Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T08:10:03.706Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Authors' reply

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

M. Verhofstadt
Affiliation:
End-of-Life Care Research Group, Vrije Universiteit Brussel (VUB) and Ghent University, Belgium
L. Thienpont
Affiliation:
Vonkel (an end-of-life consultation centre), Ghent, Belgium
G.-J. Y. Peters
Affiliation:
Department of Methodology and Statistics, Faculty of Psychology and Education Science, Open University of the Netherlands, Heerlen, The Netherlands
K. Chambaere
Affiliation:
End-of-Life Care Research Group, Vrije Universiteit Brussel (VUB) & Ghent University, Belgium. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2017 

Given that a recent trend analysis Reference Dierickx, Deliens, Cohen and Chambaere1 revealed an increase in instances of euthanasia of people with psychiatric disorders since the Belgian law on euthanasia came into effect in 2002 (despite unresolved matters of great concern), Dr Clifford's call not to ignore the potential risks of euthanasia legislation and practice is indeed essential. Since legalised euthanasia affects directly involved actors as well as healthcare systems and (inter)national societies, discussion of slippery slope arguments is necessary to stay alert and prevent ethically unacceptable acts from being accepted.

At the same time, it is important to safeguard against these discussions becoming purely philosophical, uncorroborated or even leading to a slippery slope fallacy, as might be the case if they are not based on scientific evidence. Hence, it is striking that 15 years after Belgium introduced its euthanasia law, euthanasia among psychiatric patients is still underexamined. Our own study Reference Verhofstadt, Thienpont and Peters2,Reference Dees, Vernooij-Dassen, Dekkers and van Weel3 has concentrated on the reality of clinical euthanasia practice in Belgium and finding ways of improving its transparency and quality.

In an effort to outline this reality, we would like to react to Dr Clifford's assumption that unbearable suffering as a concept might ‘lead almost effortlessly and uncritically to euthanasia’. As we stated in the introduction to our paper, Reference Verhofstadt, Thienpont and Peters2 unbearable suffering is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for granting euthanasia requests in Belgium (other conditions being the competent patient repeatedly making a voluntary and well-considered request, and suffering being rooted in an incurable medical illness without prospect of improvement 4 ). Furthermore, for patients who are not terminally ill, the Belgian euthanasia law stipulates the specific legal requirement of due care that two additional independent physicians, one of whom is specialised in the patient's disorder, must be involved in careful assessment and evaluation of all the legal requirements. Hence, in the context of psychiatric patients requesting euthanasia, consultations with at least one psychiatrist are mandatory.

Our study Reference Verhofstadt, Thienpont and Peters2,Reference Dees, Vernooij-Dassen, Dekkers and van Weel3 focused on just one of the key criteria, unbearable suffering, as it represents the most subjective and indeterminate criterion in granting euthanasia requests in the absence of an overarching solid definition and psychiatric assessment tool. In order to contribute to vigilance regarding euthanasia practice, especially concerning psychiatric patients, who are a particularly vulnerable group, the assessment of key criteria such as unbearable suffering should be undertaken as comprehensively and accurately as possible.

It is precisely this scientific involvement that might inform both the slippery slope discussion and the questioning of euthanasia as an end-of-life option on grounds of these arguments. In light of the grave concerns and potential dangers concerning the clinical practice of euthanasia, we strongly believe in scientific evidence as important in informing the juridical, philosophical, political, societal and ethical arguments in this debate. This provides a sound basis both to legitimately question euthanasia and provide sufficient built-in safeguards to protect against potential abuses.

References

1 Dierickx, S, Deliens, L, Cohen, J, Chambaere, K. Euthanasia for people with psychiatric disorders or dementia in Belgium: analysis of officially reported cases. BMC Psychiatry 2017; 17: 203.Google Scholar
2 Verhofstadt, M, Thienpont, L, Peters, G-JY. When unbearable suffering incites psychiatric patients to request euthanasia: qualitative study. Br J Psychiatry 2017; 211: 238–45.Google Scholar
3 Dees, M, Vernooij-Dassen, M, Dekkers, W, van Weel, C. Unbearable suffering of patients with a request for euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide: an integrative review. Psychooncology 2010; 19: 339–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
4 Ministry of Justice. Law on euthanasia of May 28, 2007 [in Dutch and French], Belgian Official Gazette, 2002; 22 June (http://www.npzl.be/files/107a_B3_wet_euthanasie.pdf).Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.