Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-zc66z Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-06T17:37:53.967Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Contextualism and the truth norm

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2025

Darren Bradley*
Affiliation:
University of Leeds, Leeds, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

What should we believe? One plausible view is that we should believe what is true. Another is that we should believe what is rational to believe. I will argue that both these theses can be accounted for once we add an independently motivated contextualism about normative terms. According to contextualism, the content of ‘ought’ depends on two parameters – a goal and a modal base (or set of possible worlds). It follows that there is a sense in which we should believe truths and a sense in which we should believe what is rational to believe.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Which norms govern what one ought to believe? The Truth Norm says that we ought to believe what is true. But we seem doomed to violate this norm given our imperfect epistemic position. A less demanding alternative, the Rationality Norm, says that we ought to believe what is rational to believe. But this seems to allow too big a gap between beliefs and truth.

I will argue that the intuitions driving the controversy can be clarified by an independently motivated contextualism about normative terms like ‘ought’.Footnote 1 According to contextualism, the content of normative terms depends on two parameters – a modal base (or set of possible worlds) and a goal that provides a ranking of worlds. One goal is to have true beliefs. Another goal is to have rational beliefs. As different goals can be relevant in different contexts, there will be some contexts where the Truth Norm is relevant and others where the Rationality Norm is relevant. Thus, contextualism can explain why there is something compelling about both norms.Footnote 2 Attempts to distinguish the objective and subjective ‘ought’ can be seen as coarse-grained versions of contextualism.Footnote 3

I will focus on contextualism about ‘ought’, but I take contextualism about all normative terms to follow naturally. For example, if what you ought to do is relative to a goal, it is natural to say that what reasons you have are relative to a goal. I refer the reader to Finlay (Reference Finlay2014) for a detailed defence of contextualism about all normative terms.

Section 2 explains the Truth Norm, Rationality Norm, and the main objections they face. Section 3 introduces contextualism. Section 4 applies contextualism to beliefs, and Section 5 shows how contextualism about beliefs deals with the objections of Section 2. Section 6 considers the objection that even rationality cannot always guide, and Section 7 considers the objection that it is implausible that there is no genuine disagreement. Section 8 concludes.

2. Truth and rationality

Consider two hypotheses about what one ought to believe:

Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

S ought to believe that P iff it is rational for S to believe that P.

Truth

For any agent S and any proposition P:

S ought to believe that P iff P is true.Footnote 4

Suppose there is petrol in Bernard’s glass, but he has good reason to believe it contains gin.Footnote 5 Rationality says Bernard ought to believe his glass contains gin, and Truth says Bernard ought to believe his glass contains petrol. Thus, Rationality conflicts with Truth.Footnote 6 But there are strong arguments for both Truth and Rationality.

Inspiration for Truth can be traced to at least William James:

We must know the truth; and we must avoid error—these are our first and great commandments. (James 1911, p. 17)

The list of proponents runs from Chisholm (Reference Chisholm1977) to Joyce (Reference Joyce1998), Goldman (Reference Goldman1999, Reference Goldman, Fairweather and Zagzebski2001, Reference Goldman2015), Wedgwood (Reference Wedgwood2002), and McHugh (Reference McHugh2012).Footnote 7

One powerful argument for Truth is that Rationality breaks the close connection we want between norms of belief and truth. As Gibbons puts it:

The Truth Connection Objection

If you reject [Truth], then it seems that you’re saying that when it comes to belief, truth is not required. And if it’s not required, then it’s optional. But if you see truth as an optional extra, what could be wrong with thinking that you don’t have it? So what could be wrong with thinking that you believe it’s raining but it’s not? (Gibbons Reference Gibbons2013, p. 10–11Footnote 8 )

Whereas Truth says that in believing that it is raining when it is not, you are not believing as you ought to.

On the other hand, a powerful argument for Rationality is that Truth breaks the close connection we want between norms of belief and guidance: Footnote 9

The Guidance Objection

Norms must be able to guide us, and Truth cannot always guide us. Specifically, Truth cannot guide us in cases where the truth is not available. For example, Truth says that if there is petrol in Bernard’s glass then he ought to believe there is petrol in his glass. But Bernard does not have access to the truth about what is in his glass so he cannot be guided by Truth.

We cannot always be guided by Truth, but, the thought goes, we can always be guided by Rationality. If we add that genuine norms must always be able to provide guidance, it follows that Truth is not a genuine norm.

Most epistemologists in this debate defend one of Truth and Rationality and reject the other.Footnote 10 An alternative approach, recently defended by Hughes (Reference Hughes2019, Reference Hughes2021a, 2021b, forthcomin), is to defend both of Truth and Rationality. He argues that each places an incompatible demand on us, with the result that we face epistemic dilemmas. I also defend both Truth and Rationality, but I don’t think we face epistemic dilemmas. Instead, each of Truth and Rationality is true in specific contexts; there are no contexts where both are true and so no epistemic dilemmas. I return to Hughes in Section 6.

3. Contextualism

It is a familiar thought that whether someone is correctly described as tall depends on the details of the conversation. For example, Michael Jordan, at 1.98 m, is tall for an ordinary person, but not tall for a basketball player. So the truth of ‘Michael Jordan is tall’ depends on the conversational context. It is true given a context in which ordinary people are being discussed but false given a context in which basketball players are being discussed. So the word ‘tall’ has hidden parameters that are filled by the conversational context. As the meaning of ‘tall’ depends on the conversational context, the word is context-sensitive.

The standard view in linguistics is that normative terms like ‘ought’ are context-sensitive in a similar way. They have hidden parameters that are fixed by the conversational context, resulting in different semantic values in different contexts. The standard view is that there are at least two parameters needed to fix the content of ‘ought’ – a set of live possibilities and a standard.Footnote 11

The first parameter, the live possibilities (called the modal base), are the possibilities treated as live in the conversation. For example, suppose we are discussing whether you ought to take an umbrella when you leave the house. If rain is a live possibility, then you ought to; if rain is not a live possibility, then it is not the case that you ought to. If I tell you that the forecast is for fine weather, this can be taken as eliminating the possibility in which it rains, with the result that it is not the case that you ought to take an umbrella.

The second parameter is a standard or goal that determines an ordering of the live possible worlds. The standard proposal is that ‘S ought to A’ is true iff S A’s in every live world at the top of the ranking. Assuming the goal is to stay dry, then, if there is a live possible world in which it rains, the highest ranked worlds will be those in which you take an umbrella. It follows that you ought to take an umbrella. But things change if the goal changes. Perhaps you love getting wet, so the goal is to get wet. Now the highest ranked worlds will include those in which you get wet, and it will not follow that you ought to take an umbrella.

The standard need not be one that the subject cares about. If I say ‘you ought to start with the cutlery on the outer edge’, the standard might be the rules of etiquette. The more explicit sentence is ‘by standards of etiquette, you ought to start with the cutlery on the outer edge’. This sentence can remain true even if you don’t care about etiquette. This allows us to say to the psychopath ‘you shouldn’t kill people’; the full sentence is ‘by standards of morality, you shouldn’t kill people’, which is true even if the psychopath doesn’t care about morality. More importantly for us, it allows us to say ‘you should believe things that are true’ even to someone who doesn’t care about the truth.

For our purposes, we can distinguish two goals, which might be relevant to a conversation about what someone ought to do or believe. The goal might be to:

  1. a) set a standard or

  2. b) state what is rational.

A similar distinction can be found in many places: Bales (Reference Bales1971) distinguishes decision procedures from right-making characteristics; Schroeder (Reference Schroeder2011, p. 1–2) distinguishes deliberative from evaluative oughts; McHugh (Reference McHugh2012, p. 9–10) distinguishes prescriptive from evaluative norms; Schoenfield (Reference Schoenfield2018, p. 690) distinguishes plans to make from procedures to conform to; and Steinberger (Reference Steinberger2019, p. 7) distinguishes directives that guide from evaluations which set standards. The distinction is needed in cases where agents aren’t sure what is best. For example, consequentialists can say that agents ought – in the standard-setting sense – to perform the action that brings about the best consequences, and they ought – in the rationality sense – to perform the action they think will bring about the best consequences.

Returning to norms of belief, the contextualist view is that there are two goals, corresponding to two meanings of ‘ought’ and two norms. In the standard-setting sense, agents ought to believe what is true, and in the rationality sense, agents ought to believe what is rational. Which sense is relevant depends on the context:

Contextualist Truth

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff P’ is true.

Contextualist Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff it is rational for S to believe that P’ is true.

It will be useful to make explicit the sense of ‘ought’ being used with ‘veritistically-ought’ and ‘rationally-ought’:

Contextualist Truth

For any agent S and any proposition P:

S veritistically-ought to believe that P iff P.

Contextualist Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

S rationally-ought to believe that P iff it is rational for S to believe that P.

And we can say that the context in which ‘veritistically-ought’ is relevant is a veritistic context, and a context in which rationally-ought is relevant is a rational context.

The question of precisely what fixes the values of these two parameters is a difficult open question. The contextualist says that it is determined by features of the conversation. But what features? Plausible candidates include the interests, goals, evidence, and beliefs of the participants in the conversation. Two plausible principles for turning these ideas into something more concrete are the principles of charity and the principle of accommodation (Lewis Reference Lewis1979, Reference Lewis1996). The principle of charity holds that we should interpret people so what they say makes a sensible contribution to the conversation. The principle of accommodation says that when a speaker makes an utterance involving a context-sensitive term, the parameters shift to make the sentence true. In Lewis’s terms, the utterance changes the ’conversational score’. In some cases, the participants in the conversation might disagree about which parameters to use. In such a case, they might engage in a process of metalinguistic negotiation in an attempt to resolve the disagreement. I’ll return to metalinguistic negotiation in Section 7.

Technically, from now on, I should semantically ascend and only mention ‘ought’ rather than using it. I will balance this with readability. I think the sloppiness used and apologized for by David Lewis (Reference Lewis1996, p. 566–7) helps beginners even if it irritates experts.

I note in passing that contextualism explains the debate about whether ‘ought’ is subjective or objective (see fn. 3). The contextualist can (i) associate the objective ought with the goal of believing the truth and a modal base that includes all the facts and (ii) associate the subjective ought with the goal of believing what is rational and a modal base consisting of the agent’s evidence or beliefs. The subjective and objective ‘oughts’ are two locations in the wider space opened up by contextualism.

Now that we have this machinery on the table, I will argue that the problems regarding the norms of belief can be solved.

4. Truth and rationality

Let’s work through a couple of examples. First, recall the case of Bernard, who reasonably believes he has gin in his glass, when in fact it is petrol. Truth and Rationality give different verdicts about what Bernard ought to believe. Rationality says he ought to believe there is gin in his glass; Truth says he ought to believe there is petrol in his glass.

The contextualist says either can be true depending on the context. We can make this explicit with ‘rationally-ought’ and ‘veritistically-ought’:

Bernard rationally-ought to believe there is gin in his glass.

Bernard veritistically-ought to believe there is petrol in his glass.

To put the point in terms of the contextualist semantics, the ranking of the worlds changes in different contexts (see Figure 1). In a veritistic context, the worlds are ranked by the ratio of true to false beliefs, so the highest ranking world is the one in which Bernard believes there is petrol in his glass (left); in a rational context, the worlds are ranked by how well beliefs fit the evidence (or whatever determines rationality), so the highest ranking world is the one in which Bernard believes there is gin in his glass (right).

Figure 1. Two rankings for belief.

For another example, consider a question on a student S’s exam: ‘what is the capital of Russia?’ As the answer is Moscow, there is a sense in which S ought to believe it is Moscow. And this remains true even if they have no idea what the correct answer is. Suppose S was sick for a month and missed all the work on Russia. Consider the following dialogue:

Headteacher: S ought to believe that Moscow is the capital of Russia.

Teacher: No, she shouldn’t; she missed last month and has never been taught about Russia.

The contextualist can explain that the headteacher is invoking a context in which the student ought to believe what is trueFootnote 12 :

Headteacher: S veritistically-ought to believe that Moscow is the capital of Russia.

The teacher shifts the context to one in which the highest ranked worlds are those where the student has rational beliefs:

Teacher: It is not the case that S rationally-ought to believe that Moscow is the capital of Russia.

Someone might object that there is no change in context and that the dialogue shows that the Headteacher was simply mistaken about what the student ought to believe. But the conversation might continue in ways that further strengthen the contextualist reading. For example, the headteacher might say:

Headteacher: However much school she missed, Moscow is the capital of Russia, and she should know it.Footnote 13

The contextualist can understand this as a case in which the headteacher has not accommodated the context introduced by the teacher and in which Truth remains relevant.Footnote 14

5. The truth connection objection and guidance objection redux

Let’s return to the arguments of Section 2. The objection to Rationality was that it breaks the close connection we want between norms of belief and truth. One quick contextualist response is to point out that the connection to truth is still there – in some contexts, Truth is relevant, and obviously, Truth provides a connection to truth. But the complaint might continue that this doesn’t address the objection to Rationality. After all, given that beliefs should be closely connected to the truth, we need an explanation of how Rationality could be a norm of belief at all. As Gibbons put it, Rationality seems to make truth merely an optional extra for a belief.

However, the discussion above suggests a natural response – Truth sets the standard, but following Rationality is the best way to try to meet this standard. As we don’t have direct access to what is true, we cannot always follow Truth, but the best attempt for satisfying Truth is to follow Rationality. Thus, the objection that Rationality is not sufficiently connected to the truth can be answered by pointing out that Rationality is the best method we mere (non-omniscient) mortals have for meeting the standard set by Truth.Footnote 15

The objection to Truth was that genuine norms must always be able to provide guidance, but Truth cannot always provide guidance, so Truth is not a genuine norm. In response, if Truth sets standards, it is no objection to point out that it cannot always provide guidance. The point is analogous to that made by Bales (Reference Bales1971). It is no problem for consequentialism if agents do not always know which action will bring about the best consequences; consequentialism sets the standard for a right act. Similarly, it is not a problem for Truth if agents do not always know which propositions are true; Truth sets the standard for correct beliefs.

It is worth mentioning a further advantage of the thesis that Truth sets the standard rather than states what is rational. It has proven quite difficult to work out how strong Truth should be. The following have all been suggestedFootnote 16 :

(Bi-conditional) S ought to believe that P if and only if P is true.

(Conditional) S ought to believe P only if P is true.

(Permission) S may believe that p if and only if P (Whiting Reference Whiting2013).

(Considers) If S considers a proposition at all, S should believe it if and only if it is true (Wedgwood Reference Wedgwood2002).

What’s wrong with the straightforward bi-conditional? It seems to demand too much of us. There are truths that are inaccessible, or too complicated, or impossible for us to believe. However, if Truth is understood as setting the standard, these objections have no force.Footnote 17 It is not a problem if the standard demands too much of us in some cases. The standard doesn’t tell us what to do or give advice, it simply sets the standard for when a belief is correct. So if Truth sets the standard, we can defend Bi-conditional.

This completes my main argument. It remains to discuss two further objections – that even rationality cannot always guide and that it is implausible that disagreement disappears.

6. Can rationality always guide?

Hughes (Reference Hughes2021a) claims that Rationality cannot always provide guidance.Footnote 18 This seems to threaten my claim that the Guidance Objection to Rationality is dealt with by contextualism. I will offer a response that demonstrates the resources available to the contextualist.

Hughes argues that Rationality, like Truth, often fails to provide guidance.Footnote 19 He draws on the cognitive biases psychologists have discovered. To pick just one, everyone seems to have confirmation bias; that is, evidence that undermines our beliefs tends to be assigned too little weight, with the result that we do not change our minds as often as we should. Consider an agent who is unaware that they have this bias. They will systematically assign too little weight to evidence that undermines their beliefs, and they will have no way of knowing that they are doing this. So they are unable to rationally follow the evidence. This suggests that Rationality fails to give us the advertised benefit of a close connection between norms and guidance.

I suggest that we distinguish bounded rationality from ideal rationality.Footnote 20 Ideal rationality does not take into account any cognitive limitations; bounded rationality does. This allows us to distinguish two versions of Contextualist Rationality:

Contextualist Ideal Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff it is ideally rational for S to believe that P’ is true.

Contextualist Bounded Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff it is boundedly rational for S to believe that P’ is true.

Where an agent has confirmation bias, they will often be unable to do what is ideally rational.Footnote 21 But there will still be better or worse ways to respond to the evidence. An agent who shifts their beliefs in the right direction in the light of new evidence will be doing better than an agent who ignores all new evidence. In moving in the right direction they are satisfying the demands of bounded rationality. Where the conversational context takes into account the limitations of the agent, the relevant norm in the conversation is Contextualist Bounded Rationality.

I suggest that Contextualist Bounded Rationality can always provide guidance, allowing us to make peace with the Guidance Objection.Footnote 22 Of course, what exactly is boundedly rational is highly sensitive to the knowledge and abilities of the agent in their context, as well as the allowances that the speakers make. Leaving space for these complexities is one of the virtues of contextualism.

Someone might object that this distinction is ad hoc. But as well as being intuitive and defended by many others, it fits neatly with contextualist semantics. Recall that the context determines a set of possible worlds. These can be thought of as the relevant worlds. In an ideal context, a wide range of worlds are relevant i.e. worlds in which the agent has a wide range of beliefs, including the ideally rational beliefs. We can model a non-ideal (bounded rationality) context using a narrower range of relevant worlds. Making allowances for the limitations of the agent amounts to restricting the live possible worlds.

A different objection is that some biases are not rational in any sense of ‘rational’ and so not even boundedly rational. I agree. I do not say that all biases are boundedly rational; I say that some are boundedly rational. I am committed only to the view that there is always some norm of rationality that can guide an agent (even if they have cognitive limitations).

A counterexample to my thesis that some norm of rationality (e.g. Contextualist Bounded Rationality) can always provide guidance would be an agent who cannot be guided by any norm that deserves to be called a norm of rationality. And I think it is difficult to tell a coherent story of what that would look like. For example, consider an agent so benighted that, necessarily, they can only respond irrationally (not just non-ideally) to some piece of evidence; for example, they respond to seeing a white swan by increasing their credence that there are black swans. Note: It is not just that they do respond irrationally – they are only able to respond irrationality. I think we would be reluctant to ascribe beliefs to this agent at all. For example, the standard functionalist theory of beliefs (Lewis Reference Lewis1972) would say that beliefs are caused by relevant evidence; a mental state that is not sensitive to evidence fails to be a belief. An alternative theory is that beliefs are whatever would rationalize behaviour given experiences, in which case it might be metaphysically impossible for an agent who sees a white swan to infer that there are black swans (Dennett Reference Dennett1971, Reference Dennett1987).

7. Disagreement regained

Someone might object that it is implausible that there is no genuine disagreement in the debate about the norms of belief.Footnote 23 The challenge for the contextualist is to make sense of the intuition that there is genuine disagreement. Let’s consider three ways in which a genuine disagreement might be retained.

First, even if statements about what one ought to believe are context-sensitive in English, there might be a metaphysically privileged parameter that picks out a normatively privileged property. Worsnip writes:

we should be careful to separate the question of whether (e.g.) the law …has genuine normative authority from whether there is a robustly normative usage of the legal ‘ought’. The former requires the law to actually possess normative authority, whereas the latter only requires there to be speakers who take the law to possess normative authority. (Worsnip Reference Worsnip2019, page numbers not yet available; see also Worsnip Reference Worsnip2020)

Worsnip is working with a primitive concept of ‘normative authority’. He is allowing that there might be lots of ‘oughts’, just as contextualism predicts, but that not all of them have normative authority. Indeed, perhaps only one ‘ought’ has normative authority.Footnote 24 Disagreement thus remains when speakers disagree about which ‘ought’ is privileged. And if Truth and Rationality are both normatively authoritative, then we have Hughes’ view that there are epistemic dilemmas.

Still, I take it that contextualism reduces the motivation for the thesis that there is a normatively authoritative ‘ought’. Rather than facing tricky metaphysical (what makes an ‘ought’ privileged?) and epistemic (how do we know which is privileged?) questions, we can explain apparent disagreements by appealing to different speakers using different parameters.

And notice that there can be genuine disagreement even if there is no privileged ‘ought’. All that’s needed for genuine disagreement is differing beliefs about which ‘ought’ is privileged (even if none of them actually are privileged). Compare: If you think Santa Claus is married and I think he is a bachelor, we disagree, even though we are both wrong.

The second way to retain disagreement is to hold that the full conversational context determines (metaphysical) the values of the parameters, but the inference (epistemic) from the full conversational context to the values of the parameters is non-obvious. Just because the facts are determined doesn’t mean we will all figure out what they are. This leaves room for genuine disagreement about which context one is in and so genuine disagreement about which beliefs one ought to have.

The third way to retain disagreement is to hold that some instances of disagreement involve metalinguistic negotiation, that is, an exchange in which speakers tacitly negotiate the proper deployment of some linguistic expression in a context.Footnote 25 For example, defenders of Truth argue that the best norm of belief in some context is Truth while defenders of Rationality argue that the best norm of belief in some context is Rationality. This differs from the first way to retain disagreement because speakers need not believe that any parameter is metaphysically privileged to disagree about the aim of the conversation e.g. one person wants a conversation about the standards and another wants a conversation about rationality. Contextualism allows for genuine disagreement about which context to create. So this is best understood as a practical disagreement about what to do; that is, should we create a veritistic context or a rational context?

So the contextualist can make sense of the intuition that there is genuine disagreement between proponents of Truth and proponents of Rationality. But there may well be less disagreement than originally appeared, and the remaining disagreement might not be what it initially seemed to be i.e. a disagreement about the correct unique universal norm.

8. Conclusion

Many philosophers distinguish different senses of ‘ought’, for example, objective and subjective. I have argued that systematizing these different senses of ‘ought’ in a contextualist framework helps clarify the debate about the norms of belief. Contextualism allows us to explain the conflicting intuitions that have generated the opposing positions in the epistemology literature. We have identified three norms:

Contextualist Truth

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff P’ is true.

Contextualist Ideal Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff it is ideally rational for S to believe that P’ is true.

Contextualist Bounded Rationality

For any agent S and any proposition P:

In some contexts: ‘S ought to believe that P iff it is boundedly rational for S to believe that P’ is true.

Rather than defending one norm (or more) and biting the bullet on the conflicting intuitions, we can explain the appeal of various incompatible positions in terms of different values of the parameters.Footnote 26

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the Templeton Foundation for partial support while working on this project and to several referees for helpful comments.

For the purpose of open access, the author has applied a Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) licence to any author accepted manuscript version arising from this submission.

Footnotes

1 For discussions of contextualism about normative terms, see Wedgwood (Reference Wedgwood2006, Reference Wedgwood2007: ch. 5, Reference Wedgwood, Charlow and Chrisman2016); Brogaard (Reference Brogaard2008); Kolodny and MacFarlane (Reference Kolodny and MacFarlane2010) and Björnsson and Finlay (Reference Björnsson and Finlay2010); Dowell (Reference Dowell2012, Reference Dowell2013); Charlow (Reference Charlow2013), Cariani, Kaufmann, and Kaufmann (Reference Cariani, Kaufmann and Kaufmann2013), Carr (Reference Carr2015), and Chrisman (Reference Chrisman2015); Silk (Reference Silk2017); Khoo and Knobe (Reference Khoo and Knobe2018); and Worsnip (Reference Worsnip2019). This work is strongly influenced by Kratzer (Reference Kratzer, Eikmeyer and Rieser1981, Reference Kratzer, von Stechow and Wunderlich1991, Reference Kratzer2012). For earlier forerunners of contextualism in metaethics, see Geach (Reference Geach1956), Foot (Reference Foot1972), Harman (Reference Harman1975, Reference Harman, Harman and Thomson1996), and Dreier (Reference Dreier1990).

2 Contextualism on this topic has usually been aired only to be rejected (e.g., Gibbons Reference Gibbons2013). One precedent is Feldman (Reference Feldman2000). His ‘epistemic ought’ can be understood as being relativized to a specific goal-parameter. But my theory is quite different from Feldman’s. The most salient difference is that Feldman defends evidentialism, which says roughly that one ought to have the doxastic attitude best supported by your evidence. By contrast, contextualism says that evidentialism results when ‘ought’ is relativized to a particular parameter, while other theories result from different parameter values. Another precedent is Lord (Reference Lord2015) who looks all set to offer a contextualist dissolution of the debate but doesn’t do so. Instead, he argues for a perspectival view, offering this as the correct reading of the ‘deliberative’ ought. See also Lord (Reference Lord2018).

3 See Ross (Reference Ross1939, p. 46–167), Parfit (Reference Parfit1986, p. 25), and Jackson (Reference Jackson1991) for classic discussions of objective versus subjective ought.

4 I’ve used the strong, bi-conditional version of Truth because I think even this can be reconciled with Rationality given contextualism. I say more at the end of Section 5.

5 See Williams (Reference Williams1981). Williams’ focus is on reasons, and mine is on ‘ought’, but, as I say above, the contextualist framework can be naturally extended to other normative terms such as ‘reasons’.

6 The conflict could be avoided by denying that a belief can be rational and false (e.g. Sutton Reference Sutton2007).

7 See fn. 1 of McHugh (Reference McHugh2012) for a more comprehensive list.

8 Gibbons ends up defending Rationality.

9 See Glüer and Wikforss (Reference Glüer and Wikforss2009, Reference Glüer and Wikforss2010) and Steglich-Petersen (Reference Steglich-Petersen2006, Reference Steglich-Petersen2010, Reference Steglich-Petersen2013a, Reference Steglich-Petersen and Chan2013b). This sort of motivation for Rationality can be found in the literature on evidentialism (Conee and Feldman Reference Conee, Feldman, Conee and Feldman1985) and internalism (Alston Reference Alston1989, Conee and Feldman Reference Conee and Feldman2001).

10 See Gibbons (Reference Gibbons2013) for a book length defence of a version of Rationality.

11 The standard view is Kratzer’s (Reference Kratzer, Eikmeyer and Rieser1981). I use this for concreteness, but I leave open that there are other ways to implement the semantic variability I need. See Viebahn and Vetter (Reference Viebahn and Vetter2016) for non-contextualist semantic variability.

12 The headteacher would not demand omniscience. So perhaps this should be limited to a context in which the student ought to believe the conjunction of what is true and what is on the syllabus.

13 ‘Know’ is the natural locution, which we can assume entails belief.

14 Why have I claimed that the contexts at issue shift the goal but not the live possible worlds? Because we have not eliminated the live possible worlds in which Bernard believes there is gin in the glass or S believes Moscow is the capital of Russia. They could still believe these things.

15 See Alston (Reference Alston1985, p. 83–4), BonJour (Reference BonJour1985, p. 7–8), and Wedgwood (Reference Wedgwood2002) among others.

16 See Bykvist and Hattiangadi (Reference Bykvist and Hattiangadi2007) for criticism.

17 See McHugh (Reference McHugh2012) for a similar point.

18 More precisely, Hughes argues that on some ways of thinking about guidance, Rationality cannot always provide guidance. Hughes does not think Rationality should be rejected; his aim is to defend Truth (and Rationality) despite them both being unable to always provide guidance.

19 Srinivasan (Reference Srinivasan2015) argues that no norm can always provide guidance as there is no nontrivial mental state such that we are always in a position to know that we are in it. I discuss this objection in (ms).

20 See Gigerenzer (Reference Gigerenzer2008), Reference MortonMorton (2017), and Wheeler (Reference Wheeler2020). See also Eder (Reference Eder2021) for a related distinction between guidance and assessment norms of rationality.

21 Is there a sense in which they can do what is ideally rational? They might form the ideal belief by luck. But this is not the sense of ‘can’ being used here. ‘Can’ is also context-sensitive (Schwarz Reference Schwarz2020). But we can hold fixed the meaning of ‘can’ in this discussion.

22 I do not say that all biases are boundedly rational. Some might be positively irrational, in which case they are not candidates to be norms of bounded rationality.

23 This is Gibbons’ (Reference Gibbons2013 ch. 3) objection to contextualism. He puts it in terms of disagreement about acceptance of a code of conduct (p. 63).

24 A similar view has been discussed in detail in Eklund (Reference Eklund2017).

25 See Plunkett and Sundell (Reference Plunkett and Sundell2013).

26 I am grateful to funding body x and….

References

Alston, W. (1989). Epistemic Justification. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alston, W.P. (1985). ‘Concepts of Epistemic Justification.’ The monist 68(1), 5789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bales, R.E. (1971). ‘Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?’ American Philosophical Quarterly 8(3), 257265.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G., & Finlay, S. (2010). ‘Metaethical Contextualism Defended.’ Ethics 121, 736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Google scholar, vol. 2, pp. 305321. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brogaard, B. (2008). ‘Moral Contextualism and Moral Relativism.’ Philosophical Quarterly 58(232), 385409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bykvist, K., & Hattiangadi, A. (2007). ‘Does Thought Imply Ought?Analysis 67(296), 277–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cariani, F., Kaufmann, M., & Kaufmann, S. (2013). ‘Deliberative Modality under Epistemic Uncertainty.’ Linguistics and Philosophy 36(3), 225259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, J. (2015). ‘Subjective Ought.’ Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 2, 678710.Google Scholar
Charlow, N. (2013). ‘What We Know and What to Do.’ Synthese 190(12), 22912323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1977). Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edition. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Chrisman, M. (2015). The Meaning of ‘Ought’: Beyond Descriptivism and Expressivism inMetaethics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1985). ‘Evidentialism.’ In Conee, E. and Feldman, R. (eds), Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology. 2004. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2001). ‘Internalism Defended.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 38(1), 118.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1971). ‘Intentional Systems.’ Journal of Philosophy 68, 87106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dowell, J. (2012). ‘Contextualist Solutions to Three Puzzles about Practical Conditionals.’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics 7, 271303.Google Scholar
Dowell, J. (2013). ‘Flexible Contextualism about Deontic Modals: A Puzzle about Information-Sensitivity.’ Inquiry 56(2-3), 149178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreier, J. (1990). ‘Internalism and Speaker Relativism.’ Ethics 101, 626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eder, A.M.A. (2021). ‘Explicating the Concept of Epistemic Rationality.’ Synthese 199(1–2), 49755000.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eklund, M. (2017). Choosing Normative Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2000). ‘The Ethics of Belief.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60(3), 667–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, S. (2014). Confusion of Tongues: A Theory of Normative Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. (1972). ‘Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives.’ The Philosophical Review 81(3), 305316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. (1956). ‘Good and Evil.’ Analysis 17(2), 3342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbons, J. (2013). The Norm of Belief. USA: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Rationality for Mortals: How People Cope with Uncertainty. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, K., & Wikforss, Å. (2009). ‘Against Content Normativity.’ Mind 118, 3170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, K., & Wikforss, Å. (2010). ‘The Truth Norm and Guidance: A Reply to Steglich-Petersen.’ Mind 119, 757–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (1999). Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (2001). ‘The Unity of the Epistemic Virtues.’ In Fairweather, A. and Zagzebski, L. (eds), Virtue Epistemology: Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, pp. 3048. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I. (2015). ‘Reliabilism, Veritism, and Epistemic Consequentialism.’ Episteme 12(2), 131143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1975). ‘Moral Relativism Defended.’ The Philosophical Review 84, 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1996). ‘Moral Relativism.’ In Harman, G. and Thomson, J. (eds), Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hughes, N. (2019). ‘Dilemmic Epistemology.’ Synthese 196, 4059–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, N. (2021a). ‘Epistemology Without Guidance.’ Philosophical Studies 179(1), 163–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, N. (2021b). ‘Who’s Afraid of Epistemic Dilemmas?’ In Epistemic Dilemmas, pp. 253268. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, N. (forthcoming). ‘Epistemic Dilemmas Defended’.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. (1991). ‘Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection.’ Ethics 101(3), 461482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J.M. (1998). ‘A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.’ Philosophy of Science 65(4), 575603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khoo, J., & Knobe, J. (2018). ‘Moral Disagreement and Moral Semantics.’ Noûs 52(1), 109143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). ‘Ifs and Oughts.’ Journal of Philosophy 107(3),115143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1981). ‘The Notional Category of Modality.’ In Eikmeyer, H.-J. and Rieser, H. (eds), Words, Worlds, and Contexts: New Approaches in World Semantics, pp. 3874. de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1991). ‘Modality.’ In von Stechow, A. and Wunderlich, D. (eds), Semantics: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research, pp. 639650. de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1972). ‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications.’ in Block 1980, 207215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a Language Game. Semantics from different points of view/Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1996). ‘Elusive Knowledge.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74(4).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lord, E. (2015). ‘Acting for the Right Reasons, Abilities, and Obligation.’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics 10, 2652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lord, E. (2018). The Importance of Being Rational. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McHugh, C. (2012). ‘The Truth Norm of Belief.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93(1), 830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morton, J.M. (2017). ‘Reasoning under Scarcity.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95(3), 543–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. (1986). Reasons and Persons. OUP Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plunkett, D., & Sundell, T. (2013). ‘Disagreement and the Semantics of Normative and Evaluative Terms.’ Philosophers, 13(23), 137.Google Scholar
Ross, D. (1939). Foundations of Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schoenfield, M. (2018). ‘An Accuracy Based Approach to Higher Order Evidence.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96(3), 690715.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2011). ‘Ought, Agents, and Actions.’ Philosophical Review 120(1), 141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, W. (2020). Ability and Possibility. Philosophers Imprint, 20, 6. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library.Google Scholar
Silk, A. (2017). ‘Normative Language in Context.’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12, 206–39.Google Scholar
Srinivasan, A. (2015). Normativity without Cartesian Privilege. Philosophical Issues 25, 273299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). ‘No Norm Needed: On the Aim of Belief.’ The Philosophical Quarterly 56(225), 499516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2010). ‘The Truth Norm and Guidance: A Reply to Glüer and Wikforss.’ Mind 119(475), 749–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2013a). ‘The No Guidance Argument.’ Theoria 79(1), 279–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2013b). ‘Truth as the Aim of Epistemic Justification.’ In Chan, T. (ed.), The Aim of Belief, pp. 204226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinberger, F. (2019). ‘Three Ways in which Logic Might be Normative.’ The Journal of Philosophy 116(1), 531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sutton, J. (2007). Without Justification. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viebahn, E., & Vetter, B. (2016). ‘How Many Meanings for ‘May’? The Case for Modal Polysemy.’ Philosopher’s Imprint, 16(10).Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2002). ‘The Aim of Belief.’ Philosophical Perspectives 16, 267–97.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2006). ‘The meaning of “ought”.’ In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 1, pp. 127160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2007). The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2016). ‘Objective and Subjective ’Ought’.’ In Charlow, N. and Chrisman, M. (eds), Deontic Modality, pp. 143168. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheeler, G. (2020). ‘Bounded Rationality.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/bounded-rationality/>>Google Scholar
Whiting, D. (2013b). ‘Truth: The Aim and Norm of Belief.’ Teorema: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 32(3), 121–36.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1981). ‘Internal and External Reasons.’ In Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worsnip, A. (2019). ‘“Ought”-Contextualism Beyond the Parochial.’ Philosophical Studies 176(11), 30993119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worsnip, A. (2020). ‘Resisting Relativistic Contextualism: On Finlay’s Confusion of Tongues.’ Analysis 80(1), 122–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Two rankings for belief.