Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T00:38:47.749Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Non-Conceptual Normative Pluralism and the Dualism of Practical Reason

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 November 2024

Jesse Hambly*
Affiliation:
School of Philosophy, Australian National University, Canberra, Australia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

According to normative pluralists there are no truths about what one ought simpliciter to do, only truths about what one ought to do according to some normative system or standpoint. In contrast with conceptual normative pluralists who argue for this conclusion on the basis that the concept of an ought simpliciter is somehow defective, non-conceptual normative pluralists defend this conclusion on first-order grounds. Non-conceptual normative pluralism has recently received a book-length defence by Mathea Slåttholm Sagdahl. In this article I critique Sagdahl's defence of non-conceptual normative pluralism. Firstly, I challenge Sagdahl's attempt to motivate non-conceptual normative pluralism by appealing to Henry Sidgwick's work on the dualism of practical reason. Secondly, I criticise her response to the most prominent argument against non-conceptual normative pluralism in the philosophical literature, the argument from nominal-notable comparisons. Thirdly, I explore the possibility of a view similar to Sagdahl's position but which accepts the ought simpliciter.

Type
Replies
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

According to normative pluralism there are no truths about what one ought simpliciter to do, only truths about what one ought to do according to some normative system or standpoint such as morality or prudence (Brown Reference Brown2023: 1–2; Case Reference Case2016: 2–3; Copp Reference Copp, Chang and Sylvan2021: 417; Sagdahl Reference Sagdahl2022: 7 & 33). Normative pluralism divides into conceptual and non-conceptual varieties. Conceptual normative pluralism (‘CP’) holds that the concept of an ought simpliciter is confused, incoherent, or in some other way defective.Footnote 1 Non-conceptual normative pluralism (‘NCP’) shares a commitment to the claim that there are no truths about one ought simpliciter to do but denies that this is because the very concept of an ought simpliciter is defective. NCP has recently received an impressive book-length defence by Mathea Slåttholm Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022). Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 33) contends that concept of an ought simpliciter is ‘coherent but empty’.

In this article I assess several key elements of Sagdahl's defence of NCP, in particular, her positive case for the view which draws on Henry Sidgwick's (Reference Sidgwick1874/1884/1907) work on the dualism of practical reason. I argue that Sagdahl does not provide a compelling case for NCP. I also argue that she does not provide a successful response to the most prominent objection to NCP in the philosophical literature, the argument from nominal-notable comparisons. Finally, I explore the possibility of a view similar to Sagdahl's position in many respects, but which accepts the ought simpliciter.

2. Sagdahl and Sidgwick

Sagdahl attempts to justify normative pluralism in a way that avoids an ‘unrestricted pluralism’, according to which any source of standards (e.g., medieval chivalry or imprudence) provides us with genuine reasons and oughts.Footnote 2 ‘Some standards’, Sagdahl contends, ‘are too bad or crazy to qualify as making genuine normative claims on us’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 50). Sagdahl's strategy for avoiding unrestricted pluralism is to reject what she calls the ‘top-down’ approach to normativity (a position characteristic of CP) which takes reasons and oughts to ‘flow from’ or be ‘issued by’ a source of standards (Reference Sagdahl2022: 52–53). Rather, Sagdahl adopts a ‘bottom up’ approach according to which ‘rather than starting with principles, codes or standpoints and taking oughts and reasons to be issued by them, we should use reasons as our basic unit of analysis’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 53), where ‘being a reason is not a mere formal feature of some system but some substantive relation of what we truly ought to do’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 55).

As Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 56–57) recognises, her ‘bottom up’ approach to normativity does not obviously lend itself to normative pluralism. How do we arrive at normative pluralism on this approach to normativity? Sagdahl's answer is that ‘there are different sets of reasons, and these sets are mutually incommensurable. It is not possible to force these sets of reasons into a single unified picture of the way in which reasons count against or in favour of certain actions’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 57). By ‘incommensurable’ Sagdahl means such reasons are noncomparable; it is not possible to order them according to any comparative relation such as strength or weight (Reference Sagdahl2022: 24–26).Footnote 3

Before I explain Sagdahl's case for the conclusion there are different sets of noncomparable reasons, I want to emphasise that Sagdahl's claims about reasons appear perfectly compatible with the existence of ‘unqualified’, ‘plain’, or simpliciter reasons.Footnote 4 After all, on Sagdahl's view, reasons are not fundamentally code or standpoint relative; reasons are not reasons-according-to-standpoint S (cf. Copp Reference Copp, Chang and Sylvan2021: 417–18). Rather, moral and prudential reasons are just different kinds of a single type of thing, namely, what she labels ‘genuine normative reasons’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 165). Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 3) appears to think that genuine normative reasons can be classed as moral or prudential because, very roughly speaking, prudential reasons concern what would make your own life go well while moral reasons ‘also concern the welfare and good lives of others.’Footnote 5

Sagdahl's defence of the thesis that there are distinct sets of noncomparable reasons draws on Sidgwick's work on the dualism of practical reason, which Sidgwick conceives of as concerning a conflict between utilitarianism and egoism. These theories, as developed by Sidgwick, tell us, respectively, that we ought to do what would bring about the greatest general or universal happiness (understood in terms of pleasure) and that we ought to do what would bring about our own greatest happiness. Sidgwick thought that we are justified accepting both theories, leading him to despair about the possibility of arriving at a consistent theory of practical reason.Footnote 6 What Sagdahl finds attractive in Sidgwick's work is the idea that morality and prudence are two distinct sources of reasons which generate oughts that may conflict with each other and that there is no way to resolve this conflict (Reference Sagdahl2022: 63–64). Sagdahl finds a way of defending these claims in Sidgwick's work that she uses to motivate the thesis that moral and prudential reasons are noncomparable (‘the noncomparability thesis’). This is the idea that we can occupy two different ‘points of view’ or ‘standpoints’ and from these two standpoints different actions are recommended or required. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 64) approvingly quotes Sidgwick's remarks in the third edition of the Methods of Ethics (Reference Sidgwick1884: 402) that the dualism of practical reason:

consists in the inevitable twofold conception of a human individual as a whole in himself, and a part of a larger whole. There is something different which is reasonable for him to desire when he considers himself as an independent unit, and something again which he must recognise as reasonably to be desired, when he takes the point of view of a larger whole.Footnote 7

Importantly, Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 65–66) explains that she understands standpoints as allowing us to appreciate the normative significance of certain facts, stating that ‘it is not these perspectives themselves that are fundamental but rather the facts that underlie them’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 66).Footnote 8

An important complication for Sagdahl's use of standpoints to defend the noncomparability thesis is that – at least as Sagdahl interprets the notion of a standpoint – we can adopt a variety of other standpoints, such as those of our family, our nation, and our species. Why don't facts about our membership of these groups – or these ‘identities’ as Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 70) also puts it – generate noncomparable reasons and oughts?Footnote 9 What's so special about the personal point of view and the general (universal) point of view? Sagdahl's (Reference Sagdahl2022: 71–72 & 75–76) answer to this question involves (tentatively) appealing to David Brink's (Reference Brink, Cullity and Gaut1997) work which explores a Kantian route for arriving at something like the dualism of practical reason. Brink argues that Kant may be committed to something like the dualism of practical reason in roughly the following way: Kant holds that moral requirements apply to us in so far as we are rational agents; they concern what we must will or value qua rational agent – i.e., qua creatures who are capable of deliberative self-governance (Reference Brink, Cullity and Gaut1997: 274–75). Consequently, such requirements are reason-giving (Reference Brink, Cullity and Gaut1997: 280–81). (I don't think that this conclusion follows but I'll ignore this issue for the moment.) But, as well as essentially being rational agents, we are essentially particular rational agents; we are rational agents numerically distinct from other rational agents. Brink (Reference Brink, Cullity and Gaut1997: 288) contends that:

Given that there are a plurality of purely rational agents, there must be requirements concerned with my own agency that apply to me just in so far as I am a particular rational agent, independently of my contingent interests and desires, just as Kant believes there are requirements of impartial concern that apply to me simply in so far as I am a rational agent.

Brink (Reference Brink, Cullity and Gaut1997: 288) labels these ‘requirements of categorical prudence’ and suggests that they are requirements to promote one's own rational agency.

The first point to note about Brink's Kantian argumentFootnote 10 is that it is not obvious that a requirement to promote one's own rational agency will correspond to what we intuitively think of as prudence. To see this, consider certain cases of suicide. Suppose I choose to end my own life because I am in chronic pain. This looks like an example of doing something which benefits me but frustrates my own agency. Secondly, and more significantly, Brink's argument relies on a controversial constitutivist approach to normativity – one that I find unconvincing for reasons explained by David Enoch (Reference Enoch2006, Reference Enoch and Brady2011, Reference Enoch, Chang and Sylvan2021), among others. Thirdly, Brink does not really make a case for the idea that we must adopt the end of promoting our own rational agency separate from the end of promoting rational agency as such. Brink just asserts that there must be requirements of categorical prudence because we are particular rational agents, but he does not argue that we, qua particular rational agents, must value our own rational agency as such (as opposed to rational agency generally). Perhaps a case for this conclusion can be made. In fact, I think it is much easier to make a case for this conclusion than the conclusion we must value rational agency generally,Footnote 11 but Brink does not make it. In so far as Sagdahl attempts to privilege the personal standpoint and the universal standpoint using Brink's work, she inherits all the problems I have explained here. Drawing on Brink's Kantian argument also strikes me as overly committal, requiring that one buy into a wholesale Kantian approach to ethics. I raise this point in part because Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 68) worries that Sidgwick's own way of defending the noncomparability thesis is overly committed to a particular view of the contents of morality and prudence.Footnote 12

Before I move on to consider Sagdahl's response to a prominent objection to normative pluralism, I want to discuss Derek Parfit's (Reference Parfit2011: Ch. 6) reply to what he takes to be Sidgwick's argument for the noncomparability thesis. I do this because Parfit's discussion of Sidgwick involves a development of the notion of a point of view which is arguably distinct from Sagdahl's identity-based interpretation of the idea. I want to show that this alternative interpretation is no more promising for defending the noncomparability thesis.

Parfit suggests that Sidgwick's argument for noncomparability has the following form: to compare moral and prudential reasons we would need to be capable of adopting a third, neutral point of view separate from the personal of view and the impartial (universal) point of view, but there is no such point of view. Parfit's (Reference Parfit2011: 135) reply is that ‘To be able to compare partial and impartial reasons, we don't need to have some third, neutral point of view. We can compare these two kinds of reasons from our actual, personal point of view’. Parfit (Reference Parfit2011: 40) tells us that ‘We have an impartial point of view when we are considering possible events that would affect or involve people who are all strangers to us.’ Moreover, even when ‘our actual point of view is not impartial’ we can think about events ‘from an imagined impartial point of view’. I am broadly sympathetic with Parfit's response to Sidgwick, although I would put things differently: We can think about the reasons we would have for (e.g.,) choices in some situation when those choices would only affect strangers. Similarly, we can consider the same situation from a partial point of view where those affected by our choices are ourselves and people that we care about. (That is to say, we hold fixed all details of the situation which are not related to the identity of the people involved.) When we think about a situation in these two different ways, we may discover different reasons for choosing between various options. Compare, for instance, choosing between distributing some benefit between two agents A and B when they are strangers and when you are one of A and B. If you are, say, A, you have a reason to distribute the good to A given by the fact that doing so would benefit you that you do not have when A and B are strangers (Fletcher Reference Fletcher2021: 21–22). This does not mean that those reasons which we appreciate when we adopt a partial point of view are not reasons when we are considering a situation from an impartial point of view or vice versa; these points of view do not create reasons. We can ask a question about the relative strength of those reasons which we appreciate from the impartial point of view and those we can appreciate from the partial point of view. I do not see how adding some third point of view is necessary or even helpful for answering this question, at least given the assumption that a point of view is just a device for helping us to appreciate reasons that we in fact have.

3. The argument from nominal-notable comparisons

Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: Ch. 5) responds to what is probably the most prominent challenge to normative pluralism in the philosophical literature, namely, ‘the argument from nominal-notable comparisons’. This argument is focused on cases where you could do some significant moral good at a small prudential cost or vice versa. In such cases it seems that you ought simpliciter to choose the notable good (Crisp Reference Crisp2006: 132; Dorsey Reference Dorsey and Shafer-Landau2013: 119–20; Hills Reference Hills2010: 31; Parfit Reference Parfit2011: 135–36). For example, consider (a slightly modified version of) Roger Crisp's (Reference Crisp2006: 132) Two Doors case:

You are confronted by two doors. If you pass through door A, you will experience a minor twinge in your leg, but nothing further will happen. If you pass through door B, you will not experience the twinge, but some other person, a stranger and out of sight, will suffer an extremely painful electric shock.

In Two Doors it seems that the following is true: you prudentially ought to pass through door B, you morally ought to pass through door A, and you also ought simpliciter to pass through door A. There is a conflict between the recommendations of prudence and morality and the moral reason in favour of going through door A (that doing so will avoid another person suffering serious harm) outweighs the prudential reason for going through door B (that passing through door B would mean you avoid some discomfort).

Before I continue, I should note a feature of Sagdahl's discussion of nominal-notable cases: her discussion of such cases is framed in terms of conflicting moral and prudential requirements (or a moral or prudential requirement to φ and a prudential or moral permission to ψ) rather than conflicting moral and prudential oughts.Footnote 13 Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 17–19) tells us that moral and prudential requirements, like moral and prudential oughts, are explained by moral and prudential reasons. However, she does not explain how she thinks of the relationship between moral or prudential oughts and moral or prudential requirements, although she does appear to commit herself to the view that moral and prudential requirements entail moral and prudential oughts.Footnote 14 Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 116) contends that nominal-notable cases need to involve a nominal reason ‘sufficient to ground a normative requirement or permission’ because otherwise this nominal prudential or moral reason could be outweighed by some other prudential or moral reason. However, there is no danger of this if we operate with a nominal prudential or moral reason which grounds a prudential or moral ought. Despite this, for the sake of continuity with Sagdahl's own discussion, I will follow her in framing nominal-notable cases using requirements from this point onwards.

A second feature of Sagdahl's discussion of nominal-notable cases I need to register is that Sagdahl's discussion of such cases proceeds in terms of whether there is something that one ‘ought all things considered’ to do in such cases. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 35) thinks that she can accept that there is an all things considered ought on a particular understanding of the idea, specifically, a ‘quantificational’ understanding of ‘ought all things considered’ according to which one ought all things considered to φ when all relevant normative standpoints agree that one ought to φ. In the context of the argument from nominal-notable comparisons, what is at issue between Sagdahl and her opponent is whether there are cases that show that when one of morality or prudence requires you to φ and the other requires (or permits) you to not φ, there is a fact about what you ought to do – where the relevant ought takes into account both morality and prudence but is authoritative over the verdicts of morality and prudence (cf. Sagdahl Reference Sagdahl2022: 116). I use ‘ought simpliciter’ to refer to this ought. This terminological choice allows me to avoid – as Sagdahl is forced to do – having to distinguish between different ways of understanding the notion of an all things considered ought. In her discussion of the argument from nominal-notable comparisons, Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 125) distinguishes the pluralist-friendly quantificational sense of ought all things considered from what ‘one ought all things considered to do, in the overarching normative sense’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 125).Footnote 15

Sagdahl's (Reference Sagdahl2022: 117–23) first response to the argument from nominal-notable comparisons – focused on the variant involving cases where prudence is the nominal good such as Two Doors – is to suggest that such cases, in so far as they in fact involve a conflict between morality and prudence, may not be possible. This is because it would be imprudent to pursue a nominal prudential benefit at a notable moral cost; choosing the nominal prudential benefit, and having the moral vices that would lead one to be the sort of person who would choose the nominal prudential benefit, are likely to lead one to have an overall prudentially worse life. In other words, prudence would not require or permit you take the nominal prudential good but rather would require you to take the moral option. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 124–25) suggests that if both morality and prudence require you to φ then you ought all things considered to φ in her quantificational sense, allowing her to capture the verdict that there is something that you ought all things considered to do in the relevant cases (when properly interpreted to reveal that they do not involve a conflict between morality and prudence).

Sagdahl recognises that how convincing one finds her case for the conclusion that prudence would require one to take the notable moral good in the relevant cases will depend on one's views about the nature of prudence. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 123) acknowledges that this conclusion looks less plausible if one accepts a view like hedonism. This is correct, but the point also extends to desire-satisfaction theories. I am sympathetic to hedonism or a desire-satisfaction theory. However, I cannot defend these views here.Footnote 16 Moreover, Sagdahl herself does little to motivate the sorts of ‘more sophisticated’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 123) theories of prudence that she favours. Consequently, I will limit myself to observing that this is a point at which one's sympathy for Sagdahl's discussion will depend significantly on one's background commitments.

Sagdahl's second response to nominal (prudential)-notable (moral) cases is to offer a way to debunk the intuition that there is something that one ought simpliciter to do in such cases. Sagdahl (tentatively) suggests that cases where prudence and morality conflict for an agent in this way have features that should make us doubt this intuitive verdict. She (Reference Sagdahl2022: 125–26) suggests that for such a case to arise – i.e., in order for a nominal (prudential)-notable (moral) case which genuinely involves a conflict between prudence and morality to be possible – the relevant agent would be psychologically unfamiliar to us because they have an ‘exceptional motivational structure’, and they would be in circumstances very different from those we are accustomed to. The relevant agent would be such that they:

(1) do not have the same interest in the concerns of ordinary human being, such as an interest in love, respect, and genuine relationships; (2) do not suffer from guilt; (3) do not have an interest in cultivating moral virtues; and (4) are in an exceptional circumstance where the risk of damaging sanctions are absolutely minimal.

To return to Crisp's Two Doors case described above, (1)–(4) are supposed to make us doubt the reliability of the judgement that the agent ought simpliciter to take the moral option – i.e., to go through door A (which results in a minor twinge in the agent's leg and no harm to anyone else). However, if we suppose the truth of (1)–(4) should make us doubt the reliability of the judgement that the agent ought simpliciter to take the moral option, the truth of (1)–(4) may also call into question the reliability of the judgement that the agent has sufficient reason to take the moral option in Two Doors. Sagdahl is committed to this latter verdict about the Two Doors case. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 165–66) states that on her view we have sufficient reason to act in accordance with moral requirements and sufficient reason to act in accordance with prudential requirements. Both options are, as she also puts it (Reference Sagdahl2022: 164), ‘rationally eligible’. We can stipulate that in the Two Doors case morality requires you go through door A while prudence requires you to go through door B.Footnote 17 To illustrate this claim about the way Sagdahl's debunking response may threaten her own view, I will draw on Sagdahl's own discussion of how (1)–(4) threaten the reliability of judgements such as the judgement that the agent ought simpliciter to go through door A but apply her points to the judgement that the agent has sufficient reason to go through door A. To paraphrase Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 125–27), we need to recognise that, if (1)–(4) obtain, the judgement that the agent has sufficient reason to go through door A may be distorted by the following factors: (i) our values, which do not align with those of the imagined agent in the case, making it hard to put ourselves in their shoes; (ii) our inability to really imagine there being no risk to the agent of sanctions for going through door B; and (iii) moral outrage towards any agent who would go through door B. My point here is that (i)–(iii) could be used to try to debunk the intuition that the agent has sufficient reason to go through door A, not only the intuition that the agent ought simpliciter to go through door A.

Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 136–37) also discusses nominal-notable cases where prudence is the notable good requiring you to φ and morality is the nominal good requiring you to ψ. Sagdahl dismisses the possibility of such cases because she suggests that morality plausibly contains agent-centred prerogatives which allow an agent to prioritise her own well-being. Consequently, it will not be the case that the agent is morally required to choose the nominal moral good. However, it is plausible that morality is not always sensitive to personal cost. Consider the following case: Tom receives a great deal of pleasure from surreptitiously spying on Grace, deeply desires to spy on Grace, and spying on Grace is one of his central life projects which provides him with a sense of meaning and purpose. Tom's spying on Grace seems impermissible despite the prudential cost of ceasing and the impermissibility of his action does not seem to change if the cost to him of ceasing to spy on her increases. Cost does not always make a difference to the moral status of actions (Holden Reference Holden2023: 68–69). If we can identify a case where cost does not make a moral difference, then we may be able to identify a nominal-notable case with the relevant structure.Footnote 18

Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 138–39) considers a kind of nominal (moral)-notable (prudential) case which she does think may be possible. Suppose that morality permits you to take either the nominal moral good or the notable prudential good while prudence requires that you take the notable prudential good. Commenting on cases with this structure, Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 139) says that ‘an agent who cares both about morality's demands and about his or her own interests…need have no qualms about taking the prudential option and disregarding the nominal moral reason, as the agent is all things considered justified in doing so.’ I presume ‘justified’ here is being used as a synonym for ‘permitted’. As Sagdahl notes (Reference Sagdahl2022: 139) she can employ a quantificational understanding of ‘all things permitted’ to say than an agent is all things permitted to take the prudentially required option in this case because both morality and prudence permit taking this option. However, her view cannot capture what I take to be the overwhelmingly plausible verdict that you ought to take the prudentially required option and, consequently, that you would make a serious mistake if you took the other option.

A powerful way of rejecting the noncomparability thesis related to the argument from nominal-notable comparisons (especially the variant considered in the previous paragraph) is Spencer Case's (Reference Case2016: 13–14) ‘concurrence argument’. Suppose that one has three options: Option 1 is morally better than option 2 but prudentially worse, option 2 is prudentially better than option 1 but morally worse, and option 3 is just as morally good as option 1 and just as prudentially good as option 2. Case suggests that it is obvious that one ought to choose option 3 and that the ‘ought’ here is the ought simpliciter. Sagdahl's chief response to Case's concurrence argumentFootnote 19 draws on her first reply to nominal (prudential)-notable (moral) comparison arguments; she (Reference Sagdahl2022: 140) suggests that if ‘morality and prudence are entangled’ in the way she thinks ‘such that there are always notable moral reasons to act prudently and notable prudential reasons to act morally’, then Case's concurrence scenario ‘may, after all, be impossible, as both standpoints would, in fact, uniquely favour [option] 3’. However, once again, one's sympathy with this response will depend on one's sympathy for Sagdahl's views about the correct theory of prudence.Footnote 20

4. Noncomparability, sufficient reason, and the ought Simpliciter

My final challenge to Sagdahl's case for NCP concerns Sagdahl's move from the noncomparability thesis to the conclusion that there are no truths about what agents ought simpliciter to do. Why not accept the noncomparability thesis but hold that what we ought simpliciter to do is either what prudence tells us we ought to do or what morality tells us we ought to do, but neither option individually? Buridan's donkey cases mean that everyone should agree that there are instances where one ought to (φ or ψ) but not φ or ψ individually (cf. Sagdahl Reference Sagdahl2022: 99). (The normative pluralist can read the ‘ought’ in the previous sentence as a qualified ought within a single normative standpoint like prudence.) I see no in principle barrier to making sense of this view which combines noncomparability and acceptance of the ought simpliciter on Sagdahl's picture of the normative domain, given the points I made in Section (2) about her view being consistent with the existence of unqualified or simpliciter reasons. Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 183) considers something in the vicinity of this view under the label ‘weak monism’ but frames it as holding that we have a set of options which are all plain (simpliciter) permitted. She (Reference Sagdahl2022: 186) says that its ‘mysterious’ how we can go from qualified oughts to unqualified permissions. I do not find it mysterious that we can go from qualified oughts to an unqualified disjunctive ought if qualified oughts are ultimately explained by unqualified reasons.

This view I am proposing has the advantage of cohering well with the plausible claim that there are cases in which, when morality (or prudence) does not recommend any available option, one ought simpliciter to φ because of the prudential (or moral) reasons in favour of φ-ing. For example, take a case where there are no moral reasons concerning which option you should take but prudence favours one of the options more than the others.Footnote 21 Sagdahl thinks that she can capture the judgement that you ought all things considered to φ in such cases by using her ‘quantificational’ understanding of the all things considered ought (introduced in Section (3) above). I am not convinced that this is correct because this is not a case where ‘standpoints are in agreement’ (Reference Sagdahl2022: 35); morality does not ‘agree’ that you ought to φ, rather it is silent on this issue.

What is the relationship between the view I am suggesting here and the position that one has sufficient reason to do what you morally ought to do or what you prudentially ought to do? (A view which is attributed to Sidgwick by some philosophers.)Footnote 22 I think that it is plausible that if one has sufficient reason to φ and sufficient reason to ψ, one ought simpliciter to (φ or ψ). Sagdahl might object that the ought simpliciter must resolve conflicts between morality and prudence (cf. Sagdahl Reference Sagdahl2022: 143 & 216). However, it is plausible that what is essential to the idea of an ought simpliciter is that it is such that you would be making a mistake if you fail to comply with it, that if you ought simpliciter to φ it is advisable to φ, and that it is the ought which features in deliberation about what to do.Footnote 23 All of this can be true of an ought which does not settle conflicts between morality and prudence.

5. Conclusion

To conclude, I have argued that Sagdahl has not offered a convincing case for NCP. However, I highly recommend her insightful and rigorous discussion to anyone interested in these issues.

Acknowledgements

Thank you to two anonymous referees and the editor for their helpful comments. My greatest thanks go to Josef Holden for his very generous feedback on the paper.

Footnotes

1 CP is defended in Copp (Reference Copp and Copp2007, Reference Copp2009, Reference Copp, Chang and Sylvan2021), Baker (Reference Baker and Shafer-Landau2018), and Tiffany (Reference Tiffany2007). For a response to Copp's (Reference Copp and Copp2007) argument for CP see Dorsey (Reference Dorsey2016: Ch. 1).

2 For unrestricted pluralism see Baker (Reference Baker and Shafer-Landau2018) and Tiffany (Reference Tiffany2007). Copp (Reference Copp and Copp2007, Reference Copp2009) is a restricted pluralist. I take the labels ‘unrestricted pluralism’ and ‘restricted pluralism’ from Case (Reference Case2016: 1).

3 As Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 24) notes, ‘incommensurable’ is often used in philosophy to mean that two or more things (e.g., values like fairness and pleasure) lack a common unit of measurement – something which does not preclude ordinal or even imprecise cardinal comparison (Chang Reference Chang and LaFollette2013: 5–8).

4 Despite what Sagdahl says to the contrary (Reference Sagdahl2022: 7–8).

5 In this paper I will assume with Sagdahl that we can distinguish moral and prudential reasons although cf. Forcehimes and Semrau (Reference Forcehimes and Semrau2018).

6 See Book IV, Ch. VI of the first edition of the Methods of Ethics (Reference Sidgwick1874). Sidgwick's tone is less pessimistic in later editions but even in the seventh and final edition (Reference Sidgwick1907: 508) he is clear that there is a ‘fundamental contradiction’ that he does not know how to resolve. For discussion of Sidgwick's work on the dualism of practical reason see Crisp (Reference Crisp2015: Ch. 7), Phillips (Reference Phillips2011: Ch. 5; Reference Phillips2022: Ch. 11), and de Lazari-Radek and Singer (Reference de Lazar-Radek and Singer2014: Ch. 6).

7 Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 65) also appeals to Sidgwick's famous ‘distinction passage’ in the Methods of Ethics (Reference Sidgwick1907: 498) to motivate the significance of the individual or personal point of view. Sidgwick claims that ‘it would be contrary to Common Sense to deny that the distinction between any one individual and any other is real and fundamental, and that consequently ‘I’ am concerned with the quality of my existence as an individual in a sense, fundamentally important, in which I am not concerned with the quality of the existence of other individuals; and this being so, I do not see how it can be proved that this distinction is not to be taken as fundamental in determining the ultimate end of rational action for an individual.’ For critical discussion of the distinction passage see Shaver (Reference Shaver1999: 83–98).

8 Cf. Crisp (Reference Crisp2015: 198 & 231) on Sidgwick's understanding of the notion of a point of view: ‘The notion of a point of view here, then, is epistemological. It is not, for example, as if I have a reason to promote my own happiness only when I am attending to the distinction between individuals’ (Reference Crisp2015: 231). I think that there may be interesting non-epistemological ways to develop the notion of a point of view, but I cannot pursue this line of thought here.

9 For discussion of this issue in the context of Sidgwick's work see Shaver (Reference Shaver1999: 89–95).

10 I should note that it is not clear whether Brink himself endorses this argument.

11 Cf. Korsgaard (Reference Korsgaard1996). Korsgaard's case that we must value our own rational agency (Reference Korsgaard1996: Lecture 3) is much more convincing than her case we must value others’ rational agency (Reference Korsgaard1996: Lecture 4).

12 To be fair to Sagdahl, she is alert to the worry I am raising here (Reference Sagdahl2022: 74–75).

13 Sagdahl is not alone in framing such cases in this way. See also, for instance, Dorsey (Reference Dorsey and Shafer-Landau2013: 119–20).

14 Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 124–25; see below for relevant discussion). The converse entailment is especially controversial. It seems plausible – at least conceptually – that it might be true that you morally ought to φ (in the sense that your moral reasons most strongly favour φ-ing) but not true that you are morally required to φ. One reason to think this (Darwall Reference Darwall, Lord and Maguire2016: 264–66; Reference Darwall2017: 6–7) is the possibility of supererogation understood as involving morality more highly favouring φ-ing than ψ-ing but not requiring one to φ. Note that even if one accepts a simpliciter ought, it appears that we need to distinguish what one ought simpliciter to do from what one is simpliciter required to do; it is not the case that if you simpliciter ought to φ then you are simpliciter required to φ (Portmore Reference Portmore2021: 6–7).

15 Note that in other parts of the book Sagdahl herself uses the terminology of ‘ought simpliciter’ or ‘plain’ or ‘unqualified’ ought’. I prefer the terminology of ‘ought simpliciter’ as opposed to ‘all things considered ought’ for reasons explained by Case (Reference Case2016: 3 footnote 4). See also Sagdahl (Reference Sagdahl2022: 31): ‘“all things considered” is somewhat misleading as a term for expressing the unqualified [i.e., simpliciter] ought since qualified oughts can also “consider all things.”’

16 For a defence of hedonism see Bramble (Reference Bramble2016). For a form of desire-based theory that I think has some plausibility see Heathwood (Reference Heathwood2019).

17 Of course, Sagdahl is unlikely to agree with this. However, as I understand her (Reference Sagdahl2022: 124–25), her debunking strategy is supposed to be a distinct response to nominal (prudential)-notable (moral) cases from her first response which disputes the possibility of such cases – at least in so far as they truly involve a conflict between prudence and morality. Given this dialectical situation, this stipulation is not unfair to Sagdahl.

18 An anonymous reviewer raises the following concern regarding the example involving Tom and Grace that I have relied on in this paragraph: What if Tom will die if he stops spying on Grace? Is it not the case that the moral status of Tom's action is sensitive to cost if we increase the cost to this level? This does seem plausible but I am not sure that this matters for my purposes; all I need from the example is a case where high prudential cost does not make a moral difference to the moral status of an action. One might also worry that the example involves the assumption that foregoing pleasure and having one's desires frustrated are prudential costs, but Sagdahl might reject this. Rejecting this, I think, is a significant bullet to bite.

19 Although cf. Sagdahl's (Reference Sagdahl2022: 140–41) reply to Case's (Reference Case2016: 15–17) ‘generic’ version of the concurrence argument.

20 Also, notice that Sagdahl's entanglement claim does not entail that morality and prudence will always agree in their overall verdicts. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this point.

21 Such cases are perhaps impossible according to certain moral theories, such as utilitarianism.

22 See, for instance, Parfit (Reference Parfit2011: 131). Other philosophers have (convincingly to my mind) rejected this interpretation of Sidgwick. See Crisp (Reference Crisp2015: 230, footnote 54) and Phillips (Reference Phillips2011: 139–40).

23 See Brown (Reference Brown2023) and Hambly (Reference Hambly2023) for relevant discussion.

References

Baker, Derek. 2018. ‘Skepticism about Ought Simpliciter’, in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 13 ed. Shafer-Landau, Russ (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 230–52.Google Scholar
Bramble, Ben. 2016. ‘A New Defense of Hedonism about Well-Being’, Ergo, 3.2, pp. 85112.Google Scholar
Brink, David. 1997. ‘Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy’, in Ethics and Practical Reasons eds. Cullity, Garrett and Gaut, Berys (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 255–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, James L. D. 2023. ‘On Scepticism about Ought Simpliciter’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 102.2, pp. 497511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Case, Spencer. 2016. ‘Normative Pluralism Worthy of the Name is False’, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 11.1, pp. 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, Ruth. 2013. ‘Incommensurability (and Incomparability)’, in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics ed. LaFollette, Hugh (Oxford: Blackwell) pp. 25912604.Google Scholar
Copp, David. 2007. ‘The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason’, in Morality in a Natural World ed. Copp, David (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 284308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David. 2009. ‘Toward A Pluralist and Teleological Theory of Normativity’, Philosophical Issues, 19, pp. 2137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David. 2021. ‘Normative Pluralism and Scepticism about “Ought Simpliciter’, in The Routledge Handbook of Practical Reason eds. Chang, Ruth and Sylvan, Kurt (New York: Routledge), pp. 416–37.Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 2006. Reasons and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 2015. The Cosmos of Duty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2016. ‘Making the “Hard” Problem of Moral Normativity Easier’, in Weighing Reasons eds. Lord, Errol and Maguire, Barry (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 257–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2017. ‘Moral Reasons’, Amherst Lecture in Philosophy, 12, pp. 124. <https://www.amherstlecture.org/darwall2017/> [accessed 10 July 2024].Google Scholar
de Lazar-Radek, Katarynza, and Singer, Peter. 2014. The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorsey, Dale. 2013. ‘Two Dualism of Practical Reason’, in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 8 ed. Shafer-Landau, Russ (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 114–39.Google Scholar
Dorsey, Dale. 2016. The Limits of Moral Authority. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, David. 2006. ‘Agency, Shmagency: Why Normativity Won't Come from What Is Constitutive of Action’, The Philosophical Review, 115.2, pp. 169–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, David. 2011. ‘Shmagency Revisited’, in New Waves in Meaethics ed. Brady, Michael (Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan), pp. 208–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, David. 2021. ‘Constitutivism: On Rabbits, Hats, and Holy Grails’, in The Routledge Handbook of Practical Reason eds. Chang, Ruth and Sylvan, Kurt (New York: Routledge), pp. 336–39.Google Scholar
Fletcher, Guy. 2021. Taking Prudence Seriously. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forcehimes, Andrew, and Semrau, Luke. 2018. ‘Are There Distinctively Moral Reasons?’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21.3, pp. 699717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hambly, Jesse. 2023. ‘Advice for Analytic Naturalists’, Ergo, 9.59, pp. 1604–26.Google Scholar
Heathwood, Chris. 2019. ‘Which Desires Are Relevant to Well-Being?’, Noûs 53.3, pp. 664–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2010. The Beloved Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holden, Josef. 2023. ‘A Defence of Moral Anti-Rationalism’ (unpublished doctoral thesis, Australian National University). https://doi.org/10.25911/4C9H-NQ15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters, Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Phillips, David. 2011. Sidgwickian Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, David. 2022. Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics: A Guide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Portmore, Douglas. 2021. Morality and Practical Reasons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sagdahl, Mathea Slåttholm. 2022. Normative Pluralism: Resolving Conflicts Between Moral and Prudential Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaver, Robert. 1999. Rational Egoism: A Selective and Critical History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1874/1884/1907. The Methods of Ethics, Editions 1, 3, & 7. London: Macmillan and Co. Available from https://www.hathitrust.org/.Google Scholar
Tiffany, Evan. 2007. ‘Deflationary Normative Pluralism’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume, 33, pp. 231–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar