Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T23:53:38.579Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ON SEPARATE CONTINUITY AND SEPARATE CONVEXITY: A SYNTHETIC TREATMENT FOR FUNCTIONS AND SETS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 July 2023

METIN UYANIK*
Affiliation:
School of Economics, University of Queensland, Brisbane, Queensland 4072, Australia
M. ALI KHAN
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21218, USA e-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper relies on nested postulates of separate, linear and arc-continuity of functions to define analogous properties for sets that are weaker than the requirement that the set be open or closed. This allows three novel characterisations of open or closed sets under convexity or separate convexity postulates: the first pertains to separately convex sets, the second to convex sets and the third to arbitrary subsets of a finite-dimensional Euclidean space. By relying on these constructions, we also obtain new results on the relationship between separate and joint continuity of separately quasiconcave, or separately quasiconvex functions. We present examples to show that the sufficient conditions we offer cannot be dispensed with.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Australian Mathematical Publishing Association Inc.

The notion of continuity depends upon that of order, since continuity is merely a particular type of order. Mathematics has, in modern times, brought order into greater and greater prominence. Bertrand Russell [Reference Russell21]

1 Introduction

This paper is motivated by the following basic questions concerning a set A in a finite-dimensional Euclidean space $\mathbb {R}^n.$ Can we tell if A is open or closed just by considering its intersection with lines? We already know that the intersection of an open (or closed) set with a line L in $\mathbb {R}^n$ that is parallel to a coordinate axis must be an open (or closed) subset of $L,$ but the question arises as to whether the converse holds. This is to ask whether A is open (or closed) if the intersections of A with all lines parallel to the axes are open (or closed) subsets of those lines. Furthermore, what can we say regarding whether the intersection of A with all possible lines is open (or closed)? Is that sufficient to conclude A is open (or closed)? These questions are related to matters of separate continuity of a function: is a function $f:{\mathbb {R}}^n \rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}$ necessarily continuous if all possible single-variable functions of the form $g(z) = f(x_1,\ldots ,x_{i-1},z,x_{i+1},\ldots ,x_n)$ are continuous?

These questions are hardly novel. In [Reference Halkin12], Halkin provides a characterisation of a closed and convex set A in a finite-dimensional Euclidean space ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ by imposing assumptions on the supporting hyperplanes of A. In another development, Azagra and Ferrera [Reference Azagra and Ferrera1] provide a characterisation of closed and convex sets in a separable Banach space by seeing them as null sets, and thereby minimisers or maximisers, of $C^\infty $ -smooth, real-valued convex functions. What is novel to this note are possibly new characterisations of closed and of open sets in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ by weakening or completely dropping the convexity assumption, and thereby generalising the result in [Reference Halkin12]. We are motivated by separate, linear and arc-continuity of functions.

Furthermore, Young [Reference Young25] and Kruse and Deely [Reference Kruse and Deely16] show that for separately monotone functions defined on an open set in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ , separate continuity is equivalent to joint continuity. On using the characterisation of sets referred to above, we move from sets to functions and reset our characterisations of sets to functions in a more general setting that substitutes separate quasiconvexity or separate quasiconcavity for separate monotonicity, and by drawing on weaker notions of continuity obtain the results in [Reference Kruse and Deely16, Reference Young25] as corollaries.

Section 2 presents three results each offering necessary and sufficient conditions for a set to be open or closed: the first on open sets, and the other two on sets that can be open or closed. Four supplementary examples illustrate that the assumptions in these results are not redundant. Section 3 presents a theorem and an example concerning necessary and sufficient conditions for the semicontinuity of functions. Section 4 presents three remarks: the first suggesting how the separate convexity postulate can be replaced by piecewise separate convexity, the second relating to the intermediate-value property, and the third pointing to the relevance of the results to correspondences and binary relations and to applications in mathematical economics. All in all, this interdisciplinary investigation mirrors and consolidates the different approaches available in the antecedent literature. Section 5 is devoted to the proofs.

2 On closed sets and on open sets in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$

A straight line in $X\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is defined as the intersection of a one-dimensional subset of the affine hull of X. Next, we introduce a topological property that is motivated by separate continuity of a function that imposes continuity restricted to straight lines parallel to a coordinate axis; see [Reference Genocchi and Peano9, Reference Kruse and Deely16, Reference Young25] for classic results and [Reference Ciesielski and Miller4, Reference Ghosh, Khan and Uyanik10] for recent surveys on different continuity postulates.

Definition 2.1. A set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is separately closed (open) if for any straight line L in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ that is parallel to a coordinate axis, $L\cap A$ is closed (open) in the subspace L.

For any strictly positive natural number n, let $[n]=\{1,\ldots , n\}$ . For all $x\in A$ , define $A_i(x)=\{z\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(z, x_{-i})\in A\}$ , where $x_{-i}=(x_1, \ldots , x_{i-1}, x_{i+1}, \ldots , x_n)$ . For each i and x, $A_i(x)$ determines the straight line passing through x that is parallel to the coordinate axis i. Hence, a separately closed (open) set A is equivalently defined as $A_{i}(x)$ is closed (open) in ${\mathbb {R}}$ for all $x\in A$ and all $i\in [n]$ . It is clear that if a set is open, then it is separately open. The following example illustrates a set that is separately open but not open. (The examples are illustrated in Figure 1.)

Example 2.2. Let $A=(0,1)^2\backslash \{x\in (0,1)^2 \mid x_1=x_2, x\neq 0\}$ . The intersection of a line parallel to a coordinate axis and A is either the $(0,1)$ interval or the union of two open intervals, and hence A is separately open. However, A is not open since every open ball containing $0$ contains a point in the complement of A.

Figure 1 Illustration of examples in Section 2.

Our first result shows that under a weak convexity assumption, separate openness is a necessary and sufficient condition for a set to be open.

Theorem 2.3. Let $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ and J be an $(n-1)$ -element subset of $[n]$ such that $A_i(x)$ is convex for all $x\in A$ and all $i\in J$ . Then, A is open if and only if it is separately open.

Note that the conclusion of Theorem 2.3 can be re-stated as follows: A is open in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ if and only if for any straight line L in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ that is parallel to a coordinate axis, $L\cap A$ is open in the subspace L. The convexity assumption in Theorem 2.3 is related to the literature on sets with convex sections as $A_i(x)$ denotes the ith section of A at x (see for example [Reference Fan7]). A set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is separately convex if $A_i(x)$ is convex for all $i\in [n]$ and all $x\in A$ . Example 2.2 illustrates that the convexity assumption in Theorem 2.3, which is weaker than separate convexity, is not redundant.

Next, we introduce a topological property of a set by imposing assumptions on straight lines in the set that is motivated by the linear continuity of a function (see for example [Reference Ciesielski and Miller4, Reference Genocchi and Peano9, Reference Uyanik and Khan23]).

Definition 2.4. A set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is linearly closed (open) if for any straight line L in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ , $L\cap A$ is closed (open) in the subspace L.

Example 2.2 illustrates a set that is separately open but not open and also not linearly open. The following example illustrates a set that is not open but both separately open and linearly open.

Example 2.5. Let $B=(0,1)^2\backslash \{x\in (0,1)^2 \mid x_2=x_1^2 \text { for } x_1>0, x_2=-x_1^2 \text { for } x_1\,{<}\,0, x\neq 0\}$ . The intersection of a straight line and B excludes at most finitely many points of $L\cap (0,1)^2$ . Hence, B is linearly open. However, B is not open since every open ball containing $0$ contains a point in the complement of B.

It is clear that every separately closed (open) set is linearly closed (open), and if A is convex, then $A_i(x)$ is convex for all $x\in A$ and all $i\in [n]$ . The following theorem presents a necessary and sufficient condition for a set to be closed under a convexity and a topological assumption stronger than those in Theorem 2.3.

Theorem 2.6. A convex set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is closed (open) if and only if it is linearly closed (open).

Since Theorem 2.6 imposes stronger convexity and topological assumptions than Theorem 2.3, for open sets, it is a corollary of Theorem 2.3. Theorem 2.6 complements the results of Azagra and Ferrera [Reference Azagra and Ferrera1] and Halkin [Reference Halkin12] who provide characterisations of closed and convex sets by using the minimisers of a class of convex functions in [Reference Azagra and Ferrera1] and by using the supporting hyperplanes of the set in [Reference Halkin12].

The following example illustrates that for closed sets, the convexity and topological assumptions in Theorem 2.6 are not redundant.

Example 2.7. Let $C=\{x\in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \mid x_1=x_2\}\cap (-1,1]^2$ . It is clear that C is convex and fails the topological assumption in Theorem 2.6, and it is not closed (in ${\mathbb {R}}^2$ ). Now let $D=\{x\in {\mathbb {R}}^2\mid x_1^2=x_2\}\cap (-1,1]^2$ . It is clear that D is not convex and the intersection of any straight line L in ${\mathbb {R}}^2$ with D contains at most finitely many elements, hence it is closed in L, and hence linearly closed. However, D is not closed (in ${\mathbb {R}}^2$ ). Note that both C and D are separately closed, and satisfy the convexity assumption in Theorem 2.3. Hence, the weak convexity assumed in Theorem 2.3 is not enough to guarantee a separately closed set to be closed.

Next, we show that the convexity assumptions in the theorems above can be dispensed with by imposing a topological assumption on a class of selections of A that is larger than the set of straight lines, following the restriction continuity of [Reference Rosenthal20] for functions. An arc in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ is a continuous injective function $m:[0,1]\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}^n$ , where $m(\lambda )=(m_1(\lambda ), \ldots , m_n(\lambda ))$ . An arc is called smooth if $m_i$ is continuously differentiable for all i and $m'(\lambda )=(m_1'(\lambda ), \ldots , m_n'(\lambda ))\neq 0$ for all $\lambda \in [0,1]$ . A curve in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ is the image of an arc and a smooth curve is the image of a smooth arc. Since an arc m is continuous and injective, it is a bijection from $[0,1]$ to its image $m([0,1])$ . Since $[0,1]$ is compact and $m([0,1])$ is Hausdorff, m is a homeomorphism between $[0,1]$ and $m([0,1])$ (see for example [Reference Dugundji5, Theorem 2.1, page 226]. Therefore, $[0,1]$ and the curve induced by an arc are homeomorphic. The following topological property of a set imposes assumptions on smooth curves in the set that is motivated by the arc-continuity of a function (see for example [Reference Ciesielski and Miller4, Reference Rosenthal20, Reference Uyanik and Khan23, Reference Wold24]).

Definition 2.8. A set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is arc-closed (open) if for any smooth curve C in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ , $C\cap A$ is closed (open) in the subspace C.

The following theorem drops the convexity assumption on a set by imposing a topological assumption on restrictions of the set on smooth curves.

Theorem 2.9. A set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is closed (open) if and only if it is arc-closed (open).

3 On continuity of functions on ${\mathbb {R}}^n$

In this section, we study the relationship between separate and joint continuity of a function under quasiconvexity and quasiconcavity. A real-valued function $f(x_1,\ldots , x_n)$ defined on a convex subset of ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ is quasiconcave (quasiconvex) in $x_i$ if for all $x_{-i}=(x_1, \ldots , x_{i-1}, x_{i+1}, \ldots , x_n)$ , $f(\cdot , x_{-i})$ is quasiconcave (quasiconvex). (The general reader may want to note an abuse of notation whereby $x \in {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is conceived as $(x_i, x_{-i})$ or, alternatively, $ (a, x_{-i}) $ refers to an element of ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ whereby $a \in {\mathbb {R}}$ is substituted in the ith place in $x \in {\mathbb {R}}^n.$ Unfortunately, this notation is standard in mathematical economics and game theory, and we submit to it.) Moreover, f is separately quasiconcave (separately quasiconvex) if it is quasiconcave (quasiconvex) in each variable.

Theorem 3.1. Let $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ be a convex and open set. If $f:Y\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}$ is quasiconvex in $n-1$ variables, then it is upper semicontinuous if and only if it is separately upper semicontinuous. Moreover, if f is quasiconcave in $n-1$ variables, then it is lower semicontinuous if and only if it is separately lower semicontinuous.

The two classical counterexamples of Genocchi and Peano [Reference Genocchi and Peano9] show that the separate continuity of a function is strictly weaker than its linear continuity, and that is strictly weaker than its joint continuity. Young [Reference Young25] and Kruse and Deely [Reference Kruse and Deely16] show that these three continuity postulates are equivalent under a weak monotonicity assumption. Rosenthal [Reference Rosenthal20] shows that imposing continuity of a function restricted to any smooth curve is enough to obtain its joint continuity. Uyanik and Khan [Reference Uyanik and Khan23] show that under quasiconcavity, or quasiconvexity, linear continuity and joint continuity are equivalent. Theorem 3.1 contributes to this literature by studying the relationship between separate and joint continuity of functions under convexity, or concavity, an assumption that is weaker than monotonicity. See also [Reference Christensen3, Reference Kenderov and Moors14, Reference Namioka17] for relationships between separate and joint continuity in infinite-dimensional spaces, and [Reference Ciesielski and Miller4, Reference Ghosh, Khan and Uyanik10, Reference Piotrowski18] for surveys. Moreover, lower semicontinuity under concavity and upper semicontinuity under convexity of functions is studied in [Reference Ernst6, Reference Gale, Klee and Rockafellar8]. The following example shows that joint continuity cannot be obtained from separate continuity under separate quasiconcavity or separate quasiconvexity.

Example 3.2. Define $f:{\mathbb {R}}^2\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}$ as $f(x)=0$ if $x_1\leqslant 0$ or $x_2\leqslant 0$ and $f(x)=2xy/(x^2+y^2)$ otherwise. For all i and all $x_i$ , $f(\cdot , x_i)$ is increasing in $x_j$ for $x_j<x_i$ and decreasing in $x_j$ for $x_j>x_i$ , and hence f is quasiconcave in each variable. It is easy to see that f is separately continuous. However, f is not jointly continuous (and also not linearly continuous). Note that f is not upper semicontinuous, and hence this example also illustrates that separate quasiconcavity is not sufficient for the equivalence between separate upper semicontinuity and upper semicontinuity. Analogously, $-f$ illustrates that separate quasiconvexity is not sufficient for the equivalence between separate lower semicontinuity and lower semicontinuity.

Functions that are quasiconcave in some variables and quasiconvex in other variables are commonly used in mathematics such as minimax theorems. The following simple corollary of Theorem 3.1 shows that on ${\mathbb {R}}^2$ , separate continuity is equivalent to the joint continuity of a function.

Corollary 3.3. Let $(a_1, b_1)$ and $(a_2, b_2)$ be two open intervals in ${\mathbb {R}}$ and let f be a function defined on $(a_1,b_1)\times (a_2, b_2)$ that is quasiconcave in one variable and quasiconvex in the other variable. Then, f is jointly continuous if and only if it is separately continuous.

A function $f(x_1,\ldots , x_n)$ on a set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is monotone in $x_i$ if for all $x_{-i}$ , $f(\cdot , x_{-i})$ is either increasing or decreasing. It is easy to see that if a function is both quasiconcave and quasiconvex in $x_i$ , then it is monotone in $x_i$ . Therefore, for convex sets, the following result of [Reference Kruse and Deely16, Reference Young25] is a corollary of Theorem 3.1.

Corollary 3.4. Let $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ be a convex and open set, and $f:Y\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}$ be a function that is monotone in $n-1$ variables. Then, f is jointly continuous if and only if it is separately continuous.

4 Remarks

Remark 4.1. A real valued function $f(x_1,\ldots , x_n)$ on $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is piecewise monotone in $x_i$ if there exist $m_i\in \mathbb N$ and $a_i^1<a_i^2< \cdots < a_i^{m_i}$ such that f is monotone on $[a_i^k, a_i^{k+1}]$ for all $k=1,\ldots , m_i-1$ , and $A_i(x)\subseteq [a_i^1, a_i^{m_i}]$ for all $x\in A$ . This monotonicity property is a generalisation of the piecewise monotonicity concept of Sohrab [Reference Sohrab22, page 156] from ${\mathbb {R}}$ to ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ . We show in the next section that the monotonicity assumption in Corollary 3.4 can be replaced by the weaker piecewise monotonicity assumption. Note that in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ , $n\geqslant 2$ , the piecewise monotonicity concept neither implies nor is implied by separate quasiconcavity or separate quasiconvexity properties. To see this, on ${\mathbb {R}}$ , the sine function is piecewise monotone, but it is neither quasiconcave nor quasiconvex. Conversely, Example 3.2 illustrates a function on ${\mathbb {R}}^2$ that is separately quasiconcave but not piecewise monotone in either coordinate.

Remark 4.2. If a function $f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ defined on $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is piecewise monotone in $x_i$ (or monotone in $x_i$ ), then the arguments in [Reference Sohrab22, page 156] imply that separate continuity is equivalent to the following intermediate value property in the variable $x_i$ : for all $x\in A$ and all $[a_i, b_i]\subseteq A_i(x)$ , $a_i<b_i$ , and all $y_i$ between $f(a_i)$ and $f(b_i)$ , there exists $c_i\in (a_i, b_i)$ such that $f(c_i)=y_i$ . See [Reference Ghosh, Khan and Uyanik10] for an investigation of the intermediate value theorem in two applied registers.

Remark 4.3. The separate convexity assumption in Theorem 2.3 can be replaced by the following weaker convexity property: a set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is piecewise convex in $x_i$ if there exist $m_i\in \mathbb N$ and $a_i^1<a_i^2< \cdots < a_i^{m_i}$ such that $A_i(x)\cap [a_i^k, a_i^{k+1}]$ is convex for all $x\in A$ and all $k=1,\ldots , m-1$ , and $A_i(x)\subseteq [a_i^1, a_i^m]$ for all $x\in A$ . This piecewise separate convexity property is motivated by the piecewise separate monotonicity concept for functions defined above, and is also stronger than (separate) local convexity of a set; see [Reference Klee15] for a detailed discussion of locally convex sets. We leave it for the interested reader to check that the construction of the proof in Theorem 2.3 is essentially the same.

Remark 4.4. If a set $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is piecewise convex in $x_i$ , then, as in Remark 4.2, $A_i(x)$ is open for all $x\in A$ if and only if it satisfies the following separate intermediate value property for sets: if $a_i, b_i\in A_i(x)$ , then there exists $c_i\in (a_i, b_i)$ such that $c_i\in A_i(x)$ .

Remark 4.5. Different continuity concepts of a binary relation or a correspondence, including the properties of straight lines and curves, have been extensively used in economics and psychology; see for example [Reference Bergstrom, Parks and Rader2, Reference Ghosh, Khan and Uyanik10, Reference Ghosh, Khan and Uyanik11, Reference Herstein and Milnor13, Reference Uyanik and Khan23, Reference Wold24]. We leave it for future research to study the extensions of the results in this paper to infinite-dimensional spaces, and their implications to the continuity of correspondences and binary relations.

5 Proof of the results

Let $\{X_{i}\}_{i\in I}$ be an indexed family of nonempty sets. For any nonempty $J\subseteq I$ , let $X_J=\prod _{j\in J}X_j$ and $X_{-J}=\prod _{j\in J^c}X_j$ . The subscript is omitted for $J=I$ and we use $X_i$ and $X_{-i}$ if $J=\{i\}$ for some $i\in I$ . For all $x\in X$ and all nonempty $J\subset I$ , let $x=(x_J, x_{-J})$ . For $A\subseteq X$ , all $x\in A$ and all nonempty $J\subseteq I$ , let $A_J(x)=\{z\in X_J~|~(z, x_{-J})\in A\}$ .

Proof of Theorem 2.3.

We prove the theorem by induction. First, let $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^2$ . Assume that A is separately open and, without loss of generality, that $A_2(x)$ is convex for all $x\in A$ . By separate openness, for all $x\in A$ , $A_2(x)=\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in A\}$ is open and $A_1(x)=\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', x_2)\in A\}$ is open.

Pick $x\in A$ . By separate openness, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_2, b_2]$ of $x_2$ such that for all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ , $(x_1, x_2')\in A$ . That is, $[a_2, b_2]\subset A_2(x)$ . By separate openness, $A_1(x_1, a_2)=\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', a_2)\in A\}$ and $A_1(x_1, b_2)=\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', b_2)\in A\}$ are open. Then, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_1, b_1]$ of $x_1$ such that $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ implies $(x_1', a_2)\in A$ and $(x_1', b_2)\in A$ . That is, $[a_1, b_1]\subset A_1(x_1, a_2)\cap A_1(x_1, b_2)$ . By separate convexity, $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ implies $[a_1, b_1]\subset A_1(x_1, x_2')$ . Hence, for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ and all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ , $(x_1', x_2')\in A$ . Since $[a_1, b_1]\times [a_2, b_2]\subset A$ is a neighbourhood of x and x is arbitrarily picked, it follows that A is open.

Now, let $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ , $n>2$ . Assume that A is separately open and, without loss of generality, that $A_i(x)$ is convex for all $x\in A$ and $i\geqslant 2$ . Then, by the induction hypothesis,

(5.1) $$ \begin{align} A_{-n}(x)=\{x_{-n}'\in {\mathbb{R}}^{n-1}~|~(x_{-n}', x_n)\in A\}\quad \text{is open for all } x\in A. \end{align} $$

Pick $x\in A$ . By separate openness, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_n, b_n]$ of $x_n$ such that for all $x_n'\in [a_n, b_n]$ , $(x_{-n}, x_n')\in A$ . That is, $[a_n, b_n]\subset A_n(x)$ . By (5.1) above, $A_{-n}(x_{-n}, a_n)=\{x_{-n}'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_{-n}', a_n)\in A\}$ and $A_{-n}(x_{-n}, b_n)=\{x_{-n}'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_{-n}', b_n)\in A\}$ are open. Then, there exists a neighbourhood $U=\prod _{i=1}^{n-1}[a_i, b_i]$ of $x_{-n}$ such that $x_{-n}'\in U$ implies $(x_{-n}', a_n)\in A$ and $(x_{-n}', b_n)\in A$ . That is, $U\subset A_{-n}(x_{-n}, a_n)\cap A_{-n}(x_{-n}, b_n)$ . By separate convexity, $x_n'\in [a_n, b_n]$ implies $U\subset A_{-n}(x_{-n}, x_n')$ . Hence, for all $x_{-n}'\in U$ and all $x_n'\in [a_n, b_n]$ , $(x_{-n}', x_n')\in A$ . Since $U\times [a_n, b_n]\subset A$ is a neighbourhood of x and x is arbitrarily picked, A is open.

We prove Theorem 2.6 by using an important result in convex analysis due to Rockafellar [Reference Rockafellar19, page 45]. The statement of Rockafellar’s theorem requires the following additional concepts. Let X be a subset of ${\mathbb {R}}^n.$ Since any lower dimensional subset of ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ has an empty interior, it is more convenient to work with the concept of relative interior. A subset X of a (real) vector space is called affine if for all $x,y\in X$ and $\lambda \in {\mathbb {R}},\ \lambda x+ (1-\lambda )y\in X.$ It is clear that A is affine if and only if $A-\{a\}$ is a subspace of X for all $a\in A.$ The affine hull of $X,$ aff $X,$ is the smallest affine set containing X. The relative interior of a subset X of ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ is defined as

$$ \begin{align*} \text{ri} X=\{x\in \mbox{aff}X~|~\mbox{there is an } \varepsilon \text{ neighbourhood}, N_\varepsilon, \mbox{of } x \text{ such that } N_\varepsilon\cap \text{aff}X\subseteq X\}. \end{align*} $$

That is, the relative interior of X is the interior of X with respect to the smallest affine subspace containing X.

Theorem 5.1 (Rockafellar).

Let X be a nonempty and convex subset of ${\mathbb {R}}^n.$ Then $\mathrm {ri}X$ is nonempty, and for all $x\in \mathrm {ri}X, y\in \mathrm {cl}X$ and all $\lambda \in [0,1),\ y\lambda x \in \mathrm {ri}X.$

Proof of Theorem 2.6.

For open sets, Theorem 2.6 is a corollary of Theorem 2.3. Moreover, it is clear that if A is closed, then A is linearly closed. Now, assume A is convex and linearly closed. If A is empty or a singleton, then it is closed. Otherwise, pick $x\in \text {cl}A$ . Since A is convex, Theorem 5.1 implies that its relative interior is nonempty, and that for all $y\in \text {ri}A$ and all $\lambda \in [0,1)$ , $x\lambda y\in \text {ri}A$ . Hence, for any $\lambda ^k\rightarrow 1$ , $x\lambda ^k y\in A$ for all k. Pick $y\in \text {ri}A$ and let L denote the straight line in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ passing through x and y. Since A is linearly closed, $A\cap L$ is closed in L. Since $x\lambda ^k y\in A$ for all k when $\lambda ^k\rightarrow 1$ , it follows that $x\in A$ . Therefore, A is closed.

The proof of Theorem 2.9 we provide below crucially hinges on the work of Rosenthal [Reference Rosenthal20, Theorem 3]. We state a slightly stronger version of the theorem of Rosenthal with the notation of our paper.

Theorem 5.2 (Rosenthal).

Any bounded infinite set in ${\mathbb {R}}^n$ contains an infinite subset through which a smooth curve can be laid.

Proof of Theorem 2.9.

The forward direction is obvious. To prove the backward direction, assume A is arc-closed. If A is empty or a singleton, then it is closed. Otherwise, pick $x\in \text {cl}A$ and a sequence $x_n$ in A such that $x_n\rightarrow x$ . It follows from Theorem 5.2 that there exists a smooth curve containing x and a subsequence $x_{n_k}$ of $x_n$ . Since A is arc-closed, $x\in A$ . Hence, A is closed.

Now assume A is arc-open but not open. Then there exists $x\in A\cap \text {cl}(A^c)$ . Pick a sequence $x_n$ in $A^c$ such that $x_n\rightarrow x$ . It follows from Theorem 5.2 that there exists a smooth curve C containing x and a subsequence $x_{n_k}$ of $x_n$ . This implies that $C\cap A$ contains $x\in A$ , but every open neighbourhood of x in the subspace C contains $x'\in A^c$ . This contradicts the assumption that A is arc-open. Hence, A is open.

Proof of Theorem 3.1.

First, we prove the result for $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^2$ . Assume without loss of generality that f is quasiconvex in $x_2$ . It follows that, for all $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and all $x\in Y$ , $\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in Y \text { and } f(x_1, x_2)\leqslant \alpha \}$ is convex. Next, we show that the quasiconvexity assumption implies that $\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in Y \text { and } f(x_1, x_2')< \alpha \}$ is convex for all $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and all $x\in Y$ . Assume towards a contradiction that there exists $x_1, x_2, y_2$ and $\lambda $ such that $f(x_1, x_2)< \alpha $ , $f(x_1, y_2)< \alpha $ and $f(x_1, \lambda x_2+(1-\lambda ) y_2)\geqslant \alpha $ . Set $\beta =\max \{f(x_1, x_2), f(x_1, y_2)\}<\alpha $ . By the quasiconvexity assumption, it follows that $\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in Y \text { and } f(x_1, x_2')\leqslant \beta \}$ is convex. Hence, $\alpha \leqslant f(x_1, \lambda x_2+(1-\lambda ) y_2)\leqslant \beta <\alpha $ which yields a contradiction.

By separate upper semicontinuity, $\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in Y \text { and } f(x_1, x_2')< \alpha \}$ is open and $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', x_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', x_2)< \alpha \}$ is open, for all $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and all $x\in Y$ . Pick $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and $x\in Y$ such that $f(x)<\alpha $ . Hence, pick a neighbourhood $[a_2, b_2]$ of $x_2$ such that for all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ , $f(x_1, x_2')<\alpha $ . By separate upper semicontinuity, $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', a_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', a_2)<\alpha \}$ and $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', b_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', b_2)<\alpha \}$ are open. Then, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_1, b_1]$ of $x_1$ such that $f(x_1', a_2)<\alpha $ and $f(x_1', b_2)<\alpha $ for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ . By the quasiconvexity assumption, $f(x_1', x_2')<\alpha $ for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ and all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ . Since $[a_1, b_1]\times [a_2, b_2]$ is a neighbourhood of x, it follows that f is upper semicontinuous.

Now, assume $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ with $n>2$ . We proceed by induction. Without loss of generality, assume f is quasiconvex in each variable $x_i$ for $i=2,\ldots , n$ . Since f is separately upper semicontinuous and quasiconcave in each $x_i$ for $i=2,\ldots , n-1$ , the induction hypothesis implies that $f(\cdot , x_n)$ is upper semicontinuous in $x_{-n}=(x_1,\ldots , x_{n-1})$ for each fixed value of $x_n$ . Since f is quasiconvex in $x_n$ , for all $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and all $x\in Y$ , the sets ${\{x_n'\kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_{-n}, x_n')\kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt Y \text { and } f(x_{-n}, x_n')\kern1.2pt{\leqslant}\kern1.2pt \alpha \}}$ and, as we showed above, $\{x_n'\kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_{-n}, x_n')\kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt Y \text{and } f(x_{-n}, x_n')< \alpha \}$ are convex.

Pick $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ and $x\in Y$ such that $f(x)<\alpha $ . Since f is upper semicontinuous in $x_n$ , $\{x_n'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_{-n}, x_n')\in Y \text { and } f(x_{-n}, x_n')< \alpha \}$ is open, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_n, b_n]$ of $x_n$ such that for all $x_n'\in [a_n, b_n]$ , $f(x_{-n}, x_n')<\alpha $ . Since f is upper semicontinuous in $x_{-n}$ , $\{x_{-n}'\in {\mathbb {R}}^{n-1}~|~(x_{-n}', a_n)\in Y \text { and } f(x_{-n}', a_n)<\alpha \}$ and $\{x_{-n}'~|~(x_{-n}', b_n)\in Y \text { and } f(x_{-n}', b_n)<\alpha \}$ are open. Then, there exists a neighbourhood $U_{-n}$ of $x_{-n}$ such that $f(x_{-n}', a_n)<\alpha $ and $f(x_{-n}', b_n)<\alpha $ for all $x_{-n}'\in U_{-n}$ . By the quasiconvexity assumption, $f(x_{-n}', x_n')<\alpha $ for all $x_{-n}'\in U_{-n}$ and all $x_n'\in [a_n, b_n]$ . Since $U_{-n}\times [a_n, b_n]$ is a neighbourhood of x, f is upper semicontinuous.

The proof of lower semicontinuity under quasiconcavity is analogous.

Next, we provide the proof of the following claim that we stated in Remark 4.1.

Claim 5.3. If $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^n$ is convex and open and $f:Y\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}$ is piecewise monotone in $n-1$ coordinates, then f is jointly continuous if and only if it is separately continuous.

Proof of Claim 5.3.

The proof is analogous to that of Theorem 3.1; we consider only the case when $n=2$ and leave the generalisation for an arbitrary finite n to the interested reader.

Let $Y\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}^2$ be a convex and open set. Assume without loss of generality that f is piecewise monotone in $x_2$ . Next, we prove that f is upper semicontinuous at x. Pick $x\in Y$ and $\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}$ such that $f(x)<\alpha $ . By separate upper semicontinuity, $\{x_2'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1, x_2')\in Y \text { and } f(x_1, x_2')< \alpha \}$ is open. Hence, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_2, b_2]$ of $x_2$ such that for all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ , $f(x_1, x_2')<\alpha $ . If $x_2\in (a_2^k, a_2^{k+1})$ for some $k=1,\ldots , m_2-1$ , then set $[a_2, b_2]\subset [a_2^k, a_2^{k+1}]$ ; if $x_2= a_2^k$ for some $k=2,\ldots , m_2-1$ , then set $[a_2, b_2]\subset [a_2^{k-1}, a_2^{k+1}]$ (note that since Y is open, $x_2\in (a_2^1, a_2^{m_2})$ ).

By separate upper semicontinuity, the sets $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', x_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', x_2)<\alpha \}$ , $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', a_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', a_2)<\alpha \}$ and $\{x_1'\in {\mathbb {R}}~|~(x_1', b_2)\in Y \text { and } f(x_1', b_2)<\alpha \}$ are open. Then, there exists a neighbourhood $[a_1, b_1]$ of $x_1$ such that $f(x_1', x_2)<\alpha $ , $f(x_1', a_2)<\alpha $ and $f(x_1', b_2)<\alpha $ for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ . If $x_2\in (a_2^k, a_2^{k+1})$ for some $k=1,\ldots , m_2-1$ , then $[a_2, b_2]\subset [a_2^k, a_2^{k+1}]$ , and hence $f(\tilde x_1, \cdot )$ is monotonic on $[a_2, b_2]$ for all $\tilde x_1$ . Therefore, $f(x_1', x_2')<\alpha $ for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ and all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ . If $x_2= a_2^k$ for some $k=2,\ldots , m_2-1$ , then $[a_2, b_2]\subset [a_2^{k-1}, a_2^{k+1}]$ , and hence $f(\tilde x_1, \cdot )$ is either monotonic on $[a_2, b_2]$ or has a unique kink at $x_2$ for all $\tilde x_1$ . Therefore, $f(x_1', x_2')<\alpha $ for all $x_1'\in [a_1, b_1]$ and all $x_2'\in [a_2, b_2]$ . Since $[a_1, b_1]\times [a_2, b_2]$ is a neighbourhood of x, f is upper semicontinuous.

The proof of lower semicontinuity at x is analogous. Therefore, f is continuous at x.

Acknowledgements

The authors are grateful, above all, to Ed Scheinerman for a careful reading of the first draft of this paper, and for his many useful suggestions that we hope to consider in future work. They also thank Aniruddha Ghosh, Imran Parvez Khan, Arthur Paul Pederson, Asghar Qadir and Nicholas Yannelis for conversation and continuing collaboration, and an anonymous referee for their suggestions.

References

Azagra, D. and Ferrera, J., ‘Every closed convex set is the set of minimizers of some ${C}^{\infty }$ -smooth convex function’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 130(12) (2002), 36873692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergstrom, T. C., Parks, R. P. and Rader, T., ‘Preferences which have open graphs’, J. Math. Econom. 3(3) (1976), 265268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, J. P. R., ‘Joint continuity of separately continuous functions’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 82(3) (1981), 455461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciesielski, K. C. and Miller, D., ‘A continuous tale on continuous and separately continuous functions’, Real Anal. Exchange 41(1) (2016), 1954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dugundji, J., Topology (Allyn and Bacon, Boston, 1966).Google Scholar
Ernst, E., ‘A converse of the Gale–Klee–Rockafellar theorem: continuity of convex functions at the boundary of their domains’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 141(10) (2013), 36653672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fan, K., ‘Applications of a theorem concerning sets with convex sections’, Math. Ann. 163(3) (1966), 189203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gale, D., Klee, V. and Rockafellar, R., ‘Convex functions on convex polytopes’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 19(4) (1968), 867873.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genocchi, A. and Peano, G., Calcolo Differentiale e Principii di Calcolo (Fratelli Bocca, Torino, 1884).Google Scholar
Ghosh, A., Khan, M. A. and Uyanik, M., ‘The intermediate value theorem and decision-making in psychology and economics: an expositional consolidation’, Games 13(4) (2022), 51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghosh, A., Khan, M. A. and Uyanik, M., On Continuity of Correspondences and Binary Relations: A Reconsideration of the Continuity Postulate (Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD, 2023).Google Scholar
Halkin, H., ‘Necessary and sufficient condition for a convex set to be closed’, Amer. Math. Monthly 73(6) (1966), 628630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herstein, I. N. and Milnor, J., ‘An axiomatic approach to measurable utility’, Econometrica 21(2) (1953), 291297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenderov, P. and Moors, W., ‘Separate continuity, joint continuity and the Lindelöf property’, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 134(5) (2006), 15031512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klee, V., ‘Convex sets in linear spaces’, Duke Math. J. 18(2) (1951), 443466.Google Scholar
Kruse, R. L. and Deely, J. J., ‘Joint continuity of monotonic functions’, Amer. Math. Monthly 76(1) (1969), 7476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Namioka, I., ‘Separate and joint continuity’, Pacific J. Math. 51 (1974), 515531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piotrowski, Z., ‘The genesis of separate versus joint continuity’, Tatra Mt. Math. Publ. 8 (1996), 113126.Google Scholar
Rockafellar, R. T., Convex Analysis (Princeton University Press, New York, 1970)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, A., ‘On the continuity of functions of several variables’, Math. Z. 63(1) (1955), 3138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B., ‘Mysticism and mathematics’, in: Mysticism, Logic and Other Essays (George Allen and Unwin Ltd., London, 1917), 153154.Google Scholar
Sohrab, H. H., Basic Real Analysis (Birkhaüser, Heidleberg, 2014).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uyanik, M. and Khan, M. A., ‘The continuity postulate in economic theory: A deconstruction and an integration’, J. Math. Econom. 101 (2022), Article no. 102704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wold, H., ‘A synthesis of pure demand analysis, I–III’, Scand. Actuar. J. 26 (1943), 85118, 220–263; 27 (1944), 69–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, W., ‘A note on monotone functions’, Quart. J. Pure Appl. Math. (Oxford Ser.) 41 (1910), 7987.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Illustration of examples in Section 2.