS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{LT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) for $S^k_2$ (resp. $T^k_2$ ) is defined as the system $\textbf{LPV}$ plus the bounded quantifier rules and the rule $(\textrm{PInd}_k)$ (resp. $(\textrm{Ind}_k)$ ). For some technical reasons, we prefer to work with the alternative systems where the cut and the induction rules are weakened. Define the system $\textbf{wLS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{wLT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) similar to $\textbf{LS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{LT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) with the difference that in the former the quantifier rules in $\textbf{LPV}$ are omitted and the cut and the induction rule $(\textrm{PInd}_k)$ (resp. $(\textrm{Ind}_k)$ ) are replaced by the weak cut and the weak induction rule $(\textrm{wPInd}_k)$ (resp. $(\textrm{wInd}_k)$ ) depicted below:

\begin{align*} \frac{\Gamma \Rightarrow A \qquad A \Rightarrow \Delta }{\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta }\,{\tiny wCut} \qquad \frac{\Gamma, A(\lfloor \frac{z}{2}\rfloor ) \Rightarrow A(z)}{\Gamma, A(0) \Rightarrow A(s)}\,{\tiny \textrm{wPInd}_k} \qquad \frac{\Gamma, A(z) \Rightarrow A(z+1)}{\Gamma, A(0) \Rightarrow A(s)}\,{\tiny \textrm{wInd}_k} \end{align*}

In the weak induction rules, we have the similar constraints as before, namely that $A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $z$ does not appear in the consequence of the rules. Note that the only point modified in the weak induction rules is the missing context $\Delta$ .

The following theorem ensures that the system $\textbf{wLS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{wLT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) is complete for the sequents of $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas. Notice that the lemma does not claim the full completeness as the system $\textbf{wLS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{wLT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) is clearly weak to introduce any unbounded quantifier.

Lemma 18. For any $\Gamma \cup \Delta \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ :

  • If $S^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta$ , then $\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta$ has a $\textbf{wLS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ -proof only consisting of $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas.

  • If $T^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta$ , then $\Gamma \Rightarrow \Delta$ has a $\textbf{wLT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ -proof only consisting of $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas.

Proof. It is a well-known consequence of the cut reduction theorem for $\textbf{LS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{LT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) that if $\bigwedge \Gamma \to \bigvee \Delta$ is provable in $S^k_2$ (resp. $T^k_2$ ), it has a proof in $\textbf{LS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ (resp. $\textbf{LT}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ ) only consisting of $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas and only using bounded quantifier rules instead of the usual unbounded quantifier rules in $\textbf{LPV}$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). Therefore, the only thing remained to prove is simulating the cut and the induction rules over $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas by their weak versions applied over the same family of formulas. This simulation is almost identical to the one presented in the proof of Lemma 8 and hence will be skipped here.

5.2 $k$ -flows

In this subsection, we will first introduce a $k$ -flow as a uniform term-length sequence of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas. Then, we will develop a high-level calculus for $k$ -flows to witness the provability in theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ .

Definition 19. Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ be two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas and $t(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term. A $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ with the length $t(\bar{x})$ is a pair $(H(u, \bar{x}), t(\bar{x}))$ , where $H(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow A(\bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(t(\bar{x}), \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow B(\bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall u \lt t(\bar{x}) \; [H(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(u+1, \bar{x})]$ .

A $k$ -flow is called polynomial if $t(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ , where by equality, we mean the syntactical equality between the terms. If there exists a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ with the length $t(\bar{x})$ , we write $A(\bar{x}) \rhd ^{t(\bar{x})}_{k} B(\bar{x})$ . If we intend to emphasize on the existence of the $k$ -flow regardless of its length, we write $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k B(\bar{x})$ and if the $k$ -flow is polynomial $A(\bar{x}) \rhd ^p_{k} B(\bar{x})$ . Moreover, if $\Gamma \cup \Delta \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ , by $\Gamma \rhd _k \Delta$ (resp. $\Gamma \rhd ^p_k \Delta$ ), we mean $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _k \bigvee \Delta$ (resp. $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd ^p_k \bigvee \Delta$ ).

Similar to the situation with the ordinal flows, it is also reasonable to provide a high-level calculus to work with the $k$ -flows. The following series of lemmas realize this goal.

Lemma 20. (Padding) Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $t(\bar{x}), s(\bar{x})$ be two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash t(\bar{x}) \leq s(\bar{x})$ . If $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k^{t(\bar{x})} B(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k^{s(\bar{x})} B(\bar{x})$ . Therefore, without loss of generality, we can always assume that the length $t(\bar{x})$ of a $k$ -flow is $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone, that is, $\textrm{PV} \vdash \bigwedge _{i=1}^n (x_i \leq y_i) \to t(\bar{x}) \leq t(\bar{y})$ .

Proof. Let $(H(u, \bar{x}),t(\bar{x}))$ be a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ . Then, define

\begin{equation*} H'(u, \bar {x})= \begin {cases} H(u, \bar {x}) & u \leq t(\bar {x})\\ B(\bar {x}) & u \gt t(\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

Notice that $H'(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . It is easy to prove that $(H'(u, \bar{x}), s(\bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ . The only thing worth emphasizing is the role of the assumption $\textrm{PV} \vdash t(\bar{x}) \leq s(\bar{x})$ in the proof. This assumption together with the definition of $H'(u, \bar{x})$ shows $\textrm{PV} \vdash H'(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow B(\bar{x})$ which is one of the conditions of being a $k$ -flow. This observation completes the proof of the first part of the claim. For its second part, note that for any term $t(\bar{x})$ , there exists a polynomial $q$ such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash t(\bar{x}) \leq 2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). As $2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone, it is enough to use the first part to extend a $k$ -flow with the length $t(\bar{x})$ to a $k$ -flow with the length $2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}$ . For polynomial $k$ -flows, as the length $t(\bar{x})$ is in the form $q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ , it is already $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone and hence there is nothing to prove.

Lemma 21. Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}), C(\bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Then:

  1. (i) If $\textrm{PV} \vdash A(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k B(\bar{x})$ .

  2. (ii) If $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k B(\bar{x})$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \circ C(\bar{x}) \rhd _k B(\bar{x}) \circ C(\bar{x})$ , for any $\circ \in \{\wedge, \vee \}$ . A similar claim also holds for $\rhd ^p_k$ .

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Lemma 10.

Lemma 22. (Bounded variables) Let $A(\bar{x}, y), B(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ be two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas and $s(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term (not depending on $y$ ). If $A(\bar{x}, y) \rhd _k B(\bar{x}, y)$ , then there exists a formula $I(u, y, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $r(\bar{x})$ (not depending on $y$ ) such that:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash I(0, y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow A(\bar{x}, y)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) [I(r(\bar{x}), y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow B(\bar{x}, y)]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash I(u, y, \bar{x}) \rightarrow I(u+1, y, \bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash r(\bar{x}) \geq 1$ .

If we also have $A(\bar{x}, y) \rhd ^p_k B(\bar{x}, y)$ , then the term $r(\bar{x})$ can be chosen in the form $q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ .

Proof. Assume $(H(u, y, \bar{x}), t(y, \bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x}, y)$ to $B(\bar{x}, y)$ . Using Lemma 20, we can assume that $t(y, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone and $\textrm{PV} \vdash t(y, \bar{x}) \geq 1$ . Define

\begin{equation*} I(u, y, \bar {x})= \begin {cases} H(u, y, \bar {x}) & u \leq t(y, \bar {x})\\ B(y, \bar {x}) & u \gt t(y,\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

and notice that $I(u, y, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Recall from the basic facts in bounded arithmetic that for the term $s(\bar{x})$ , there is a polynomial $q_s$ such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash |s(\bar{x})| \leq q_s(|\bar{x}|)$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). Define $r(\bar{x})=t(2^{q_s(|\bar{x}|)}, \bar{x})$ and note that $\textrm{PV} \vdash y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to t(y, \bar{x}) \leq r(\bar{x})$ , as $t(y, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone and $\textrm{PV} \vdash r(\bar{x}) \geq 1$ . We claim that $I(u, y, \bar{x})$ and $r(\bar{x})$ work. The first and the third claims in the statement of the lemma are the trivial consequences of the fact that $(H(u, y, \bar{x}), t(y, \bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x}, y)$ to $B(\bar{x}, y)$ . For the second, notice that as $\textrm{PV} \vdash y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to t(y, \bar{x}) \leq r(\bar{x})$ , we can use the definition of $I(y, \bar{x})$ to see that the formula $I(r(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(y, \bar{x})$ .

For the polynomial case, if $(H(u, y, \bar{x}), t(y, \bar{x}))$ is a polynomial $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x}, y)$ to $B(\bar{x}, y)$ , then there is a polynomial $q_t$ such that $t(y, \bar{x})=q_t(|y|, |\bar{x}|)$ . Therefore, $r(\bar{x})=q_t(q_s(|x|)+1, |\bar{x}|)$ which implies that $r(\bar{x})$ is in the form $q_r(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some poynomial $q_r$ .

Lemma 23. Let $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \cup \{A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}), C(\bar{x}), D(y, \bar{x})\} \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Then:

  1. (i) (weak gluing) If $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k B(\bar{x})$ and $ B(\bar{x}) \rhd _k C(\bar{x})$ then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k C(\bar{x})$ . A similar claim also holds for $\rhd ^p_k$ .

  2. (ii) (polynomial strong gluing) If $\Gamma (\bar{x}), D(\lfloor \frac{y}{2}\rfloor, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k D(y, \bar{x})$ , then we have $\Gamma (\bar{x}), D(0, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ , for any $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $s(\bar{x})$ .

  3. (iii) (strong gluing) If $ \Gamma (\bar{x}), D(y, \bar{x}) \rhd _k D(y+1, \bar{x})$ , then $\Gamma (\bar{x}), D(0, \bar{x}) \rhd _k D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ , for any $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $s(\bar{x})$ .

Proof. For $(i)$ , as $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k B(\bar{x})$ and $ B(\bar{x}) \rhd _k C(\bar{x})$ , there exist $k$ -flows $(H(u, \bar{x}), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H'(u, \bar{x}), t'(\bar{x}))$ , from $A(\bar{x})$ to $B(\bar{x})$ and from $B(\bar{x})$ to $C(\bar{x})$ , respectively. Set $t''(\bar{x})=t(\bar{x})+t'(\bar{x})+1$ and

\begin{equation*} H''(u, \bar {x})= \begin {cases} H(u, \bar {x}) & u \leq t(\bar {x})\\ H'(u \dot {-} (t(\bar {x}) + 1), \bar {x}) & u \gt t(\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

Notice that $H''(u, \bar{x})$ is clearly a $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formula. We claim that $(H''(u, \bar{x}), t''(\bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $C(\bar{x})$ as depicted in the following figure (for simplicity, in the figure, we sometimes drop the free variables $\bar{x}$ ):

First, it is trivial that $H''(0, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(0, \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $A(\bar{x})$ . Similarly, $H''(t''(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H'(t'(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $C(\bar{x})$ . To prove $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall u \lt t''(\bar{x}) \; [H''(u, \bar{x}) \to H''(u+1, \bar{x})]$ , the cases $u \lt t(\bar{x})$ and $t(\bar{x}) \lt u \lt t''(\bar{x})$ are reduced to a similar claim for $H$ and $H'$ . For $u=t(\bar{x})$ , note that $H''(t(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H(t(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ and $H''(t(\bar{x})+1, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H'(0, \bar{x})$ . As both formulas are $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $B(\bar{x})$ , the proof is complete. Finally, note that if the $k$ -flows $(H(u, \bar{x}), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H'(u, \bar{x}), t'(\bar{x}))$ are polynomial, there are polynomials $q$ and $q'$ such that $t(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)$ and $t'(\bar{x})=q'(|\bar{x}|)$ . Hence, $t''(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)+q'(|\bar{x}|)+1$ . Therefore, the $k$ -flow $(H''(u, \bar{x}), t''(\bar{x}))$ is also polynomial.

For $(ii)$ , as $\Gamma (\bar{x}), D(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k D(y, \bar{x})$ , by Lemma 21, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k \bigwedge \Gamma \wedge D(y, \bar{x})$ . For simplicity, denote $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(y, \bar{x})$ by $E(y, \bar{x})$ . Therefore, we have $E(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k E(y, \bar{x})$ . First, we want to prove $E(0, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k E(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ . Roughly speaking, the idea is gluing the polynomial $k$ -flows from $E(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x})$ to $E(y, \bar{x})$ , one after another, starting from $y=s(\bar{x})$ till reaching $E(0, \bar{x})$ :

Notice that the result of this gluing extends the length of the $k$ -flow by $|s(\bar{x})|$ which is bounded by a polynomial and hence acceptable. More formally, using Lemma 22 for the formulas $E(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x})$ and $E(y, \bar{x})$ and the term $2s(\bar{x})$ (the choice of $2s(\bar{x})$ instead of $s(\bar{x})$ is rather technical) and using the fact that $E(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k E(y, \bar{x})$ , we reach a pair $(H'(u, y, \bar{x}), t'(\bar{x}))$ such that:

  1. (1) $\textrm{PV} \vdash H'(0, y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow E(\lfloor \frac{y}{2} \rfloor,\bar{x})$ ,

  2. (2) $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall y \leq 2s(\bar{x}) [H'(t'(\bar{x}), y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow E(y, \bar{x})]$ ,

  3. (3) $\textrm{PV} \vdash H'(u, y, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H'(u+1, y, \bar{x})$ ,

  4. (4) $\textrm{PV} \vdash t'(\bar{x}) \geq 1$ ,

and $t'(\bar{x})=q_{t'}(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q_{t'}$ . Define the function $Y(z, \bar{x})$ as the result of $|s(\bar{x})|+1\dot{-} z$ many iterations of the operation $n \mapsto \lfloor \frac{n}{2}\rfloor$ on $2s(\bar{x})$ . Note that the function is clearly polynomial time computable. Therefore, we can define it recursively in $\textrm{PV}$ and represent it by an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term. This term is $\textrm{PV}$ -provably bounded by $2s(\bar{x})$ , that is, $\textrm{PV} \vdash Y(z, \bar{x}) \leq 2s(\bar{x})$ and we have $Y(0, \bar{x})=0$ , $Y(|s(\bar{x})|, \bar{x})=s(\bar{x})$ and if $z \leq |s(\bar{x})|$ , then $Y(z, \bar{x})=\lfloor \frac{Y(z+1, \bar{x})}{2} \rfloor$ , all provable in $\textrm{PV}$ . Now, define

\begin{equation*} I(u, \bar {x})=H'(u \dot {-} t'(\bar {x})\lfloor \frac {u}{t'(\bar {x})} \rfloor, Y(\lfloor \frac {u}{t'(\bar {x})} \rfloor +1), \bar {x}). \end{equation*}

Note that $I(u, \bar{x})$ is well defined as $t'(\bar{x})$ is greater than zero, provably in $\textrm{PV}$ . It is trivial that $I(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Set $r(\bar{x})=t'(\bar{x})|s(\bar{x})|$ . We claim that the pair $(I(u, \bar{x}), r(\bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $E(0, \bar{x})$ to $E(s(\bar{x}),\bar{x})$ as depicted in the following figure. For simplicity, we drop the free variables $\bar{x}$ in the figure.

To prove, we first claim that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \forall z \leq |s(\bar {x})| \, [I(t'(\bar {x})z, \bar {x}) \leftrightarrow E(Y(z, \bar {x}), \bar {x})] \quad \quad (*) \end{equation*}

The reason is that by definition, $I(t'(\bar{x})z, \bar{x})=H'(0,Y(z+1, \bar{x}), \bar{x})$ and the latter is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $E(\lfloor \frac{Y(z+1, \bar{x})}{2}\rfloor, \bar{x})$ , by the property $(1)$ above. Finally, since for any $z \leq |s(\bar{x})|$ , we have $Y(z, \bar{x})=\lfloor \frac{Y(z+1, \bar{x})}{2} \rfloor$ provably in $\textrm{PV}$ , we reach the $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalence with $E(Y(z, \bar{x}), \bar{x})$ .

Now, we prove that $(I(u, \bar{x}), r(\bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $E(0, \bar{x})$ to $E(s(\bar{x}),\bar{x})$ . First, note that $I(0, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $E(0, \bar{x})$ , by substituting $z=0$ in $(*)$ and using the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable fact that $Y(0, \bar{x})=0$ . Second, note that $I(r(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $E(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ , by substituting $z=|s(\bar{x})|$ in $(*)$ and using the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable fact that $Y(|s(\bar{x})|, \bar{x})=s(\bar{x})$ . Third, to prove $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall u \lt t'(\bar{x}) \; [I(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow I(u+1, \bar{x})]$ , there are two cases to consider: Either $u+1$ divides $t'(\bar{x})$ or not. In the latter case, we have $\lfloor \frac{u+1}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor =\lfloor \frac{u}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor$ . By definition $I(u, \bar{x})$ is $H'(u \dot{-} t'(\bar{x})\lfloor \frac{u}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor, Y(\lfloor \frac{u}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor +1), \bar{x})$ while $I(u+1, \bar{x})$ is $H'(u+1 \dot{-} t'(\bar{x})\lfloor \frac{u+1}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor, Y(\lfloor \frac{u+1}{t'(\bar{x})} \rfloor +1), \bar{x})$ . Therefore, the former proves the latter by property $(3)$ above. For the first case, if $t'(\bar{x}) | u+1$ , then there exists $z \leq |s(\bar{x})|$ such that $u+1=t'(\bar{x})z$ . Therefore, $I(u+1, \bar{x})$ is $I(t'(\bar{x})z, \bar{x})$ which is $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $E(Y(z, \bar{x}), \bar{x})$ by $(*)$ , and hence $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent to $H'(t'(\bar{x}), Y(z, \bar{x}), \bar{x})$ by $(2)$ , as $Y(z, \bar{x})$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -provably bounded by $2s(\bar{x})$ . As $I(u, \bar{x})$ is $H'(t'(\bar{x}) \dot{-} 1, Y(z, \bar{x}), \bar{x})$ by definition, by $(3)$ , the formula $I(u, \bar{x})$ implies $I(u+1, \bar{x})$ in $\textrm{PV}$ .

So far, we showed that $(I(u, \bar{x}), r(\bar{x}))$ is a $k$ -flow from $E(0, \bar{x})$ to $E(s(\bar{x}),\bar{x})$ . Again, recall that for the term $s(\bar{x})$ , there is a polynomial $q_s$ such that $\textrm{PV} \vdash |s(\bar{x})| \leq q_s(|\bar{x}|)$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). Hence, $\textrm{PV} \vdash r(\bar{x}) \leq q_s(|\bar{x}|)q_{t'}(|\bar{x}|)$ . Therefore, using Lemma 20, we can prove the existence of a $k$ -flow with the length $q_s(|\bar{x}|)q_{t'}(|\bar{x}|)$ from $E(0, \bar{x})$ to $E(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ which implies $E(0, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k E(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ . Now, to complete the proof of $(ii)$ , by the definition of $E(y, \bar{x})$ , we have $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(0, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ . As $\textrm{PV} \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x}) \to D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ , by Lemma 21, we have $ \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ . Hence, by the weak gluing, the part $(i)$ in the present lemma, we reach $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(0, \bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k D(s(\bar{x}), \bar{x})$ .

The proof of $(iii)$ is similar to that of $(ii)$ and even easier. In this case, one must again define $E(y, \bar{x})$ as $\bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \wedge D(y, \bar{x})$ and then glue the $k$ -flows from $E(y, \bar{x})$ to $E(y+1, \bar{x})$ , one after another, for all $0 \leq y \lt s(\bar{x})$ .

Lemma 24. (Conjunction and Disjunction Rules) Let $\Gamma \cup \Delta \cup \{A, B\} \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Then:

  1. (i) If $\Gamma, A \rhd _k \Delta$ or $\Gamma, B \rhd _k \Delta$ then $\Gamma, A \wedge B \rhd _k \Delta$ .

  2. (ii) If $\Gamma \rhd _k A, \Delta$ and $\Gamma \rhd _k B, \Delta$ then $\Gamma \rhd _k A \wedge B, \Delta$ .

  3. (iii) If $\Gamma \rhd _k A, \Delta$ or $\Gamma \rhd _k B, \Delta$ then $\Gamma \rhd _k A \vee B, \Delta$ .

  4. (iv) If $\Gamma, A \rhd _k \Delta$ and $\Gamma, B \rhd _k \Delta$ then $\Gamma, A \vee B \rhd _k \Delta$ .

A similar claim also holds for $\rhd ^p_k$ .

Proof. The argument is identical to that of Lemma 12 claiming the same fact for the ordinal flows.

Lemma 25. (Negation Rules) If $\Gamma \cup \Delta \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $A, \neg A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ , then:

  1. (i) If $\Gamma, A \rhd _k \Delta$ then $\Gamma \rhd _k \neg A, \Delta$ .

  2. (ii) If $\Gamma \rhd _k A, \Delta$ then $\Gamma, \neg A \rhd _k \Delta$ .

A similar claim also holds for $\rhd ^p_k$ .

Proof. We only prove the claim for $\rhd _k$ . The case for $\rhd _k^p$ is identical. For $(i)$ , assume $\Gamma, A \rhd _k \Delta$ which means $\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge A \rhd _k \bigvee \Delta$ . As $\neg A \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ , by Lemma 21, we have $(\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge A) \vee \neg A \rhd _k \bigvee \Delta \vee \neg A$ . Since $ \textrm{PV} \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge A) \vee \neg A$ , by Lemma 21, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _k (\bigwedge \Gamma \wedge A) \vee \neg A$ . Hence, by weak gluing, Lemma 23, we have $\bigwedge \Gamma \rhd _k \bigvee \Delta \vee \neg A$ . The proof for $(ii)$ is similar.

Lemma 26. (Bounded Universal Quantifier) Let $A(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and $s(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term. If $A(\bar{x}), (y \leq s(\bar{x})) \rhd _k B(\bar{x}, y)$ , then $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k \forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(y, \bar{x})$ . The same also holds for $\rhd _k^p$ .

Proof. Again, we only prove the claim for $\rhd _k$ . The proof for $\rhd ^p_k$ is identical. Since $A(\bar{x}), (y \leq s(\bar{x})) \rhd _k B(\bar{x}, y)$ and $y \leq s(\bar{x})$ is quantifier-free, by Lemma 25, we have $A(\bar{x}) \rhd _k (y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x}, y))$ . Note that $(y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x}, y))$ is defined as $\neg (y \leq s(\bar{x})) \vee B(\bar{x}, y)$ , as the negation is not primitive in the language. Use Lemma 22 for the formulas $A(\bar{x})$ and $(y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x}, y))$ and the term $s(\bar{x})$ . Therefore, we have a formula $I(u, y, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and a term $r(\bar{x})$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash I(0, y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow A(\bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) [I(r(\bar{x}), y, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow (y \leq s(\bar{x}) \to B(\bar{x}, y))]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash I(u, y, \bar{x}) \rightarrow I(u+1, y, \bar{x})$ .

It is easy to see that the pair $\big (\forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) I(u, y, \bar{x}), r(\bar{x})\big )$ is a $k$ -flow from $A(\bar{x})$ to $\forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y)$ .

Now we are ready to use $k$ -flows to witness the provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas in $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ .

Theorem. (Soundness and Completeness) Let $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \cup \Delta (\bar{x}) \subseteq \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Then:

  1. (i) $S^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ iff $ \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k \Delta (\bar{x})$ .

  2. (ii) $T^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ iff $ \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd _k \Delta (\bar{x})$ .

Proof. We only prove $(i)$ . The proof of $(ii)$ is similar. First, we prove the easier completeness part. If $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \rhd ^p_{k} \Delta (\bar{x})$ , then by Definition 19, there exist a polynomial $q$ , and a formula $H(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x})$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(q(|\bar{x}|), \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall u \lt q(|\bar{x}|) \; [H(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(u+1, \bar{x})]$ .

Using Lemma 20, without loss of generality, we can also assume that $\textrm{PV} \vdash q(|\bar{x}|) \geq 1$ . As $\textrm{PV}$ is a subtheory of $S^k_2$ , we also have all the above provabilities for $S^k_2$ . Hence, $ S^k_2 \vdash \forall u \lt q(|\bar{x}|) \; [H(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(u+1, \bar{x})].$ Since $H(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^k_2$ , by the $\hat{\Pi }^b_k-\textrm{LInd}$ axiom, we have, $ S^k_2 \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(|2^{q(|\bar{x}|)\dot{-} 1}|, \bar{x})$ . As $\textrm{PV} \vdash q(|\bar{x}|) \geq 1$ , we have $\textrm{PV} \vdash |2^{q(|\bar{x}|)\dot{-} 1}|=|q(\bar{x})|$ . Hence, $S^k_2 \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(q(|\bar{x}|), \bar{x})$ . Therefore, $S^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ .

For soundness, assume $S^k_2 \vdash \bigwedge \Gamma (\bar{x}) \rightarrow \bigvee \Delta (\bar{x})$ . By Lemma 18, $\Gamma (\bar{x}) \Rightarrow \Delta (\bar{x})$ has a $\textbf{wLS}^{\textbf{k}}_{\textbf{2}}$ -proof only consisting of $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas. By induction on this proof, we show that for any sequent $\Sigma \Rightarrow \Lambda$ in the proof, we have $\Sigma \rhd ^p_k \Lambda$ . For the axioms, as they are provable in $\textrm{PV}$ , using Lemma 21, there is nothing to prove. The case of structural rules (except for the weak cut) is easy. Weak cut and $(\textrm{wPInd}_k)$ are addressed in Lemma 23. The conjunction and disjunction rules are proved in Lemma 24 and the rule $(R\forall ^{\leq })$ is addressed in Lemma 26. Therefore, there are only three cases to consider. If the last rule is

\begin{align*} \frac{\Sigma (\bar{x}, y), B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x}, y)) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x}, y)}{\Sigma (\bar{x}, y), s(\bar{x}, y) \leq t(\bar{x}, y), \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}, y) B(\bar{x}, y) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x}, y)}\,{\tiny L\forall ^{\leq }} \end{align*}

by the induction hypothesis, we have $\Sigma (\bar{x}, y), B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x}, y)) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar{x}, y)$ . Since

\begin{equation*} \bigwedge \Sigma (\bar {x}, y) \wedge (s(\bar {x}, y) \leq t(\bar {x}, y)) \wedge \forall y \leq t(\bar {x}, y) B(\bar {x}, y) \end{equation*}

implies $\bigwedge \Sigma (\bar{x}, y) \wedge B(\bar{x}, s(\bar{x}, y))$ in $\textrm{PV}$ , by Lemma 21 and weak gluing, Lemma 23, we have

\begin{equation*} \Sigma (\bar {x}, y), s(\bar {x}, y) \leq t(\bar {x}, y), \forall y \leq t(\bar {x}, y) B(\bar {x}, y) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar {x}, y). \end{equation*}

The case for the rule $R\exists ^{\leq }$ is similar to the previous case. Finally, if the last rule is

\begin{align*} \frac{\Sigma (\bar{x}), z \leq s(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, z) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x})}{\Sigma (\bar{x}), \exists y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y) \Rightarrow \Lambda (\bar{x})}\,{\tiny L\exists ^{\leq }} \end{align*}

by the induction hypothesis, we have $\Sigma (\bar{x}), z \leq s(\bar{x}), B(\bar{x}, z) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar{x})$ . Since $\exists y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_k$ and it starts with an existential quantifier, it must belong to $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-1}$ . Hence, both $\neg B(\bar{x}, z)$ and $\neg \exists y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y)=\forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) \neg B(\bar{x}, y)$ are in $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ . Therefore, by Lemma 25,

\begin{equation*} \Sigma (\bar {x}), z \leq s(\bar {x}) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar {x}), \neg B(\bar {x}, z). \end{equation*}

By using the fact that the names of the parameters are not important in $k$ -flows and employing Lemma 26, we have $ \Sigma (\bar{x}) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar{x}), \forall y \leq s(\bar{x}) \; \neg B(\bar{x}, y)$ . Finally again by Lemma 25, we reach $ \Sigma (\bar{x}), \exists y \leq s(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y) \rhd ^p_k \Lambda (\bar{x})$ .

5.3 Reductions and $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, l)}$ -programs

In Subsection 5.2, we transformed the $S^k_2$ -provable (resp. $T^k_2$ -provable) implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas into exponentially (resp., polynomially) long uniform sequences of $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications between $\hat{\Pi }^b_k$ -formulas. Having that characterization at hand, one can use the universality of $\textrm{PV}$ to employ generalized Herbrand’s theorem and push the characterization of Theorem 6 even further to witness all essentially existential quantifiers in the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications by polynomial-time computable functions. Instead of following this rather absolute approach, in this subsection, we will employ a relative approach to witness all the essentially existential quantifiers up to a given level $l \leq k$ . The idea is simple. First, by moving the $\textrm{PV}$ -provable implications from $\textrm{PV}$ to $\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}$ , we will pretend that all the $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas in $\hat{\Pi }^b_{k-l} \cup \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-l}$ are quantifier-free in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_{k-l+1}}$ . Therefore, only $l$ many alternating quantifiers are left to peel off for which we use the generalized Herbrand’s theorem. In choosing the right value for $l$ , there is a clear trade-off between the complexity of the witnessing functions on the one hand and the complexity of the witnessing more alternating quantifiers, on the other. For the smaller values of $l$ , the latter would be quite easy as evidenced by Theorem 2. However, the cost to pay is the higher complexity of the witnessing functions that now live in the higher level of the polynomial hierarchy, that is, in the class $\square ^p_{k-l+1}$ . For the higher values of $l$ , the situation is reverse. For instance, if $l=k$ , then all the witnessing functions are polynomial time as they live in $\textrm{PV}_{k-k+1}=\textrm{PV}$ . However, the generalized Herbrand’s theorem must witness $k$ many quantifier alternations that is combinatorially too complex to deal with. In the present subsection, we will lean toward the lower values for $l$ and will only apply the relative approach to two instances of $l=1$ and $l=2$ to avoid the high witnessing complexity. However, it is worth emphasizing that the main base, that is, Theorem 6 is there and one can use it for any value of $l$ by employing the right instance of Herbrand’s theorem. We only cover these two cases to show that how interesting the concrete consequences can be. For $l=1$ , we will show that some well-known witnessing theorems in bounded arithmetic are just special cases of our witnessing theorem. For $l=2$ , the witnessing results are all new.

5.3.1 The game interpretation

Let $k \geq l \geq 1$ be two numbers, $G(\bar{x}, y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_l)$ be a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula and $t(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term. We call the pair $(G(\bar{x}, y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_l), t(\bar{x}))$ a $(k, l)$ -game (a game, for short), and we interpret it as a uniform family of $l$ -turn games between two players parameterized by the variables $\bar{x}$ . To emphasize this parameter role, we sometimes write $G_{\bar{x}}(y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_l)$ for $G(\bar{x}, y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_l)$ and if the variables are clear from the context, we use the shorthand $(G_{\bar{x}}, t(\bar{x}))$ for an instance of the game and $(G, t)$ for the uniform family itself. Given the value $\bar{a}$ for $\bar{x}$ , the game $G_{\bar{a}}$ starts with the first player, denoted by I, playing the number $b_1 \leq t(\bar{a})$ for $y_1$ . Then, the second player, denoted by II, plays $b_2 \leq t(\bar{a})$ for $y_2$ and so on. The resulting tuple $(b_1, b_2, \ldots, b_l)$ is called a play of the game. For a play, $(b_1, b_2, \ldots, b_l)$ , if $G(\bar{a}, b_1, b_2, \ldots, b_l)$ holds, the first player wins the game and otherwise, the second player is the winner. A play $(b_1, \ldots, b_l)$ is called a winning play for the first (second) player, if it makes the first (second) player wins. It is an easy and well-known fact that the first player has a winning strategy in $G_{\bar{a}}$ iff $\exists y_1 \leq t(\bar{a}) \forall y_2 \leq t(\bar{a}) \exists y_3 \leq t(\bar{a}) \ldots G(\bar{a}, y_1, \ldots, y_l)$ holds. As we are always interested in the first player in this subsection, by a winning play and a winning strategy, we always mean them for the first player. Having two $(k, l)$ -games $(G(\bar{x}, y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_l), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, z_1, z_2, \ldots, z_l), s(\bar{x}))$ , a natural question to ask is the following. Let the existence of a winning strategy in $(G_{\bar{x}}, t(\bar{x}))$ implies the existence of a winning strategy in $(H_{\bar{x}}, s(\bar{x}))$ , for any $\bar{x}$ , that is, the implication

\begin{equation*} \exists y_1 \leq t(\bar {x}) \forall y_2 \leq t(\bar {x}) \ldots G(\bar {x}, y_1, \ldots, y_l) \to \exists z_1 \leq s(\bar {x}) \forall z_2 \leq s(\bar {x}) \ldots H(\bar {x}, z_1, \ldots, z_l) \quad \quad (\dagger ) \end{equation*}

hold. Then, does it mean that we can find an explicit way to use a winning strategy for $(G_{\bar{x}}, t(\bar{x}))$ to design a winning strategy for $(H_{\bar{x}}, s(\bar{x}))$ ? One can even sharpen the question by asking if having a proof of the implication $(\dagger )$ in the theory $\textrm{PV}_k$ helps to provide an explicit and relatively simple transformation between the winning strategies. Fortunately, as $\textrm{PV}_k$ is a universal theory, the extraction of the explicit transformation between the winning strategies is possible, and it is simply the content of Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2 (up to some small modifications). We will explain the details for the two case $l=1$ and $l=2$ , below.

5.3.2 The case $l=1$

Let $(G(\bar{x}, y), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, z), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 1)$ -games. The most trivial way to reduce the winning strategy of the latter to that of the former is via a function $f(\bar{x}, y)$ that maps any move $y \leq t(\bar{x})$ in $(G, t)$ to a move $z \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ such that if the play $y$ is a winning play in $(G, t)$ , then the play $z=f(\bar{x}, y)$ is a winning play in $(H, s)$ . Moreover, as we expect the reduction to be simple and verifiable, we expect that everything happens inside a base theory, in our case $\textrm{PV}_k$ . More formally:

Definition 27. Let $(G(\bar{x}, y), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, z), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 1)$ -games. A $(k, 1)$ -reduction from $(H(\bar{x}, z), s(\bar{x}))$ to $(G(\bar{x}, y), t(\bar{x}))$ is an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $f(\bar{x}, y)$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [f(\bar{x}, y) \leq s(\bar{x})]$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, y) \to H(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}, y))]$ .

Naturally, we expect a connection between the provability of

\begin{equation*} \exists y \leq t(\bar {x}) G(\bar {x}, y) \to \exists z \leq s(\bar {x}) H(\bar {x}, z) \end{equation*}

in $\textrm{PV}_k$ and the existence of a $(k, 1)$ -reduction. This is the content of the following modification of Herbrand’s theorem.

Theorem. For any two $(k, 1)$ -games $(G(\bar{x}, y), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, z), s(\bar{x}))$ , the following are equivalent:

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \exists y \leq t(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, y) \to \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) H(\bar{x}, z)$

  • There is a $(k, 1)$ -reduction from $(H(\bar{x}, z), s(\bar{x}))$ to $(G(\bar{x}, y), t(\bar{x}))$ .

Proof. One direction is trivial. For the other, assume

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \exists y \leq t(\bar {x}) G(\bar {x}, y) \to \exists z \leq s(\bar {x}) H(\bar {x}, z). \end{equation*}

Therefore, $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \exists z\, [(y \leq t(\bar{x}) \wedge G(\bar{x}, y)) \to (z \leq s(\bar{x}) \wedge H(\bar{x}, z))]$ . By Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2, there exists an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $g(\bar{x}, y)$ such that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash [y \leq t(\bar {x}) \wedge G(\bar {x}, y)] \to [g(\bar {x}, y) \leq s(\bar {x}) \wedge H(\bar {x}, g(\bar {x}, y))]. \end{equation*}

Define

\begin{equation*} f(\bar {x}, y)= \begin {cases} g(\bar {x}, y) & g(\bar {x}, y) \leq s(\bar {x})\\ 0 & g(\bar {x}, y) \gt s(\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

It is easy to represent $f(\bar{x}, y)$ as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term. By definition, it is clear that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [f(\bar{x}, y) \leq s(\bar{x})]$ . Moreover, it is easy to see that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, y) \to H(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}, y))]$ .

As explained in the opening of this subsection, for $l=1$ , the combination of witnessing by $k$ -flows, moving from $\textrm{PV}$ to $\textrm{PV}_k$ and using Theorem 7 provides an explicit witnessing theorem for theories $S^k_2$ and $T^k_2$ . This is what we will come back to in Corollary 30. However, as the combination has a natural form itself, it is worth defining it directly.

Definition 28. Let $A(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-1}$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula and $t(\bar{x})$ and $r(\bar{x})$ be two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms. By a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program for $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $t(\bar{x})$ , we mean the following data: an initial $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $i(\bar{x})$ , a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , and an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $p(\bar{x}, z)$ , such that:

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash i(\bar{x}) \leq s(\bar{x})$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash G(\bar{x}, 0, i(\bar{x}))$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) [N(\bar{x}, u, z) \leq s(\bar{x})]$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) \, [G(\bar{x}, u, z) \to G(\bar{x}, u+1, N(\bar{x}, u, z))]$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) [p(\bar{x}, z) \leq r(\bar{x})]$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, t(\bar{x}), z) \to A(\bar{x}, p(\bar{x}, z))]$ .

By $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ , we mean the class of all the pairs $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ for which there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program. By $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}^p$ , we mean the class of all the pairs $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ for which there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program with a polynomial length, that is, $t(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ .

It is easy to see that if $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ then $\forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ holds and the $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program actually provides an algorithm to compute $y \leq r(\bar{x})$ from $\bar{x}$ . Denoting $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ by $G^u$ , the algorithm starts at the zeroth level with an initial value $i(\bar{x})$ bounded by $s(\bar{x})$ satisfying the property $G^0$ . Then, using the modification $N$ , it goes from one level to the next updating any value $z \leq s(\bar{x})$ with the property $G^u$ to a value satisfying the property $G^{u+1}$ . Note that the modification always respects the bound $s(\bar{x})$ . Finally, reaching the level $t(\bar{x})$ , the algorithm uses $p$ to compute $y \leq r(\bar{x})$ satisfying $A$ from any value $z \leq s(\bar{x})$ with the property $G^{t(\bar{x})}$ .

There are two points to emphasize here. First, the case $k=1$ , where the predicate $G(\bar{x}, y, z)$ and all the functions $i(\bar{x})$ , $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , and $p(\bar{x}, z)$ are polynomial time computable is just another presentation of the well-known polynomial local search problems, ( $\textrm{PLS}$ for short), see Buss and Krajíček (Reference Buss1994); Krajíček (Reference Krajíček1995). Therefore, one can simply read $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -programs as a generalization of $\textrm{PLS}$ from polynomial time to the $k$ th level of the polynomial hierarchy, where the predicate $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ and the functions $i(\bar{x})$ , $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , and $p(\bar{x}, z)$ are all allowed to be on the $k$ -th level of the hierarchy. It is also worth mentioning that our $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -programs are similar to but weaker than $\Pi ^b_k-\textrm{PLS}$ problems with $\Pi ^b_l$ -goals defined in Beckmann and Buss (Reference Beckmann and Buss2009), where the functions $i(\bar{x})$ , $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , and $p(\bar{x}, z)$ (and not the predicate $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ ) must be polynomial-time computable and everything must be provable in $S^1_2$ rather than in $\textrm{PV}_k$ . The second point is about the $\textrm{PLS}^p_{(k, 1)}$ -programs with a polynomial length. For these programs, the algorithm we just provided can efficiently (relative to the level of the polynomial hierarchy, of course) compute the value of $y$ as it only needs to iterate the modification function $N$ for polynomially many times. In other words, we can pack the whole algorithm in one single $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term as a formalized version of a $\square ^p_k$ -function that computes $y$ . We will come back to this observation in Corollary 31, where we reprove a well-known witnessing theorem for $S^k_2$ , characterizing the $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -definable functions of $S^k_2$ as the ones in the $k$ th level of the polynomial hierarchy.

Remark 29. Employing the game interpretation we explained before, a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ program for $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $t(\bar{x})$ is nothing but the following three $(k, 1)$ -reductions:

  • $i(\bar{x})$ as a $(k, 1)$ -reduction from $(G(\bar{x}, 0, z), s(\bar{x}))$ to $(\top, s(\bar{x}))$ .

  • $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ as a $(k, 1)$ -reduction from the game $(G(\bar{x}, u+1, z), s(\bar{x}))$ to the game $(G(\bar{x}, u, z), s(\bar{x}))$ . Notice that $u$ is also a parameter here.

  • $p(\bar{x}, z)$ as a $(k, 1)$ -reduction from the game $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ to the game $(G(\bar{x}, t(\bar{x}), z), s(\bar{x}))$ .

Notice that the formula $A(\bar{x}, y)$ is not quantifier-free in $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ and hence we cannot read the pair $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ as a $(k, 1)$ -game. However, as $A(\bar{x}, y)$ is in $\hat{\Pi }^b_{k-1}$ , it is $\textrm{PV}_k$ -equivalent to a quantifier-free formula and hence we can pretend that it is quantifier-free. Having that observation, we can use Theorem 7 to see that there is a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ program for $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $t(\bar{x})$ iff there exist a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ and an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $s(\bar{x})$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, 0, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, z) \rightarrow \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u+1, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, t(\bar{x}), z) \to \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ .

The next Corollary uses $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -programs (resp. $\textrm{PLS}^p_{(k, 1)}$ -programs) to witness the theorems of $S^k_2$ (resp. $T^k_2$ ) as promised before.

Corollary 30. Let $k \geq 1$ , $A(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-1}$ and $r(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term:

  1. (i) $S^{k}_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ iff $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}^p_{(k, 1)}$ .

  2. (ii) $T^{k}_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ iff $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ .

Proof. We only prove $(i)$ . The proof of $(ii)$ is similar. For the right to left direction, if there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program for $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ , using Remark 29, there are quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ and an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $s(\bar{x})$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, 0, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, z) \rightarrow \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u+1, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), z) \to \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ .

Since $\textrm{PV}_k$ is interpretable in $S^k_2$ , mapping all quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formulas to $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ , we can pretend that $G(\bar{x}, u, z) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ and all the above formulas are also provable in $S^k_2$ . Finally, since the theory $S^k_2$ has the axiom $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k-\textrm{LInd}$ and $\exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, z) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ , we have $S^k_2 \vdash \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ . For the other direction, assume $S^{k}_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ . Hence, $S^{k}_2 \vdash \forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, y) \rightarrow \bot$ . By Theorem 6, $\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, y) \rhd ^p_k \bot$ . Therefore, there exist a polynomial $q$ and a formula $H(u, \bar{x}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k}$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(0, \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow [\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H(q(|\bar{x}|), \bar{x}) \leftrightarrow \bot$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash \forall u \lt q(|\bar{x}|) \; [H(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H(u+1, \bar{x})]$ .

Define $H'(u, \bar{x})$ as $[(u \leq q(|\bar{x}|)) \to H(u, \bar{x})]$ . It is easy to see that

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash [\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, \bar{y})] \to H'(0, \bar{x})$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H'(q(|\bar{x}|), \bar{x}) \to \bot$ .

  • $\textrm{PV} \vdash H'(u, \bar{x}) \rightarrow H'(u+1, \bar{x})$ .

As $\textrm{PV}$ has the pairing function, it can encode finite many bounded variables as one bounded variable. Hence, without loss of generality, we can assume that $H'$ is in the prenex bounded form starting with one universal quantifier on $z$ , that is, $H'(u, \bar{x})=\forall z \leq s'(\bar{x}, u) \; I(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , where $s'$ is $\textrm{PV}$ -monotone and $I \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-1}$ . Define $s(\bar{x})$ as $s'(q(|\bar{x}|), \bar{x})$ . Then, it is easy to see that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash H'(u, \bar {x}) \leftrightarrow [\forall z \leq s(\bar {x}) [(z \leq s'(u, \bar {x})) \wedge (u \leq q(|\bar {x}|)) \to I(\bar {x}, u, z)]]. \end{equation*}

Hence, without loss of generality, we can assume that $H'$ is in the form $\forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , where $J$ is in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-1}$ . Since $\textrm{PV}$ is a subtheory of $\textrm{PV}_{k}$ and in $\textrm{PV}_{k}$ any formula in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-1}$ is equivalent to a quantifier-free formula, we can assume that $J$ is quantifier-free in the language of $\textrm{PV}_{k}$ and we have

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash [\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, y)] \to \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, 0, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), z) \to \bot$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u, z) \rightarrow \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u+1, z)$ .

Define $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ as $\neg J(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|) \dot{-} u, z)$ and note that it is a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula. Therefore, we have

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), z) \to \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, 0, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k} \vdash \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, z) \rightarrow \exists z \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u+1, z)$ .

Finally, it is enough to use Remark 29 to get a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program for the pair $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $q(|\bar{x}|)$ . Hence, $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}^p_{(k, 1)}$ .

Note that the second part in Corollary 30, when applied on $k=1$ , reproves the well-known characterization of the $T^1_2$ -provable formulas of the form $\forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ , where $A(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_0$ , in terms of the usual $\textrm{PLS}$ problems (Buss and Krajíček Reference Buss and Krajíček1994; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995). Our result, however, seems a bit weaker than the one proved in Buss and Krajíček (Reference Buss and Krajíček1994), Krajíček (Reference Krajíček1995), as in the latter $y$ is not assumed to be bounded and $A(\bar{x}, y)$ can be in $\hat{\Sigma }^b_1$ rather than in our lower class of $\hat{\Pi }^b_0$ . However, proving the stronger form from the one we provided is just a standard technique. First, notice that the presence of $r(\bar{x})$ is no restriction, thanks to Parikh theorem. Second, to reduce the complexity of $A(\bar{x}, y)$ , it is enough to write $A(\bar{x}, y)$ in the form $\exists \bar{z} \leq \bar{x}(\bar{x}) B(\bar{x}, y, \bar{z})$ , where $B(\bar{x}, y, \bar{z}) \in \hat{\Pi }^b_0$ . Then, using the pairing function available in $\textrm{PV}$ , we can make $y$ and all the variables $\bar{z}$ into one bounded variable $w \leq t(\bar{x})$ . Now, we can apply Corollary 30 to compute $w$ by a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program. With this technique, the $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program not only computes the intended variable $y$ but it also finds a value for the variables $\bar{z}$ . To retrieve our formula $A(\bar{x}, y)$ , we can simply keep the computation for $y$ and forget the other values for $\bar{z}$ by reintroducing their existential quantifiers. Having this observation about the usual $\textrm{PLS}$ , one can read Corollary 30 as a generalization of the mentioned characterization for $T^1_2$ to cover both $T^k_2$ and $S^k_2$ , for any $k \geq 1$ . However, the latter case can be strengthened even further as the polynomial $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program provided in Corollary 30 can be simplified to one single $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term. This reproves the following well-known witnessing theorem for $S^k_2$ (Buss Reference Buss1986; Krajíček Reference Krajíček1995).

Corollary 31. The provably $\hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ -definable functions of $S_2^k$ are in $\square _{k}^p$ . Even better, if $S^k_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y A(\bar{x}, y)$ , where $A(\bar{x}, y) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ , then there exists a function $f \in \square _k^p$ represented as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term such that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall \bar{x} \, A(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}))$ .

Proof. Following the technique we just described, without loss of generality, we can assume that $A(\bar{x}, y)$ has no existential quantifier in its front and hence it is actually in $\hat{\Pi }^{b}_{k-1}$ . By Parikh theorem, there exists an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term $r(\bar{x})$ such that $S^k_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y)$ . By Corollary 30, there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program for $(A(\bar{x}, y), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for a polynomial $q$ . Let $G(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , $i(\bar{x})$ , $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ , and $p(\bar{x}, z)$ be the data of the $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program. By recursion on notation on $w$ , define the function $M(w, \bar{x})$ as

\begin{equation*} \begin {cases} M(0, \bar {x})=i(\bar {x}) & \\ M(w, \bar {x})=N(\bar {x}, |w| \dot {-} 1, M(\lfloor \frac {w}{2} \rfloor, \bar {x})) & w \gt 0\\ \end {cases} \end{equation*}

Recall that the $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms are closed under bounded recursion on notation. As both $i$ and $N$ are $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms and $i(\bar{x})$ is bounded by $s(\bar{x})$ and $N(\bar{x}, u, z)$ maps any $z \leq s(\bar{x})$ to something below $s(\bar{x})$ , we can make sure that the function $M(w, \bar{x})$ is also representable as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term. Now, define $I(\bar{x}, w, z)$ as $G(\bar{x}, |w|, z)$ . Using the properties of the $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 1)}$ -program, it is clear that

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash I(\bar{x}, 0, i(\bar{x}))$ ,

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \gt 0 \, [I(\bar{x}, \lfloor \frac{w}{2} \rfloor, z) \to I(\bar{x}, w, N(\bar{x}, |w| \dot{-} 1, z))]$ .

Therefore, as $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash M(w, \bar{x}) \leq s(\bar{x})$ , by using the axiom $\textrm{PInd}$ on the quantifier-free formula $I(\bar{x}, w, M(w, \bar{x}))$ , we can prove $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash I(\bar{x}, w, M(w, \bar{x}))$ . Substituting $w=\lfloor \frac{2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}}{2} \rfloor$ , we reach

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash I(\bar {x}, |\lfloor \frac {2^{q(|\bar {x}|)}}{2} \rfloor |, M(\lfloor \frac {2^{q(|\bar {x}|)}}{2} \rfloor, \bar {x})). \end{equation*}

Using the fact that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash |\lfloor \frac{2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}}{2} \rfloor |=q(|\bar{x}|)$ , we have

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash G(\bar {x}, q(|\bar {x}|), M(\lfloor \frac {2^{q(|\bar {x}|)}}{2} \rfloor, \bar {x})). \end{equation*}

Therefore, as $p(\bar{x}, z)$ is an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term and it has the property

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \forall z \leq s(\bar {x})[G(\bar {x}, q(|\bar {x}|), z) \to A(\bar {x}, p(\bar {z}, z))], \end{equation*}

we can define $f(\bar{x})=p(\bar{x}, M(\lfloor \frac{2^{q(|\bar{x}|)}}{2} \rfloor, \bar{x}))$ as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term. Therefore, $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall \bar{x} A(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}))$ .

5.3.3 The case $l=2$

Let $(G(\bar{x}, y, z), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 2)$ -games. To use a winning strategy for $(G(\bar{x}, y, z), t(\bar{x}))$ to design one for $(H(\bar{x}, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ , the most trivial way is using two functions $f(\bar{x}, y)$ and $g(\bar{x}, y, w)$ , where $f(\bar{x}, y)$ reads the first move $y \leq t(\bar{x})$ in $(G, t)$ and computes a first move $v \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ . Then, $g(\bar{x}, y, w)$ reads the second move $w \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ and computes a second move $z \leq t(\bar{x})$ in $(G, t)$ . These computations must be in a way that if the play $(y, z)$ is winning in $(G, t)$ , the play $(v, w)$ is winning in $(H, t)$ . Expecting the whole reduction process to be simple relative to $\textrm{PV}_k$ , we have:

Definition 32. Let $(G(\bar{x}, y, z), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 2)$ -games. By a deterministic $(k, 2)$ -reduction from $(H, s)$ to $(G, t)$ , we mean two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms $f(\bar{x}, y)$ and $g(\bar{x}, y, w)$ such that:

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [f(\bar{x}, y) \leq s(\bar{x})]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [g(\bar{x}, y, w) \leq t(\bar{x})]$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, y, g(\bar{x}, y, w)) \to H(\bar{x}, f(\bar{x}, y), w)]$ .

In a similar fashion to what we had n the previous subsubsection, we expect an equivalence between the provability of

\begin{equation*} \exists y \leq t(\bar {x}) \forall z \leq t(\bar {x}) G(\bar {x}, y, z) \to \exists v \leq s(\bar {x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar {x}) H(\bar {x}, v, w) \end{equation*}

in $\textrm{PV}_k$ and the existence of a deterministic $(k, 2)$ -reduction from $(H, s)$ to $(G, t)$ . Unfortunately, this expected equivalence does not exist, unless a hardness conjecture in complexity theory fails. Let us first explain this conjecture.

Let $U, V \subseteq \mathbb{N}$ be two disjoint $\textbf{NP}$ -sets. We call a polynomial time computable $S \subseteq \mathbb{N}$ a separator for $U$ and $V$ , if $U \subseteq S$ and $S \cap V=\varnothing$ . The hardness conjecture we want to use states that there are two disjoint $\textbf{NP}$ -sets $U$ and $V$ that have no separator.

Example 33. Let $U$ and $V$ be two disjoint $\textbf{NP}$ -sets that have no separator and represent them by the $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas $\exists y \leq s_B(x) B(x, y)$ and $\exists y \leq s_C(x) C(x, y)$ , respectively, where $B(x, y)$ and $C(x, z)$ are two quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formulas and $s_B(x)$ and $s_C(x)$ are two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms. First, notice that without loss of generality, we can always assume that $s_B(x)=s_C(x)$ and $\forall x (s_B(x) \gt 0)$ holds in the standard model. The reason is that we can replace $\exists y \leq s_B(x) B(x, y)$ by

\begin{equation*} \exists y \leq s_B(x)+s_C(x)+1 \,[y \leq s_B(x) \wedge B(x, y)] \end{equation*}

and similarly for $\exists z \leq s_C(x) C(x, z)$ . From now on, denote both $s_B(x)$ and $s_C(x)$ , by the common name $s(x)$ . Moreover, notice that as $U \cap V=\varnothing$ , the formula $\forall y \leq s(x) \neg B(x, y) \vee \forall z \leq s(x) \neg C(x, z)$ is true, for any value for $x$ . Now, let

\begin{equation*} A(x, w, y, z)=(w=0 \to \neg B(x, y)) \wedge (w \neq 0 \to \neg C(x, z)). \end{equation*}

It is clear that the formula

\begin{equation*} \exists w_0w_1 \leq s(x) \forall y_0y_1z_0z_1 \leq s(x) \; [A(x, w_0, y_0, z_0) \vee A(x, w_1, y_1, z_1)] \end{equation*}

logically implies $ \exists w \leq s(x) \forall yz \leq s(x) \; A(x, w, y, z)$ and hence the implication is provable in $\textrm{PV}$ . Unfortunately, in both formulas, some of the quantifier blocks have more than one bounded quantifiers, and hence, the formulas cannot be read as $(k, 2)$ -games. However, using the pairing function and its projections available in $\textrm{PV}$ , it is not hard to change the formulas to $\textrm{PV}$ -equivalent formulas in the right form. We will avoid applying this change here as it makes everything unnecessarily complicated. Instead, we keep working with the original formulas as the one and the only exception in this paper. However, let us emphasize that whatever we claim in this example can be rewritten in a precise way using the mentioned encoding. Having said that, in the rest of this example, we pretend that we are working with the two $(k, 2)$ -games $(A(x, w, y, z), s(x))$ and $(A(x, w_0, y_0, z_0) \vee A(x, w_1, y_1, z_1), s(x))$ and we show that there is no deterministic $(k, 2)$ -reduction from the $(k, 2)$ -game $(A(x, w, y, z), s(x))$ to the $(k, 2)$ -game $(A(x, w_0, y_0, z_0) \vee A(x, w_1, y_1, z_1), s(x))$ . For the sake of contradiction, assume that there are polynomial time computable functions $f(x, w_0, w_1)$ , $g_0(x, w_0, w_1, y, z)$ , $g_1(x, w_0, w_1, y, z)$ , $h_0(x, w_0, w_1, y, z)$ , and finally $h_1(x, w_0, w_1, y, z)$ , all represented as $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms such that they read $w_0$ , $w_1$ , $y$ , and $z$ below $s(x)$ and compute $w$ , $y_0$ , $y_1$ , $z_0$ , and $z_1$ all below $s(x)$ , respectively, satisfying the property

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV} \vdash \forall w_0w_1yz \leq s [(A(x, w_0, g_0, h_0) \vee A(x, w_1, g_1, h_1)) \to A(x, f, y, z)]. \end{equation*}

(The arguments of the functions are omitted, for simplicity). Therefore, the formula

\begin{equation*} \forall w_0w_1yz \leq s [(A(x, w_0, g_0, h_0) \vee A(x, w_1, g_1, h_1)) \to A(x, f, y, z)] \end{equation*}

is true in the standard model. Substitute $w_0=0$ and $w_1=1$ and notice that the condition $s(x) \geq 1$ allows such a substitution. We see that $A(x, 0, g_0, h_0)$ is equivalent to $\neg B(x, g_0)$ and $A(x, 1, g_1, h_1)$ is equivalent to $\neg C(x, h_1)$ . Therefore, the following formula is true:

\begin{equation*} \forall yz \leq s(x) [(\neg B(x, g_0) \vee \neg C(x, h_1)) \to A(x, f, y, z)]. \end{equation*}

Therefore, we have

\begin{equation*} [\forall y \leq s(x) \neg B(x, y) \vee \forall z \leq s(x) \neg C(x, z)] \to \forall yz \leq s(x) A(x, f, y, z). \end{equation*}

Recall that as $U \cap V=\varnothing$ , we know $\forall y \leq s(x) \neg B(x, y) \vee \forall z \leq s(x) \neg C(x, z)$ is true. Therefore, we reach $\forall yz \leq s(x) A(x, f, y, z)$ . Now, note that if $f(x, 0, 1)=0$ , the formula $A(x, f, y, z)$ is equivalent to $\neg B(x, y)$ and if $f(x, 0, 1) \neq 0$ , it is equivalent to $\neg C(x, z)$ . Therefore, if $f(x, 0, 1)=0$ , we have $\forall y \leq s(x) \neg B(x, y)$ and if $f(x, 0, 1) \neq 0$ , we have $\forall z \leq s(x) \neg C(x, z)$ . We claim that the set $S=\{x \in \mathbb{N} \mid f(x) \neq 0\}$ is a separator. First, note that $S$ is polynomial computable as $f(x, w_0, w_1)$ is a polynomial-time computable function. Second, it is clear that $S$ is disjoint from $V$ . To show that it includes $U$ , assume $x \in U$ and $f(x, 0, 1)=0$ . Then, $\forall y \leq s(x) \neg B(x, y)$ which means that $x \notin U$ . Therefore, we found a separator which is impossible. Hence, the claimed deterministic $(k, 2)$ -reduction does not exist.

As we observed in Example 33, deterministic $(k, 2)$ -reductions are not even powerful enough to capture the pure logical implications between the existence of the winning strategies. To solve the problem, in the following, we strengthen the notion by relaxing the determinism in the definition.

Definition 34. Let $(G(\bar{x}, y, z), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 2)$ -games. By a $(k, 2)$ -reduction from $(H, s)$ to $(G, t)$ , we mean a finite sequence of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms $f_0(\bar{x}, y)$ , $f_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0)$ , …, $f_m(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m-1})$ together with an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -term $g(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})$ such that all the following are provable in $\textrm{PV}_k$ :

  • $\forall \bar{w} \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [f_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}) \leq s(\bar{x})]$ , for any $0 \leq i \leq m$ .

  • $\forall \bar{w} \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [g(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}) \leq t(\bar{x})]$ .

  • $ \forall \bar{w} \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, y, g(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})) \to \bar{H}(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_m)]$ , where the formula $\bar{H}(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_m)$ is $\bigvee _{i=0}^m H(\bar{x}, f_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i)$ .

Remark 35. Here is a computational interpretation of a $(k, 2)$ -reduction as a nondeterministic version of the deterministic $(k,2)$ -reductions we had before. A $(k, 2)$ -reduction starts with reading the first move $y \leq t(\bar{x})$ in $(G, t)$ and uses $f_0$ to transform it to a first move $v_0 \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ . Then, as before it reads the second move $w_0 \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ . However, instead of using it to find a second move in $(G, t)$ , it uses $f_1$ to come up with another possible first move $v_1 \leq s(\bar{x})$ in $(H, s)$ and asks about its second move $w_1$ . It keeps repeating this procedure to finally after $m+1$ many enquiries, it uses $g$ to compute the second move in $(G, t)$ . These computations are in a way that if the produced play for $(G, t)$ is winning, then one of the produced plays for $(H, s)$ is winning.

The following theorem slightly modifies Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2, to connect the $\textrm{PV}_k$ -provability of the implication between the existence of the strategies and the existence of $(k, 2)$ -reductions.

Theorem. Let $(G(\bar{x}, y, z), t(\bar{x}))$ and $(H(\bar{x}, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ be two $(k, 2)$ -games. Then

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \exists y \leq t(\bar {x}) \forall z \leq t(\bar {x}) G(\bar {x}, y, z) \to \exists v \leq s(\bar {x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar {x}) H(\bar {x}, v, w) \end{equation*}

iff there exists a $(k, 2)$ -reduction from $(H, s)$ to $(G, t)$ .

Proof. One direction is clear. For the other, assume

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \exists y \leq t(\bar {x}) \forall z \leq t(\bar {x}) G(\bar {x}, y, z) \to \exists v \leq s(\bar {x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar {x}) H(\bar {x}, v, w). \end{equation*}

Define $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, z)$ as $[y \leq t(\bar{x}) \wedge (z \leq t(\bar{x}) \to G(\bar{x}, y, z))]$ and $\tilde{H}(\bar{x}, v, w)$ as $[v \leq s(\bar{x}) \wedge (w \leq s(\bar{x}) \to H(\bar{x}, v, w))]$ . Now, by moving the quantifiers, we have

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \forall y \exists vz \forall w [\tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, z) \to \tilde {H}(\bar {x}, v, w)]. \end{equation*}

Using the pairing function available in $\textrm{PV}$ , we can make two variables $v$ and $z$ into one variable, apply Herbrand’s theorem, Theorem 2 and then retrieve $y$ and $z$ again, by projections. Therefore, there are $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms $g_0(\bar{x}, y)$ , $h_0(\bar{x}, y)$ , $g_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0)$ , $h_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0)$ , …, $g_m(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m-1})$ and $h_m(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m-1})$ such that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash \bigvee _{i=0}^{m} [\tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1})) \to \tilde {H}(\bar {x}, h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i)]. \end{equation*}

Define $g'(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})$ by cases: if $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_0(\bar{x}, y))$ is false, define $g'$ as $g_0(\bar{x}, y)$ ; if $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_0(\bar{x}, y))$ is true but $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0))$ is false, define $g'$ as $g_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0)$ ; if both $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_0(\bar{x}, y))$ and $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_1(\bar{x}, y, w_0))$ are true but $\tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_2(\bar{x}, y, w_0, w_1))$ is false, define $g'$ as $g_2(\bar{x}, y, w_0, w_1)$ and so on. Finally, if all of $G(\bar{x}, y, g_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}))$ ’s are true, define $g'$ as $0$ :

\begin{equation*} g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})= \begin {cases} g_0(\bar {x}, y) & \neg \tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g_0(\bar {x}, y))\\ g_1(\bar {x}, y, w_0) & \tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g_0(\bar {x}, y)), \neg \tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g_1(\bar {x}, y, w_0))\\ $\ldots $ & $\ldots $\\ 0 & o.w. \end {cases} \end{equation*}

Note that $g'$ is defined in a way that unless $\bigwedge _{i=0}^{m} \tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}))$ is true, we always have $\neg \tilde{G}(\bar{x}, y, g'(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}))$ . Therefore, it is easy to see that

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash [\tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})) \to \bigwedge _{i=0}^{m} \tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}))], \end{equation*}

and hence

\begin{equation*} \textrm {PV}_k \vdash [\tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})) \to \bigvee _{i=0}^{m}\tilde {H}(\bar {x}, h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i)]. \end{equation*}

Define

\begin{equation*} f_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1})= \begin {cases} h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}) & h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}) \leq s(\bar {x})\\ 0 & h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}) \gt s(\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

for any $0 \leq i \leq m$ and set

\begin{equation*} g(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})= \begin {cases} g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}) & g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}) \leq t(\bar {x})\\ 0 & g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}) \gt t(\bar {x}) \end {cases} \end{equation*}

It is clear that $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash f_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}) \leq s(\bar{x})$ , for any $0 \leq i \leq m$ and $\textrm{PV}_k \vdash g(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}) \leq t(\bar{x})$ . It is also clear that

\begin{equation*} \forall y \leq t(\bar {x})[G(\bar {x}, y, g(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})) \to \tilde {G}(\bar {x}, y, g'(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m}))] \end{equation*}

and

\begin{equation*} \forall \bar {w} \leq s(\bar {x}) [\tilde {H}(\bar {x}, h_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i) \to H(\bar {x}, y, f_i(\bar {x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i)] \end{equation*}

are provable in $\textrm{PV}_k$ . Therefore, we reach the implication $\forall \bar{w} \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall y \leq t(\bar{x}) [G(\bar{x}, y, g(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{m})) \to \bigvee _{i=0}^m H(\bar{x}, f_i(\bar{x}, y, w_0, \ldots, w_{i-1}), w_i)]$ in $\textrm{PV}_k$ .

Definition 36. Let $k \geq 2$ be a natural number, $A(\bar{x}, y, z) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-1}$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula and $t(\bar{x})$ and $r(\bar{x})$ be two $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -terms. By a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k,2)}$ -program for the pair $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ , we mean a $(k, 2)$ -game $(G(\bar{x}, u, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ (read $u$ as a parameter) and

  • an initial sequence $i(\bar{x}, w)$ of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms as a $(k, 2)$ -reduction from the game $(G(\bar{x}, 0, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ to $(\top, s(\bar{x}))$ ,

  • a sequence $N(\bar{x}, u, v, w)$ of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms as a $(k, 2)$ -reduction from the game $(G(\bar{x}, u+1, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ to $(G(\bar{x}, u, v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ ,

  • a sequence $p(\bar{x}, v, z)$ of $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -terms as a $(k, 2)$ -reduction from the game $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ to $(G(\bar{x}, t(\bar{x}), v, w), s(\bar{x}))$ . Here, we pretend that $A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ is a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_k}$ -formula.

By $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ , we mean the class of all the pairs $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ for which there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -program. By $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}^p$ , we mean the class of all the pairs $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ for which there exists a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -program with polynomial length, that is, $t(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ .

One can read a (polynomial) $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -program as (a polynomially) an exponentially long sequence of reductions between $2$ -turn games, starting with an explicit winning strategy for the first game, where all the functions and predicates live in the $k$ -th level of the polynomial hierarchy verified in $\textrm{PV}_k$ .

Similar to what we had in the last subsubsection, we can finally witness provability in $T^k_2$ (resp. $S^k_2$ ) by (resp. polynomial) $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -programs.

Corollary 37. Let $k \geq 2$ , $A(\bar{x}, y, z) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-2}$ and $r(\bar{x})$ be an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -term:

  1. (i) $S^{k}_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(x) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ iff $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}^p_{(k-1, 2)}$ .

  2. (ii) $T^{k}_2 \vdash \forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ iff $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}_{(k-1,2)}$ .

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Corollary 30. Therefore, we only explain the main ingredients for $(i)$ . For the right to left, assume that there is a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -program for $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ . We use Theorem 8 to transform the existence of the reductions in the $\textrm{PLS}_{(k, 2)}$ -program to the following provable implications:

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, 0, v, w)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, v, w) \rightarrow \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u+1, v, w)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), v, w) \to \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ .

As any quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_{k-1}}$ -formula can be interpreted as an $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula in $\hat{\Pi }^b_{k-1}$ and $\textrm{PV}_{k-1}$ can be interpreted in $S^{k-1}_2$ , we can pretend that all the above implications are provable in $S^k_2$ and $G \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-1}$ . Therefore, we can assume that $\exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, v, w) \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_k$ . Using $\textrm{LInd}$ in $S^k_2$ on the formula $\exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, v, w)$ , we reach $S^k_2 \vdash \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ . Conversely, we assume that $S^k_2 \vdash \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ . Hence, $\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \exists z \leq r(\bar{x}) \neg A(\bar{x}, y, z) \to \bot$ is provable in $S^k_2$ . Since $A \in \hat{\Sigma }^b_{k-2}$ , the formula $\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \exists z \leq r(\bar{x}) \neg A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ is in $\hat{\Pi }^b_{k}$ . Hence, by Theorem 6, we have $\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \exists z \leq r(\bar{x}) \neg A(\bar{x}, y, z) \rhd ^p_k \bot$ . Call the $k$ -flow $(H(u, \bar{x}), t(\bar{x}))$ , where $t(\bar{x})=q(|\bar{x}|)$ , for some polynomial $q$ . Without loss of generality, write $H(u, \bar{x})$ in the form $\forall v \leq s(\bar{x}) \exists w \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u, v, w)$ , where $J \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-2}$ . As $k \geq 2$ , the theory $\textrm{PV}$ is a subtheory of $\textrm{PV}_{k-1}$ . Therefore, moving the implications in the definition of the $k$ -flow from $\textrm{PV}$ to $\textrm{PV}_{k-1}$ , we have:

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash [\forall y \leq r(\bar{x}) \exists z \leq r(\bar{x}) \; \neg A(\bar{x}, y, z)] \to \forall v \leq s(\bar{x}) \exists w \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, 0, v, w)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \forall v \leq s(\bar{x}) \exists w \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), v, w) \to \bot$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \forall v \leq s(\bar{x}) \exists w \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u, v, w) \rightarrow \forall v \leq s(\bar{x}) \exists w \leq s(\bar{x}) J(\bar{x}, u+1, v, w)$ .

As $J \in \hat{\Pi }^b_{k-2}$ , in $\textrm{PV}_{k-1}$ , we can pretend that $J$ is a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}_{k-1}}$ -formula. Define $G(\bar{x}, u, v, w)$ as $\neg J(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|) \dot{-} u, v, w)$ . Therefore, we have:

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, q(|\bar{x}|), v, w) \to \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(\bar{x}) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, 0, v, w)$ .

  • $\textrm{PV}_{k-1} \vdash \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u, v, w) \rightarrow \exists v \leq s(\bar{x}) \forall w \leq s(\bar{x}) G(\bar{x}, u+1, v, w)$ .

Finally, it is enough to use Theorem 8 to get a $\textrm{PLS}_{(k-1, 2)}$ -program for the pair $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x}))$ with the length $q(|\bar{x}|)$ . Hence, $(A(\bar{x}, y, z), r(\bar{x})) \in \textrm{PLS}^p_{(k-1, 2)}$ .

It is worth putting Corollary 37 for the concrete case $k=2$ into plain words. Here, the corollary characterizes the $T^2_2$ -provability (resp. $S^2_2$ -provability) of a formula in the form $\forall \bar{x} \exists y \leq r(\bar{x}) \forall z \leq r(x) A(\bar{x}, y, z)$ , where $A$ is a polynomial time computable predicate represented as a quantifier-free $\mathcal{L}_{\textrm{PV}}$ -formula by the existence of an exponentially (resp. polynomially) long sequence of polynomial time reductions between polynomial time games starting on an explicit polynomial time winning strategy in the first game.

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to Pavel Pudlák and Neil Thapen for the fruitful discussions we had and for bringing the connection between the total search problems and the theories of arithmetic into our attention. We are also thankful to the anonymous referees whose suggestions improved the paper’s presentation. The support by the FWF project P 33548 and the Czech Academy of Sciences (RVO 67985840) is also gratefully acknowledged.

References

Avigad, J. (2002). Ordinal analysis without proofs. In: Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics (Stanford, CA 1998), Lecture Notes in Logic, Urbana, IL, Association for Symbolic Logic, vol. 15, 136.Google Scholar
Avigad, J. and Feferman, S. (1998). Gödel’s functional (“Dialectica”) interpretation. In: Handbook of Proof Theory, vol. 137, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 337405, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A. (2009). A characterisation of definable NP search problems in Peano arithmetic. In: Logic, Language, Information and Computation, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Berlin, Springer, vol. 5514, 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A. and Buss, S. (2017). The NP search problems of Frege and extended Frege proofs. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic 18 (2) 1919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A. and Buss, S. R. (2009). Polynomial local search in the polynomial hierarchy and witnessing in fragments of bounded arithmetic. Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1) 103138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A. and Buss, S. R. (2010). Characterising definable search problems in bounded arithmetic via proof notations. In: Ways of Proof Theory, vol. 2, Heusenstamm, Ontos Verlag, 65133, Ontos Mathematical Logic CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A. and Buss, S. R. (2014). Improved witnessing and local improvement principles for second-order bounded arithmetic. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic 15 (1) Art.2,35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckmann, A., Pollett, C. and Buss, S. R. (2003). Ordinal notations and well-orderings in bounded arithmetic. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 120 (1-3) 197223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beklemishev, L. D. (2004). Provability algebras and proof-theoretic ordinals. I. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (1-3) 103123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchholz, W. (1991). Notation systems for infinitary derivations. Archive for Mathematical Logic 30 (5-6) 277296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchholz, W. (1997). Explaining Gentzen’s consistency proof within infinitary proof theory. Computational logic and proof theory (Vienna, 1997), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Berlin, Springer, vol. 1289, 417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, S. R. (1986). Bounded Arithmetic, Studies in Proof Theory. Lecture Notes , vol. 3, Naples, BibliopolisBibliopolis.Google Scholar
Buss, S. R. (1994). The witness function method and provably recursive functions of Peano arithmetic. In: Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, IX (Uppsala, 1991), Amsterdam, North-Holland, vol. 134, 2968, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, S. R. (1997). Bounded arithmetic and propositional proof complexity. In: Logic of Computation (Marktoberdorf 1995), Berlin, Springer, vol. 157, 67121, NATO Science Series, III: Computer and Systems Sciences.Google Scholar
Buss, S. R. (1998a). An introduction to proof theory. In: Handbook of Proof Theory, vol. 137, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 178, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics.Google Scholar
Buss, S. R. (1998b). First-order proof theory of arithmetic. In: Handbook of Proof Theory, vol. 137, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 79147, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, S. R. and Krajíček, J. (1994). An application of Boolean complexity to separation problems in bounded arithmetic. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 69 (1) 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, S. R., Krajíček, J. and Takeuti, G. (1993). Provably total functions in bounded arithmetic theories Ri 3, Ui 2 and Vi 2 . In: Arithmetic, Proof Theory, and Computational Complexity (Prague 1991), vol. 23, New York, Oxford University Press, 116161, Oxford Logic Guides Google Scholar
Cobham, A. (1965). The intrinsic computational difficulty of functions. In: Logic, Methodology and Philos. Sci. (Proc. 1964 Internat. Congr.), Amsterdam, North-Holland, 2430.Google Scholar
Cook, S. A. (1975). Feasibly constructive proofs and the propositional calculus (preliminary version). In: Seventh Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing (Albuquerque, N.M., 1975), 8397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fairtlough, M. and Wainer, S. S. (1998). Hierarchies of provably recursive functions. In: Handbook of Proof Theory, vol. 137, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 149207, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, H. and Sheard, M. (1995). Elementary descent recursion and proof theory. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 71 (1) 145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kołodziejczyk, L. A., Nguyen, P. and Thapen, N. (2011). The provably total NP search problems of weak second order bounded arithmetic. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (6) 419446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajíček, J. (1995). Bounded Arithmetic, Propositional Logic, and Complexity theory, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications , vol. 60, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajíček, J. and Pudlák, P. (1990). Quantified propositional calculi and fragments of bounded arithmetic. Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (1) 2946.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajíček, J., Pudlák, P. and Takeuti, G. (1991). Bounded arithmetic and the polynomial hierarchy. In: International Symposium on Mathematical Logic and Its Applications (Nagoya, 1988), vol. 52, 143153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajíček, J., Skelley, A. and Thapen, N. (2007). NP search problems in low fragments of bounded arithmetic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (2) 649672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreisel, G. (1952). On the interpretation of non-finitist proofs. II. Interpretation of number theory. Applications. Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (1) 4358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paris, J. B. and Wilkie, A. J. (1981). 0 sets and induction. In: Open Days in Model Theory and Set Theory, 237248.Google Scholar
Rathjen, M. (1999). The realm of ordinal analysis. In: Sets and Proofs (Leeds 1997), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, vol. 258, 219279, London Mathematical Society Lecture Note series CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skelley, A. and Thapen, N. (2011). The provably total search problems of bounded arithmetic. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society (3) 103 (1) 106138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tabatabai, A. A. (2018). In the light of intuitionism: two investigations in proof theory. Phd thesis, Charles University.Google Scholar
Takeuti, G. and Zaring, W. M. (1982). Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory, vol. 1, New York, Springer Science & Business Media.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thapen, N. (2011). Higher complexity search problems for bounded arithmetic and a formalized no-gap theorem. Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (7-8) 665680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troelstra, A. S. (1998). Realizability. In: Handbook of Proof Theory, vol. 137, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 407473, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar