Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T14:33:56.227Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ON CUPPING AND AHMAD PAIRS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2022

ISKANDER SH. KALIMULLIN
Affiliation:
N.L. LOBACHEVSKY INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS AND MECHANICS KAZAN FEDERAL UNIVERSITY KAZAN 420008, RUSSIA E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://kpfu.ru/Iskander.Kalimullin?p_lang=2 E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://kpfu.ru/Mars.Yamaleev?p_lang=2
STEFFEN LEMPP
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN MADISON, WI 53706-1325, USA E-mail: [email protected] URL: http://www.math.wisc.edu/~lempp/
KENG NG*
Affiliation:
DIVISION OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES SCHOOL OF PHYSICAL & MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES COLLEGE OF SCIENCE NANYANG TECHNOLOGICAL UNIVERSITY, SINGAPORE URL: http://www.ntu.edu.sg/home/kmng/
MARS M. YAMALEEV
Affiliation:
N.L. LOBACHEVSKY INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS AND MECHANICS KAZAN FEDERAL UNIVERSITY KAZAN 420008, RUSSIA E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://kpfu.ru/Iskander.Kalimullin?p_lang=2 E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://kpfu.ru/Mars.Yamaleev?p_lang=2
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Working toward showing the decidability of the $\forall \exists $-theory of the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$-enumeration degrees, we prove that no so-called Ahmad pair of ${\Sigma ^0_2}$-enumeration degrees can join to ${\mathbf 0}_e'$.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Enumeration reducibility is a natural counterpart to its more famous cousin, Turing reducibility, and arises naturally as a notion of relative computability especially in computable model theory as well as, in slightly modified form, Ziegler reducibility in group theory.

This paper is devoted to the study of enumeration reducibility in terms of a degree structure, more specifically, the degree structure of the enumeration degrees of the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -sets, which can be defined also as those enumeration degrees below the degree ${\mathbf 0}_e'$ , i.e., the enumeration degree of the complement $\overline {K}$ of the halting problem $K = \{e \mid \varphi _e(e)\!\downarrow \,\}$ . (By this double characterization, the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees can be viewed as the counterpart of both the c.e. Turing degrees and the Turing degrees $\le {\mathbf 0}'$ , i.e., the $\Delta ^0_2$ -Turing degrees.)

One of the common questions about a degree structure viewed as a partial order is that of the complexity of its first-order theory as well as the decidability of fragments thereof. For most degree structures commonly being considered, the theory turns out to be as complicated as possible (i.e., equivalent to first-order or second-order arithmetic), while the $\exists $ -and often even the $\forall \exists $ -fragment is decidable and the $\exists \forall \exists $ -fragment is not.

For the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees, the first of these questions has been completely settled: The full first-order theory was shown to be undecidable by Slaman and Woodin [Reference Slaman and Woodin13], and equivalent to full first-order arithmetic by Ganchev and Soskova [Reference Ganchev and Soskova3].

As for the second question, the $\exists $ -fragment is easily seen to be decidable, whereas Kent [Reference Kent6] showed the $\exists \forall \exists $ -fragment to be undecidable. On the other hand, the decidability of the $\forall \exists $ -fragment remains open.

The decidability of the $\forall \exists $ -fragment can be rephrased algebraically as (uniformly effectively) deciding the following.

Question 1.1. For any given finite partial orders ${\mathcal P}$ and ${\mathcal Q}_i \supseteq {\mathcal P}$ (for $i \le n$ ), can any embedding of ${\mathcal P}$ into the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees be extended to an embedding of ${\mathcal Q}_i$ for some $i \le n$ (where i may depend on the particular embedding of ${\mathcal P}$ )?

Two major subproblems of Question 1.1 have been shown to be decidable:

  • Lempp, Slaman, and Sorbi [Reference Lempp, Slaman and Sorbi9] showed that the above question is decidable for $n=0$ , i.e., given any finite partial orders ${\mathcal P} \subseteq {\mathcal Q}$ , it is decidable whether any embedding of ${\mathcal P}$ into the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees can be extended to an embedding of ${\mathcal Q}$ .

  • Lempp and Sorbi [Reference Lempp and Sorbi10] showed that all finite lattices can be embedded, even preserving 0 and 1. (The lattice embeddings question can be seen as a disjunction of extending embeddings to certain one-point extensions ${\mathcal Q}_i$ of a finite lattice ${\mathcal P}$ viewed as a partial order.)

The ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees are often compared to the c.e. Turing degrees, where the situation is somewhat similar but also quite different in other respects: The full first-order theory is as complicated as first-order arithmetic by Slaman and Woodin (unpublished; see [Reference Nies, Shore and Slaman11]); the $\exists $ -fragment is easily seen to be decidable, whereas Lempp, Nies, and Slaman [Reference Lempp, Nies and Slaman8] showed the $\exists \forall \exists $ -fragment to be undecidable; the lattice embeddings problem for the c.e. Turing degrees remains one of the main open problems dating back to the 1960s (see [Reference Lempp, Lerman and Reed Solomon7] for the most recent update), and thus the decidability of the $\forall \exists $ -theory of the c.e. Turing degrees remains wide open as well.

The main algebraic difference between the c.e. Turing degrees and the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees was discovered by Ahmad in her Ph.D. thesis [Reference Ahmad1] (see [Reference Ahmad and Lachlan2, Corollary 3.2]): There are incomparable ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees ${\mathbf a}, {\mathbf b}$ (called an “Ahmad pair”) such that any degree ${\mathbf x} < {\mathbf a}$ is also $< {\mathbf b}$ . (This makes ${\mathbf a}$ “non-splitting” (i.e., join-irreducible) and thus cannot happen in the c.e. Turing degrees by the Sacks Splitting Theorem [Reference Sacks12].) More interestingly, even Ahmad also showed (see [Reference Ahmad and Lachlan2, Theorem 3.3]) that this phenomenon is not symmetric: For any two incomparable ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees ${\mathbf a}, {\mathbf b}$ , there is either a degree ${\mathbf x} < {\mathbf a}$ which is $\nleq {\mathbf b}$ , or there is a degree ${\mathbf y} < {\mathbf b}$ which is $\nleq {\mathbf a}$ .

In the language of Question 1.1, Ahmad’s results can be rephrased as stating that not every embedding of an antichain ${\mathcal P} = \{a,b\}$ can be extended to an embedding of ${\mathcal Q}_0 = \{a,b,x\}$ where $x<a$ and $x \nleq b$ , but that every embedding of ${\mathcal P}$ can be extended to an embedding of either ${\mathcal Q}_0$ or of ${\mathcal Q}_1 = \{a,b,y\}$ where $y<b$ and $y \nleq a$ .

One of the two main open questions extending the work of the second author, Slaman, and Sorbi [Reference Lempp, Slaman and Sorbi9] asks whether an Ahmad pair of ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees can join to the greatest ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degree ${\mathbf 0}_e'$ . In this paper, we answer this question (communicated to the second author in 2007 by Kent) in the negative:

Main Theorem. There is no cupping Ahmad pair of ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees $;$ i.e., given any two incomparable ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degrees ${\mathbf a}$ and ${\mathbf b}$ , there is either a ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -enumeration degree ${\mathbf x} < {\mathbf a}$ with ${\mathbf x} \nleq {\mathbf b}$ , or else ${\mathbf a} \cup {\mathbf b} < {\mathbf 0}_e'$ .

This result is a small part of a proposed framework for deciding the $\forall \exists $ -theory of the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -degrees, which is equivalent to deciding Question 1.1.

Given the difficulty of the overall problem of deciding the $\forall \exists $ -theory, researchers are currently concentrating on the following question concerning 1-point extensions:

Question 1.2. Given a finite antichain ${\mathcal P} = \{a_0, \dots , a_n\}$ and 1-point extensions ${\mathcal Q}_S = \{a_0, \dots , a_n, x_S\}$ and ${\mathcal Q}^T = \{a_0, \dots , a_n, x^T\}$ for some sets $S \in {\mathcal S}$ and $T \in {\mathcal T}$ (where ${\mathcal S}, {\mathcal T} \subseteq {\mathcal P}(\{0, \dots , n\}) - \{\emptyset \})$ ; $x_S < a_i$ iff $i \in S$ ; and $x^T> a_i$ iff $i \in T$ ), does any embedding of ${\mathcal P}$ into the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -degrees extend to an embedding into the ${\Sigma ^0_2}$ -degrees of ${\mathcal Q}_S$ for some $S \in {\mathcal S}$ or to an embedding of ${\mathcal Q}^T$ for some $T \in {\mathcal T}$ ?

Note that it is always possible to extend an embedding of a finite antichain ${\mathcal P}$ to an embedding of a larger antichain, so the case $S = T = \emptyset $ is not interesting. The subproblem involving only extensions ${\mathcal Q}^T$ is easy to see: We have extendibility iff there is a singleton $T \in {\mathcal T}$ .

Recent work of Goh, the second and third authors, and Soskova [Reference Goh, Ng, Lempp and Soskova4, Reference Goh, Ng, Lempp and Soskova5] gives a complete (and quite complicated) characterization of the subproblem involving only extensions ${\mathcal Q}_S$ .

We have no working conjecture that combines the ${\mathcal Q}_S$ and the ${\mathcal Q}^T$ ; our main result is the only result known to us in this direction.

2 The proof of the Main Theorem

This section is devoted to the proof of our Main Theorem.

2.1 Requirements

Rather than proving the result directly, we use an indirect approach, trying to “weakly split” the degree of A. Specifically, given two $\Sigma ^0_2$ -sets A and B and an enumeration operator $\Lambda $ such that $\overline {K} = \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ (K here denotes the usual Halting set), we construct two sets $X_0 = \Phi _0(A)$ and $X_1 = \Phi _1(A)$ with these enumeration operators and an enumeration operator $\Gamma $ , and meet the following requirements for all enumeration operators $\Delta $ :

$$ \begin{align*} \text{Global} &: A=\Gamma(B\oplus X_0\oplus X_1),\\ {\mathcal N}^0_\Delta &: A=\Delta(X_0)\Rightarrow \exists \Omega\,(A=\Omega(B)),\\ {\mathcal N}^1_\Delta &: A=\Delta(X_1)\Rightarrow \exists \Omega\,(A=\Omega(B)). \end{align*} $$

Here, the enumeration operators $\Omega $ are built locally by ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements; indeed, as we will see below, each ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement will build different versions of $\Omega $ based on different guesses about the higher-priority requirements.

If we succeed with these requirements, then we have that $A \le _e B$ , or that $X_0, X_1<_e A$ and $A \le _e B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1$ , and so the degrees of A and B clearly cannot form an Ahmad Pair. This corollary is non-uniform in two ways, in that we do not know whether $A \le _e B$ or which one (or both) of the $X_i$ is not below B, and even assuming $A \not \le _e B$ , we cannot tell uniformly which of $X_0$ or $X_1$ (or both) is now below B (in fact, these non-uniformities are unavoidable, as can be shown).

The construction will be a finite-injury construction. The global requirement should proceed carefully to ensure that we do not end up with a “runaway” $\Gamma $ -axiom. The other requirements will be ordered in some way in order type $\omega $ which determines their priority.

Our construction uses the Recursion Theorem with Parameters in that we will define “agitators” that we enumerate into the Halting set K, which will then force $A \oplus B$ to change. More precisely, we assume that we are given an infinite computable list of indices $i_0,i_1,\dots $ for which we are able to define $\varphi _{i_y}$ for every y. This allows us to be able to use any of these indices as an “agitator.” For any choice of ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement, stage s, and potentially numbers a and strings $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ , we may define agitators $p_{a,\sigma }$ and q for the ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement at stage s, picked from the aforementioned list of agitators, and the Recursion Theorem with Parameters allows us to assume that we know what corresponding number will enter K when we enumerate an agitator.

2.1.1 Agitators and the use of the Recursion Theorem

We provide more details about agitators and the use of the Recursion Theorem here; the reader who is familiar with this may skip this subsection. As mentioned above, we assume that we are given an infinite computable list of indices $i_0,i_1,\dots $ for which we are able to control the value of $K(i_y)$ for every y. What this means is that for any y, we can assume that $i_y\not \in K$ until we choose to enumerate it into K (via making a definition $\varphi _{i_y}(i_y))$ . If we never choose to enumerate $i_y$ into K, then it will never appear in $K_s$ for any s; otherwise, if we choose to enumerate it into K, then it must appear in $K_s$ for some large s which we can then wait for by speeding up the approximation to $K_s$ .

Now it remains to justify the existence of the sequence $i_0,i_1,\dots $ . To do this, we require the use of the Recursion Theorem with Parameters, applied in the following way. We perform infinitely many constructions, rather than just the one described in the proof, and each construction is given a different label $c\in \omega $ . These constructions are performed uniformly, and each differs only on the assigned label c. In each construction, we build infinitely many partial computable functions $h_{c,0},h_{c,1},\dots $ representing the list of potential agitators in that construction. The construction will guess that $h_{c,y}$ has index $\varphi _c(c,y)$ for each y, where c is its assigned label. That is, the construction believes that $h_{c,y}=\varphi _{\varphi _c(c,y)}$ for every y. All constructions proceed in exactly the same way, except for its guess on the indices for the sequence $h_{c,0},h_{c,1},\dots $ . This allows us to use the s-m-n Theorem to obtain a computable function f such that $h_{c,y} = \varphi _{f(\varphi _c(c,y),c,y)}$ for every c and y. The Recursion Theorem with Parameters gives an index c such that $h_{c,y}=\varphi _{f(\varphi _c(c,y),c,y)}=\varphi _{\varphi _c(c,y)}$ holds for every y. Now the construction which was assigned label c will have the correct guesses on the indices of the agitators.

2.2 Basic strategies for the requirements

We fix a computable enumeration $\{K_s\}$ of K, and let $\overline {K}_s$ be the complement of $K_s$ . By speeding up the enumeration of $\Lambda $ and the approximations to A and B, we may assume at any stage s that for all numbers $p<s$ , if $p \in \overline {K}_s$ , then currently $p \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ , and if $p \notin \overline {K}_s$ , then any axiom putting p into $\Lambda (A \oplus B)$ at stage $s-1$ will no longer apply at stage s.

The global requirement constructing the operator $\Gamma $ will enumerate axioms into $\Gamma $ taking into account more and more of the other requirements’ action; the basic action of the global requirement is to just enumerate an axiom for a into $\Gamma $ whenever it sees a enter A. Specifically, for each $a \in A$ , we associate with a fresh numbers $c^i_a>a$ targeted for $X_i$ for $i<2$ ; we then enumerate $c^i_a$ into $X_i$ via the $\Phi _i$ -axioms $\langle c^i_a,\{a\} \rangle $ , and we enumerate a new axiom $\langle a,B_a \oplus C^0_a \oplus C^1_a \rangle $ into $\Gamma $ where $B_a$ is some finite subset of B, and $C^i_a$ is a finite subset of $X_i$ containing $c^i_a$ and possibly other numbers determined later; this will result in $a \in \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ . Now, when a leaves A, this will remove $c^0_a$ from $X_0$ and $c^1_a$ from $X_1$ unless we introduce additional axioms for either of these numbers. (More generally, ensuring $C^0_a \not \subseteq X_0$ or $C^1_a \not \subseteq X_1$ or $B_a \not \subseteq B$ would suffice, as will be required later.)

The basic strategy for the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement is to try to show that $A = \Omega (B)$ as follows: At each stage, the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement determines the oldest $a \in A$ (if any) which has not yet been confirmed (as defined precisely below) and checks if there is currently some F such that $a \in \Delta (F)$ ; if no such F exists, the requirement does nothing for now. If there is such F, the requirement declares a to be confirmed and dumps all $x \in F$ into $X_i$ by enumerating axioms $\langle x,\emptyset \rangle $ into $\Phi _i$ (and thus ensures that $a \in \Delta (X_i)$ permanently); it also chooses a fresh agitator $p_a$ , keeps $p_a \in \overline {K}$ for now, and waits for $p_a \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ (which must happen by the first stage $s>p_a$ ) via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle p_a,F_a \oplus G_a \rangle $ , say, for which all $a' \in F_a$ have been confirmed already (which need not ever happen). The ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement then enumerates a into $\Omega (B)$ via the $\Omega $ -axiom $\langle a,G_a \rangle $ . If $p_a$ leaves $\Lambda (A \oplus B)$ before we enumerate $p_a$ into K (if ever), then we wait again for a to re-enter $\Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a possibly different $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle p_a,F^{\prime }_a \oplus G^{\prime }_a \rangle $ (such that again all $a' \in F^{\prime }_a$ are confirmed); then we will use the (possibly different) set $G^{\prime }_a$ in redefining $a \in \Omega (B)$ , etc.; this can happen only finitely often for this fixed $p_a$ . If a leaves A after a is confirmed, then we enumerate the current agitator $p_a$ into K; if later a re-enters A, then we pick a new, fresh agitator $p^{\prime }_a$ , say, for which we proceed as above (finding sets $F^{\prime }_a$ and $G^{\prime }_a$ and enumerating an $\Omega $ -axiom $\langle a,G^{\prime }_a \rangle $ , etc.). From now on, whenever some agitator $p_a \in K$ and for any corresponding set $G_a$ , we see $G_a \subseteq B$ , then the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement stops (since it believes that $F_a \not \subseteq A$ while $F_a \subseteq \Delta (X_i)$ by dumping). Note that if a is truly in A, then the final agitator $p_a$ for a will stabilize and be in $\overline {K}$ ; on the other hand, if $a \notin A$ then a will either appear to be outside A at cofinitely many stages, or the agitator will never stabilize, and any temporary agitator $p_a$ will eventually be in K.

We need to check two things: First of all, note that the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement can act only finitely often unless $A = \Omega (B)$ (which would contradict our hypotheses): If the requirement acts for the sake of infinitely many distinct a, then, since we always choose a by age, we will have for each $a \in A$ that a will be confirmed and that $a \in \Omega (B)$ by an axiom using the final agitator $p_a \in \overline {K}$ and the B-part $G_a$ of its $\Lambda $ -use; and for each $a \notin A$ we will have that $a \notin \Omega (B)$ since no $\Omega $ -axiom can apply: If $a \in \Omega (B)$ via some axiom $\langle a,G_a \rangle $ , say, but $a \notin A$ , then $G_a$ is the B-part of the $\Lambda $ -use of some agitator $p_a$ , but every such agitator $p_a$ will be enumerated into K and thus $G_a \subseteq B$ will eventually stop the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement permanently. On the other hand, the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement cannot act infinitely often for some fixed $a_0$ since that would mean that $a_0 \notin A$ and so the age of $a_0$ would keep increasing and we would choose other numbers infinitely often (assuming here, of course, that A is infinite).

The second item we need to check is that the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement satisfies its requirement, so assume that indeed $A = \Delta (X_i)$ : Then every a truly in A must be confirmed eventually, but since we may assume A to be infinite, this means that the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement acts infinitely often and thus ensures $A = \Omega (B)$ as shown in the previous paragraph.

2.3 Conflicts between the ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements and the global requirement

A single ${\mathcal N}^i$ -requirement will not conflict with the global requirement building and correcting $\Gamma $ since when a leaves A, $\Gamma $ can always be corrected by extracting $c^{1-i}_a$ from $X_{1-i}$ (as no requirement has dumped that number into $X_{1-i}$ so far).

So let’s consider the case of a higher-priority ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement above a lower-priority ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement: The main difficulty is that any number $x_0$ dumped by the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement is associated with some number a potentially in A, which in turn may be associated with a number $x_1$ that the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement may dump into $X_1$ , so if both $x_0$ and $x_1$ are dumped, then we may not be able to correct $\Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ if a leaves A, injuring the global requirement.

So the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement, assuming that the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement acts only finitely often, will be modified as follows: Each time the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement acts, the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement’s action will be completely undone by enumerating an agitator q (chosen by the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement) into K, which will force an $(A \oplus B)$ -change undoing all $\Gamma $ -axioms enumerated since the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement was last active (and thus any $\Gamma $ -axioms enumerated while the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement was active since then), where $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q,F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ , say; now the numbers in $F_q$ are associated with sets of numbers $F^i_q$ in $X_i$ for $i<2$ , and so we may assume that each $\Gamma $ -axiom enumerated since the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement was last active contains $B_q \oplus C^0_q \oplus C^1_q$ in its use; thus we will now ensure that when q enters K, this will entail $B_q \oplus C^0_q \oplus C^1_q \not \subseteq B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1$ . This feature will thus prevent the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement from interfering with the global requirement as long as the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement cannot unconditionally dump numbers into $X_1$ like the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement.

In addition to this extra initialization, we will now modify the strategy for the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement as follows: Let r be a strict bound on the largest number ever considered by the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement up to this stage, and assume that this bound is reset each time the computation for $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ changes. (If the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement acts only finitely often, then this number will stabilize eventually.)

The ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement will now be prevented from making any changes to $X_1$ at any number $<r$ and will work with all possible guesses $\sigma \in 2^r$ about $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ . (Recall here that any number x potentially in $X_1$ is associated with a number $a<x$ potentially in A, or with no number at all, so a guess about $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ will eventually give complete information about $X_1 {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ .) Each version of the strategy for the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement (let’s call it the ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy) will build its own version of the enumeration operator $\Omega $ (call it $\Omega _\sigma $ ); each ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy will now act independently, building not only its own $\Omega _\sigma $ but also define its own agitators $p_a = p_{a,\sigma }$ . (On the other hand, the agitator q is attached to an entire requirement and so can be joint for all ${\mathcal N}$ -strategies working for the same requirement since this is a finite-injury argument.)

Each ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy will then, instead of dumping a number $x<r$ into $X_1$ , simply check if its guess about $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ and about $\Phi _1$ puts x into $X_1$ , and this guess will eventually be correct about each such x; for numbers $x \ge r$ , the ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy can still simply “dump” numbers into $X_1$ but only with the set $F_q$ (from the $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q, F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ ) in the A-part of the $\Phi _1$ -use. (Also, the strategy will stop if it sees a number $a \in A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ with $\sigma (a)=0$ .) Note that this is sufficient to allow the global strategy to correct $\Gamma $ whenever necessary: If any number a leaves A, then the global strategy can either use $X_0$ to correct $\Gamma $ if the $\Gamma $ -axiom for $a \in \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ was defined after the stage $s_r$ , say, at which the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement last acted (since no strategy will have dumped any number $\ge r$ into $X_0$ up to this point), or it can use $X_1$ or B if the $\Gamma $ -axiom for $a \in \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ was defined before stage $s_r$ (since any number dumped into $X_1$ before stage $s_r$ must have been dumped by an ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy before r was last increased, and thus the corresponding agitator q of the ${\mathcal N}^0$ -requirement from that time was enumerated into K, resulting in a B-change, or in an A- and thus an $X_0$ -change, invalidating any $\Gamma $ -axiom for a that might involve a number dumped by an ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy in its use).

We now have to verify two things: Firstly, the ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy with the correct guess $\sigma = A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ will ensure the satisfaction of the ${\mathcal N}^1$ -requirement. And secondly, any ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy will act at most finitely often even if its guess $\sigma $ about $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ is incorrect.

So suppose first that r is the final value of this parameter and fix $\sigma = A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ . Then, starting at some stage $s_r$ , any number $x \in X_1 {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ will forever be in $X_1 = \Phi _1(A)$ . So starting at stage $s_r$ , the ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy can act like the ${\mathcal N}$ -strategy in isolation except that it cannot dump any number $x<r$ into $X_1$ , but no such number will be truly in $X_1$ unless it is so by stage $s_r$ , so this does not cause more than finitely many mistakes for $\Omega _\sigma $ in case the ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy acts infinitely often.

Next, fix any ${\mathcal N}^1_\sigma $ -strategy (irrespective of whether $\sigma = A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ or not). In order to show that this strategy acts at most finitely often, we distinguish two cases: If $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r \not \subseteq \sigma $ , fix the oldest element $a \in A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ with $\sigma (a)=0$ ; in that case, the strategy clearly stops as soon as a no longer leaves A. On the other hand, if $A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r \subseteq \sigma $ , then the strategy will act as in isolation (since it will never want to dump a number into $X_1$ that it cannot dump) and so must also eventually stop unless $A \le _e B$ .

This concludes the presentation of the intuition behind our construction; we are now ready to describe it formally in full.

2.4 The full construction

Recall that we are given approximations to $\Sigma ^0_2$ -sets A and B and an enumeration operator $\Lambda $ such that at any stage s, for any number $p<s$ , if $p \in \overline {K}_s$ then $p \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)[s]$ , and if $p \in K_s$ then p is not in both $\Lambda (A \oplus B)[s-1]$ and $\Lambda (A \oplus B)[s]$ via the same axiom. Furthermore, we may assume to be given a good approximation $\{A_s \oplus B_s\}_{s \in \omega }$ (of finite sets) to $A \oplus B$ , i.e., there are infinitely many true stages, namely, stages s with $A_s \oplus B_s \subseteq A \oplus B$ .

Since we have a finite-injury construction with one global requirement, the action at each stage s will consist of a single action for the highest-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement requiring attention, followed by some global action. At stage 0, all ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements are initialized and all functionals and agitators are set to be undefined.

We say that an ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy (for $\sigma \in 2^r$ and some $r \in \omega $ ) requires attention if:

  • there is no $a \in A_s {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ with $\sigma (a)=0$ ; and

  • there is no agitator $p_a \in K_s$ with $G_a \subseteq B_s$ for the corresponding $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle p_a, F_a \oplus G_a \rangle $ where $p_a = p_{a,\sigma '}$ is any agitator ever used by an ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma '}$ -strategy working for the same ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement; and

  • one of the following four conditions holds:

    1. (1) there is some $a \in \Omega (B)[s] - A_s$ (with the oldest $\Omega $ -axiom applicable); or

    2. (2) there is some (oldest) $a \in A_s - \Omega (B)[s]$ which has already been confirmed by the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy (since its last initialization) via F, say, and each $a' \in F$ has also already been confirmed by the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy (since its last initialization); or

    3. (3) there is some (oldest) $a \in A_s$ which has not yet been confirmed by the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy (since its last initialization) and for which there is a finite set F (of least canonical index) with $F {\,\upharpoonright \,} r = \Phi _i(\sigma ) {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ and $a \in \Delta _s(F)$ ; or

    4. (4) all the strategies for this ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement have not acted since they were last initialized.

If an ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy requires attention, we also say that the corresponding ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement requires attention.

At a stage $s>0$ , we first check if there is a (highest-priority) ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement requiring attention; if so, allow all ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategies working for this ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement to act if they require attention. Each such ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy will now act according to the first clause of the third bullet that applies.

If (1) applies, then the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy enumerates into K the agitator $p_a = p_{a,\sigma }$ which was chosen when the current $\Omega _\sigma $ -axiom for $a \in \Omega _\sigma (B)$ was defined. (Note that $p_a \notin K_s$ since otherwise, the second bullet would have prevented the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement from requiring attention.)

If (2) applies, then the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy, for the current agitator $p_a = p_{a,\sigma }$ and the (oldest) $\Lambda $ -axiom putting $p_a \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ with use $F_a \oplus G_a$ , enumerates the axiom $\langle a,G_a \rangle $ into $\Omega _\sigma $ .

If (3) applies, then the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy declares a to be confirmed via F, chooses a fresh agitator $p_a$ , and enumerates all of $F - [0,r)$ (for the threshold r imposed on this requirement) into $\Phi _i(A)$ with use including all $F_q$ for all agitators $q \in \overline {K}$ defined by strategies for higher-priority requirements (where $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via an (oldest) $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q,F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ ). If now (2) applies to this a, then continue as for that case, else proceed to the global action for this stage.

If one of (1)–(3) applies, then we also enumerate into K the agitator q of the ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement for which we acted at this stage, choose a new fresh agitator q, choose a new threshold r above all numbers mentioned so far which will be imposed on the lower-priority strategies, and initialize all lower-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -strategies.

If (4) applies, then the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement, i.e., the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategies (for all $\sigma \in 2^r$ , where r is the threshold imposed by the higher-priority strategies) simply defines a new threshold $r'$ above all numbers mentioned so far which is imposed on all lower-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -strategies.

After the strategies for an ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement have acted, the global requirement building $\Gamma $ will act. First of all, as we will show in the verification below (see Lemma 2.3), since all corrections will be automatic there will never be a number a and a stage s such that $a \in \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1) - A$ . So the global requirement will simply identify the (oldest) $a \in A - \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ (which must exist since A is infinite), let Q be the set of all current agitators q of ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements whose current threshold r is less than $<a$ , and then enumerate an axiom $\langle a, B_a \oplus C^0_a \oplus C^1_a \rangle $ into $\Gamma $ where:

  • $B_a$ contains all sets $G_q$ such that $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q, F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ for some $q \in Q$ and some finite set $F_q$ ,

  • $C^0_a$ contains all $c^0_{a'}$ for all $a' \in F_q$ such that $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q, F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ for some $q \in Q$ and some finite sets $F_q$ and $G_q$ , as well as a freshly chosen number $c^0_a$ for which we enumerate $c^0_a$ into $X_0$ via a $\Phi _0$ -axiom $\langle c^0_a,\{a\} \rangle $ , and

  • $C^1_a$ contains all $c^1_{a'}$ for all $a' \in F_q$ such that $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q, F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ for some $q \in Q$ and some finite sets $F_q$ and $G_q$ , as well as a freshly chosen number $c^1_a$ for which we enumerate $c^1_a$ into $X_1$ via a $\Phi _1$ -axiom $\langle c^1_a,\{a\} \rangle $ .

In the last two bullets above, for each $a'$ , if there is no $c^i_{a'}$ (for $i<2$ ) which has not yet been dumped and for which there is a $\Phi _i$ -axiom $\langle c^i_{a'},\{a'\} \rangle $ , then we pick a fresh such number $c^i_{a'}$ for the $\Gamma $ -axiom, enumerate a corresponding axiom $\langle c^i_{a'},\{a'\} \rangle $ into $\Phi _i$ , and use it in the above $\Gamma $ -axiom. Also, recall here that each current agitator $q \in Q$ must be in $\overline {K}$ and thus in $\Lambda (A \oplus B)$ .

This concludes the formal description of the construction.

2.5 Verification

We now verify that our construction satisfies the requirements in a number of lemmas. In addition to assuming that $\overline {K} = \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ and that $A \oplus B$ has a good approximation, we will also assume tacitly throughout that $A \not \le _e B$ and in particular that A is infinite.

We start by verifying that our construction is indeed finite injury:

Lemma 2.1. Each ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement acts at most finitely often and eventually defines a final threshold r and a final agitator q which is in $\overline {K} ($ unless it does not have an eventual agitator at all $)$ .

Proof We proceed by induction on the priority of the ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement. So fix an ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement and assume the lemma for all higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements. Fix a (least) stage $s_0$ such that no higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement acts after stage $s_0$ . Let $r_0$ be the maximum of the final thresholds of all these higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements, and let Q be the set of the final agitators of all these higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements.

Let’s now analyze how the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement can require attention after stage $s_0$ : First of all, observe that clause (4) of the third bullet can apply at most once after stage $s_0$ .

For the sake of a contradiction, assume that an ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy acts infinitely often. By the first bullet in the conditions for requiring attention, there can be no $a \in A$ with $\sigma (a)=0$ .

Furthermore, clause (3) of the third bullet must apply infinitely often (and thus infinitely many a will be confirmed by the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy), since clauses (1) and (2) of the third bullet can possibly apply to a fixed a only if $a \notin A$ , but then the age of a keeps increasing and, since A is infinite, infinitely many other numbers must take precedence in requiring attention. This implies, by age and clause (3) of the third bullet, that each $a \in A$ must eventually be confirmed, and so, since the first bullet fails for $\sigma $ , $a \in \Delta (X_i)$ . But then there will be a final agitator $p_a = p_{a,\sigma }$ , which will be in $\overline {K}$ and thus in $\Lambda (A \oplus B)$ via a $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle p_a, F_a \oplus G_a \rangle $ , say. Thus $a \in \Omega _\sigma (B)$ via the axiom $\langle a,G_a \rangle $ . Conversely, if $a \notin A$ , then any axiom $\langle a,G_a \rangle $ enumerated into $\Omega _\sigma $ cannot apply and put $a \in \Omega _\sigma (B)$ since otherwise, $G_a \subseteq B$ while the corresponding agitator $p_a \notin \overline {K}$ , so the second bullet for requiring attention will eventually prevent any ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -strategy from acting. We have thus shown that an ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy acting infinitely often will imply $A = \Omega _\sigma (B)$ , contrary to assumption.

Thus the ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement will act at most finitely often and eventually define a final threshold r and a final agitator q (if there is an agitator q ever defined).

Note that the action of the global requirement does not interfere with any of the above argument.

We next verify that each ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement is satisfied.

Lemma 2.2. Each ${\mathcal N}^i_\Delta $ -requirement is satisfied.

Proof Suppose that $A = \Delta (X_i)$ . Fix the final threshold r of the higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements and set $\sigma = A {\,\upharpoonright \,} r$ . We will show that the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy acts infinitely often, contradicting Lemma 2.1.

First, note that for each a, the first and second bullets of requiring attention will eventually not prevent the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy from acting. (This is clear for the first bullet by definition of $\sigma $ , and for the second bullet, we argue that otherwise, $p_a \in K$ and $G_a \subseteq B$ implies $p_a \notin \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ and so $F_a \not \subseteq A$ , say, $a' \in F_a - A$ . But $a'$ is confirmed, so $ \in \Delta (X_i) - A$ , contradicting our assumption.)

But now $A = \Delta (X_i)$ implies that every $a \in A$ will be confirmed, implying that the ${\mathcal N}^i_{\Delta ,\sigma }$ -strategy acts infinitely often, again contradicting Lemma 2.1.

Finally, we need to verify that the global requirement is satisfied.

Lemma 2.3. The global requirement is satisfied: $A = \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ .

Proof We need to prove two directions. Assume first that $a \in A$ , so we need to verify that some $\Gamma $ -axiom will eventually put a into $\Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ . So find a stage s such that all thresholds r of ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements with $r<a$ , as well as their potential agitators q, have settled down. Then for each such agitator q, $q \in \overline {K}$ and thus there will be a stable $\Lambda $ -axiom $\langle q, F_q \oplus G_q \rangle $ putting $q \in \Lambda (A \oplus B)$ , say, all of this happens by a stage $s' \ge s$ . Then by stage $s'$ , the global strategy will have enumerated a $\Gamma $ -axiom $\langle a, B_a \oplus C^0_a \oplus C^1_a \rangle $ with $B_a \subseteq B$ and $C^i_a \subseteq X_i$ for $i<2$ , and so $a \in \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ .

Conversely, suppose $a \notin A$ , so we need to show that no valid $\Gamma $ -axiom puts a into $\Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ . For the sake of a contradiction, suppose that at some stage s, while $a \in A_s$ , the global strategy enumerates a valid axiom $\langle a, B_a \oplus C^0_a \oplus C^1_a \rangle $ into $\Gamma $ . We now distinguish two possibilities:

Assume first that after this stage s, no ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement with current threshold $r \le a$ acts; then the ${\mathcal N}$ -requirements with threshold $r \le a$ cannot dump any numbers $c^i_{a'}$ into $X_i$ involved in the $\Gamma $ -axiom putting a into $\Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ (for either $i<2$ ); and only the highest-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement with threshold $r>a$ can dump any such numbers into only one of the $X_i$ , so $a \notin \Gamma (B \oplus X_0 \oplus X_1)$ by an $X_{1-i}$ -change.

On the other hand, suppose that some ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement with current threshold $r \le a$ acts, say, the first such requirement is an ${\mathcal N}^j$ -requirement acting at a stage $s'>s$ . In that case, the ${\mathcal N}^j$ -requirement’s current agitator q will be enumerated into K, and so the $\Lambda $ -axiom involving $F_q \oplus G_q$ will no longer apply. Now if $G_q \not \subseteq B$ , then the $\Gamma $ -axiom will clearly no longer apply for a. If only $F_q \not \subseteq A$ , then we will need to argue that $C^0_a \not \subseteq X_0$ or $C^1_a \not \subseteq X_1$ to invalidate the $\Gamma $ -axiom for a, but by the choice of the numbers $c^i_{a'}$ in the definition of the $\Gamma $ -axiom for a, both $c^0_{a'}$ and $c^1_{a'}$ will leave $X_0$ and $X_1$ , respectively, unless they will be dumped. However, since any ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement of lower priority than the ${\mathcal N}^j$ -requirement is prevented from dumping a number in $C^{1-j}_a$ into $X_{1-j}$ after the ${\mathcal N}^j$ -requirement acts at stage $s'$ , we know that $C^{1-j}_a \not \subseteq X_{1-j}$ as long as no ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement of higher priority acts later. If that should happen, we repeat the above argument until there is no even higher-priority ${\mathcal N}$ -requirement acting to dump even smaller numbers. So eventually, we see that this $\Gamma $ -axiom cannot apply to a anymore, as desired.

This establishes that the global requirement does indeed succeed as desired, completing the proof.

Funding

The first author’s research was partially supported by development program of Volga Region Mathematical Center (agreement no. 075-02-2022-882). The second author’s research was partially supported by NSF Binational grant DMS-DMS-1101123 entitled “Collaboration in Computability” and AMS-Simons Foundation Collaboration Grant 209087. The third author’s research was partially supported by the Ministry of Education, Singapore, under its Academic Research Fund Tier 1 (RG23/19). The fourth author’s research was partially supported by the Russian Science Foundation (project no. 22-21-20024; https://rscf.ru/project/22-21-20024/). This research was partially carried out while the second and third authors were visiting Kazan Federal University.

References

Ahmad, S., Some results on the structure of the ${\boldsymbol{\varSigma}}_{\boldsymbol{2}}$ enumeration degrees , Ph.D. thesis, Simon Fraser University, Canada, 1989.Google Scholar
Ahmad, S. and Lachlan, A. H., Some special pairs of ${\varSigma}_2$ e-degrees . Mathematical Logic Quarterly , vol. 44 (1998), no. 4, pp. 431449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ganchev, H. A. and Soskova, M. I., Interpreting true arithmetic in the local structure of the enumeration degrees, this Journal, vol. 77 (2012), pp. 1184–1194.Google Scholar
Goh, J. L., Ng, K. M., Lempp, S., and Soskova, M. I., Extensions of two constructions of Ahmad. Computability , vol. 11 (2022), no. 3-4, pp. 269297.Google Scholar
Goh, J. L., Ng, K. M., Lempp, S., and Soskova, M. I., Extensions of embeddings of 1-point extensions of finite antichains in the ${\varSigma}_2^0$ -enumeration degrees, in preparation.Google Scholar
Kent, T. F., The ${\varPi}_3$ -theory of the ${\varSigma}_2^0$ -enumeration degrees is undecidable, this Journal, vol. 71 (2006), pp. 1284–1302.Google Scholar
Lempp, S., Lerman, M., and Reed Solomon, D., Embedding finite lattices into the computably enumerable degrees—A status survey , Logic Colloquium’02 (Z. Chatzidakis, P. Koepke and W. Pohlers, editors), Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 27, Association for Symbolic Logic, La Jolla, 2006, pp. 206229.Google Scholar
Lempp, S., Nies, A., and Slaman, T. A., The ${\varPi}_3$ -theory of the computably enumerable Turing degrees is undecidable . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 350 (1998), pp. 27192736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lempp, S., Slaman, T. A., and Sorbi, A., On extensions of embeddings into the enumeration degrees of the ${\varSigma}_2^0$ -sets . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 5 (2005), pp. 247298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lempp, S. and Sorbi, A., Embedding finite lattices into the ${\varSigma}_2^0$ -enumeration degrees, this Journal, vol. 67 (2002), pp. 69–90.Google Scholar
Nies, A., Shore, R. A., and Slaman, T. A., Interpretability and definability in the recursively enumerable degrees . Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society (3) , vol. 77 (1998), pp. 241291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sacks, G. E., On the degrees less than ${\boldsymbol{0}}^{\prime }.$ Annals of Mathematics. Second Series , vol. 77 (1963), pp. 211231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slaman, T. A. and Woodin, W. H., Definability in the enumeration degrees . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 36 (1997), nos. 4–5, pp. 255267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar