Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T13:36:52.363Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

LEIBNIZ ON BODIES AND INFINITIES: RERUM NATURA AND MATHEMATICAL FICTIONS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 December 2021

MIKHAIL G. KATZ*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS BAR ILAN UNIVERSITY RAMAT GAN 5290002, ISRAEL
KARL KUHLEMANN
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS AND PHYSICS GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ UNIVERSITY HANNOVER D-30167 HANNOVER, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected]
DAVID SHERRY
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NORTHERN ARIZONA UNIVERSITY FLAGSTAFF, AZ 86011, USA E-mail: [email protected]
MONICA UGAGLIA
Affiliation:
Il GALLO SILVESTRE LOCALITÀ COLLINA 38 MONTECASSIANO, ITALY E-mail: [email protected]
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The way Leibniz applied his philosophy to mathematics has been the subject of longstanding debates. A key piece of evidence is his letter to Masson on bodies. We offer an interpretation of this often misunderstood text, dealing with the status of infinite divisibility in nature, rather than in mathematics. In line with this distinction, we offer a reading of the fictionality of infinitesimals. The letter has been claimed to support a reading of infinitesimals according to which they are logical fictions, contradictory in their definition, and thus absolutely impossible. The advocates of such a reading have lumped infinitesimals with infinite wholes, which are rejected by Leibniz as contradicting the part–whole principle. Far from supporting this reading, the letter is arguably consistent with the view that infinitesimals, as inassignable quantities, are mentis fictiones, i.e., (well-founded) fictions usable in mathematics, but possibly contrary to the Leibnizian principle of the harmony of things and not necessarily idealizing anything in rerum natura. Unlike infinite wholes, infinitesimals—as well as imaginary roots and other well-founded fictions—may involve accidental (as opposed to absolute) impossibilities, in accordance with the Leibnizian theories of knowledge and modality.

MSC classification

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Association for Symbolic Logic

Just as a bounded infinite line is made up of finite ones, so a finite line is made up of infinitely small ones. –Leibniz, De Quadratura Arithmetica

Infinite and infinitely small quantities can be written out of the mathematics altogether via a syncategorematic analysis in favour of expressions referring only to finite quantities and their relations. –Levey, 2021

Calculus necessary leads to them, and people who are not sufficiently expert in such matters get entangled and think they have reached an absurdity. –Leibniz, Elementa nova matheseos universalis

1 Toland’s indictment of mathematicians

In 1716, an anonymous critic claimed to identify a confusion shared by Leibniz and other philosophers of a mathematical bent:

Mais de s’imaginer, qu’ils pourront rendre compte de la nature des choses par de tels Calculs, c’est là precisement que consiste leur erreur.Footnote 1 [Reference Toland76, p. 131] (emphasis added)

The critic has by now been definitively identified as John TolandFootnote 2 (1670–1722); see [Reference Lamarra36, Reference Woolhouse78]. Toland accused Leibniz of allowing his calculus to infect his metaphysics. The critique was apparently written already in 1703Footnote 3 but only published in a 1716 volume of Histoire Critique de la Republique des Lettres.

In the same year (his last), Leibniz penned a response in a detailed letterFootnote 4 to editor Samuel Masson. The letter deals with issues of the philosophy of nature and also comments briefly upon the infinitesimal calculus. Bassler [Reference Bassler11], Arthur [Reference Arthur and De Risi6], and Rabouin and Arthur (RA) [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71] have appealed to one such comment in support of the claim that Leibnizian infinitesimals are syncategorematic (in the sense detailed in Section 3). Contextualizing the letter will help evaluate such claims.

We analyze the Leibnizian exposition on the philosophy of nature and its historical and theological context in Section 2, where we also deal with the meaning of his comments on the calculus. In Section 3 we analyze RA’s reading and show that the 1716 comments on the calculus not only provide no support for an Ishiguro-syncategorematic reading, but support a rather different interpretation of his infinitesimals: they are well-founded ‘fictions of the mind’ (mentis fictiones,Footnote 5 Leibniz to des Bosses [Reference Leibniz53]). In Section 4 we analyze the distinctions infinite number vs. infinite whole, and bounded infinity vs. unbounded infinity in Leibniz, as well as his comparison of the hornangle and inassignables. In Section 5 we analyze the meaning of infinity, fiction, and well-founded fiction in Leibniz. Here we show that, while infinite wholes contradicting the part–whole principle are absolute impossibilities, imaginary roots and infinitesimals are only accidental impossibilities, even if their definitions are taken to be only nominal. In Section 6 we present the conclusions of our contextualisation of the letter to Masson. This text extends our analysis of the Leibnizian heritage pursued in [Reference Bair, Błaszczyk, Ely, Henry, Kanovei, Katz, Katz, Kutateladze, McGaffey, Reeder, Schaps, Sherry and Shnider8] and elsewhere.

2 Monads, rerum natura, and mathematics

Leibniz opens his letter to Masson with a discussion of the concept of $\zeta\underset{\iota}{\tilde{\omega}}\text{o}\nu~(\text{z}\bar{\textrm {{o}}}\text{on})$ ,Footnote 6 i.e., living being. He describes monad as the underlying substance Footnote 7 of the z $\bar {\textrm {{o}}}$ on. According to Leibniz, the relation between nature and monadic reality is such that nature is a phenomenon, whereas the monads are the substances underlying natural phenomena. Leibniz first used the term ‘monad’ in 1696; in earlier texts he used various expressions such as ‘individual substance’ [Reference Leibniz58, p. 32], ‘atom of substance’, and ‘metaphysical point’ [Reference Leibniz58, p. 142].Footnote 8

2.1 Leibnizian Passage I

Toward the end of the letter, Leibniz turns to Toland’s claim that mathematicians are not successful as philosophers. After a bit of ad hominem, Leibniz gets down to the business of refuting the claim. His strategy is to draw a line between

  1. (1) philosophy, concerned with the ‘nature des choses’, i.e., rerum natura; and

  2. (2) mathematics, concerned with applying entities, both ideal and fictional, in geometry and physics.

Toland accused Leibniz of viewing the extension (i.e., the continuum) as made up of mathematical points (the punctiform view).Footnote 9 Leibniz first responds to this accusation, and then comments on the relation between the calculus and the nature des choses:

[Passage I:] I am also far from making extension up of mathematical points. … And, notwithstanding my infinitesimal calculus, I do not admit any real [veritable] infinite number, even though I confess that the multitude of things surpasses any finite number [la multitude des choses passe tout nombre fini], or rather any number. (Leibniz [Reference Leibniz54] as translated by Ariew in [Reference Leibniz58, p. 229])

Passage I draws a line between, on the one hand, the mathematician’s task of exploiting the well-founded fictions of the infinitesimal calculus, and on the other, the philosopher’s task of elucidating the natural phenomena (and perhaps the ultimately real monadic entities which underlie the phenomena) in the framework of an unequivocal rejection of infinite wholes.

In Sections 2.2 and 2.3 we will deal with the distinction Mathematics vs. rerum natura. The distinction infinite wholes vs. well-founded fictions will be analyzed in Section 4.

2.2 Leibnizian Passage II

Unlike the choses whose nature Leibniz seeks to explore in the 1716 letter, mathematical entities exploited in the infinitesimal calculus are only useful fictions (mentis fictiones; see Section 5.1):

[Passage II:] The infinitesimal calculus is useful with respect to the application of mathematics to physics; however, that is not how I claim to account for the nature of things [la nature des choses]. For I consider infinitesimal quantities to be useful fictions. (Leibniz [Reference Leibniz54] as translated by Ariew in [Reference Leibniz58, p. 230])

Leibniz’s comment “however, that is not how I claim to account for the nature of things” is a direct response to Toland’s allegation that Leibniz seeks to account for the nature des choses by means of his calculus (see Section 1). Garber quotes Passage II and notes:

[T]he point seems to be that nature is one thing, and its mathematical representation is another. [Reference Garber23, p. 303]

Garber points out a significant difference between the positions of Leibniz and the Cartesians:

[Leibniz’s] opponents are the Cartesians who have tried to make nature mathematical in a literal sense, to make the physical world over into a physical instantiation of mathematical concepts [whereas Leibniz] can embrace the mathematical representation of dead force in terms of infinitesimals, without having to say that there are real infinitesimals in nature. [Reference Garber23, p. 306]

Thus in Garber’s view, in Passage II Leibniz (disagreeing with the Cartesians) insists on the separation of rerum natura and its mathematical representation.

2.3 Leibnizian evolution on mathematics and rerum natura

The distinction between the mathematical realm and the rerum natura is a crucial feature of Leibniz’s mature philosophy. Whereas he started with a belief that physics could be reduced to mechanics,Footnote 10 and hence to mathematics, over the years mathematics ceased to be perceived by Leibniz as the foundation of physics and turned into a mere representation thereof.

For the young Leibniz, extension (corpus mathematicum) is a component of the matter of choses. As Leibniz explains to Thomasius, a physical body is the compound of matter—which Leibniz identifies with extension and impenetrability—and form, which he identifies with shape:

Space is a primary extended being or a mathematical body (corpus mathematicum), which contains nothing but three dimensions and is the universal locus of all things. Matter is a secondary extended being, or that which has, in addition to extension or mathematical body, also a physical body (corpus physicum), that is, resistance, antitypy, solidity, the property of filling space, impenetrability.Footnote 11 (Leibniz to Thomasius, April 20–30, 1669 [Reference Leibniz37, p. 34]. Transl. Loemker [Reference Leibniz57, p. 100] with minor changes)Footnote 12

During this phase of Leibniz’s development, physical bodies are seen as continuous, exactly as extension is. Namely, they are potentially infinitely divisible:

Matter has quantity too, though it is indefinite, or interminate as the Averroists call it. For being continuous, it is not cut into parts and therefore does not actually have boundaries. (Leibniz to Thomasius, April 20–30, 1669 [Reference Leibniz37, p. 26–27]. Transl. Loemker [Reference Leibniz57, p. 95])Footnote 13

By contrast, in his mature system, Leibniz distinguishes between mathematical extension, which is potentially infinitely divisible, and the matter of physical bodies, which is actually infinitely divided:

But in real things, that is, bodies, the parts are not indefinite—as they are in space, which is a mental thing—but actually specified in a fixed way according to the divisions and subdivisions which nature actually introduces through the varieties of motion. And granted that these divisions proceed to infinity, they are nevertheless the result of fixed primary constituents or real unities, though infinite in number. Accurately speaking, however, matter is not composed of these constitutive unities but results from them. (Leibniz to de Volder, June 30, 1704 [Reference Leibniz52, p. 268]. Transl. Loemker [Reference Leibniz57, p. 536])Footnote 14

Similarly in a March 11, 1706 letter to des Bosses, Leibniz writes:

To pass now from the ideas of geometry to the realities of physics, I hold that matter is actually fragmented into parts smaller than any given, or that there is no part of matter that is not actually subdivided into others exercising different motions. This is demanded by the nature of matter and motion and by the structure of the universe, for physical, mathematical, and metaphysical reasons. (Leibniz to des Bosses, March 11, 1706 [Reference Leibniz53, p. 305]. Transl. Look–Rutherford [Reference Leibniz61, p. 33–35])Footnote 15

The last passage is analyzed by Antognazza, who emphasizes the distinction in Leibnizian thought between the mathematical realm and the rerum natura:

Leibniz is quite consistent in pointing out that the actual infinite he is endorsing concerns the ‘real’ as opposed to the ‘ideal’ order. In the letter of March 11, 1706 to des Bosses … he explicitly stresses that in moving his attention to the actual infinite, he is shifting from the ideal to the real order. [Reference Antognazza1, p. 9]

To avoid confusion between continuous extension, which is an ideal entity, and the actual structure of physical matter, Leibniz employs for the latter the adjective contiguous:

I recall that Aristotle too distinguishes between Contiguum and Continuum: things are continuous if their extremes are one, and are contiguous if their extremes are together. (Pacidius Philaleti, 1676; Leibniz [Reference Leibniz55]. A6.3. 537)Footnote 16

Levey similarly emphasizes the difference between the actual subdivisions of the real world and the potential ones of the ideal mathematical world:

[To Leibniz,] a body is separable into various parts because it actually has contiguous parts that cohere together but which could be brought not to cohere and be separated from one another. … Potentiality, in the sense of potential divisions or potential parts, is a concept that belongs to the ‘ideal’ realm of mathematics and geometry but has no application to the world of matter. [Reference Levey63, note 6, p. 53] (emphasis in the original)

Views similar to that of Antognazza were expressed by Bosinelli [Reference Bosinelli16, p. 168] and Breger [Reference Breger and Li17, p. 124], as acknowledged by Arthur in [Reference Arthur, Nachtomy and Winegar5, p. 156]. But especially, they were expressed by Leibniz himself, who specifically warned his readers against the misunderstandings arising from the conflation of the two realms:

It is the confusion of the ideal with the actual which has muddled everything and caused the labyrinth of the composition of the continuum. (Remarques sur les Objections de M. Foucher, 1695. Gerhardt [Reference Gerhardt25, vol. IV, p. 491]. Transl. Ariew–Garber [Reference Leibniz58, p. 146])Footnote 17

A detailed study of the issue appears in [Reference Ugaglia, Ademollo, Amerini and De Risi77].

Just as the Leibnizian Passage I in Section 2.1, Passage II in Section 2.2 draws a line between the fictional entities (mentis fictiones) of the infinitesimal calculus—well-founded fictions, or useful fictions, as Leibniz also calls them—and the entities of rerum natura. The conflation of the two realms is behind some of the purported evidence in favor of the so-called syncategorematic reading, analyzed in Section 3.

3 Syncategorematics vs. keeping bodies and calculus separate

RA follow [Reference Ishiguro30, chap. 5] in interpreting the Leibnizian term ‘useful fiction’ syncategorematically via a logical analysis of the quantifier clause ‘smaller than every given’. This stance enables RA to claim that Leibnizian infinitesimals are ‘in keeping with the Archimedean axiom’ [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, Abstract] (in the previous installment by Arthur [Reference Arthur4] the refrain was ‘fully in accord with the Archimedean Axiom’).

3.1 Small magnitudes vs. Ishiguro’s alternating quantifiers

In 1990, Ishiguro formulated the following hypothesis concerning Leibnizian infinitesimals:

It seems then that throughout his working life as a mathematician Leibniz did not think of founding the calculus in terms of a special kind of small magnitude. [Reference Ishiguro30, p. 86] (emphasis added)

To explain in what sense Leibniz allegedly did not found the calculus on a special kind of small magnitude, she elaborates as follows:

It seems that when we make reference to infinitesimals in a proposition, we are not designating a fixed magnitude incomparably smaller than our ordinary magnitudes. Leibniz is saying that whatever small magnitude an opponent may present, one can assert the existence of a smaller magnitude. In other words, we can paraphrase the proposition with a universal proposition with an embedded existential claim. (ibid., p. 87; emphasis on ‘ordinary’, ‘universal’, and ‘existential’ added)

Accordingly, when Leibniz asserted that his inassignable $dx$ , or alternatively $\epsilon $ , was smaller than every assignable quantity Q, he really meant that for each given $Q>0$ there exists an ‘ordinary’ $\epsilon>0$ such that $\epsilon <Q$ .

Ishiguro interprets Leibniz’s uses of the term ‘infinite quantity’ by a similar paraphrase involving embedded quantifiers. Such an approach has been described as a syncategorematic treatment of statements involving ‘infinite’ and its cognates. Ishiguro goes on to compare the theories of Leibniz and Russell and concludes:

The similarity which we find in the two theories lies in the common intention Leibniz and Russell have of understanding a sentence which ostensibly designates a specific entity, as really, in its logical form, being a quantified sentence; i.e., a universal or an existential sentence. (ibid., p. 99; emphasis on ‘logical’ added)

Taking her cue from Russell, Ishiguro reads Leibnizian ‘useful fictions’ as logical fictions.Footnote 18 In the same vein, Levey writes:

[T]he fiction is intended by Leibniz to be ‘logical’ in character: infinite and infinitely small quantities can be written out of the mathematics altogether via a syncategorematic analysis in favour of expressions referring only to finite quantities and their relations. [Reference Levey, Shapiro and Hellman64, p. 148]

By a similar quantifier sleight-of-hand, RA declare Leibniz’s uses of the term ‘infinitesimal’ to be “fully-in-accord/in-keeping with the Archimedean axiom” (see further in Section 3.3).

3.2 Rabouin on syncategorematic entities

In 2013, Rabouin toys with “the idea that the entities being studied are relational or in Leibniz’s parlance ‘syncategorematic’” [Reference Rabouin67, p. 120] and adds: “This is the reason why Leibniz calls them fictitia (they are terms not referring to individual beings, but to some relational properties)” (ad loc., note 40).

On the other hand, in 2015, Rabouin seeks to distance himself from attributing hidden quantifiers to Leibniz, in the following terms:

The core of the demonstration … is the arbitrariness of the choice of $\varepsilon $ . But this arbitrariness does not amount, in modern terms, to a universal quantification (at least in classical first order logic), which would be meaningless to Leibniz. [Reference Rabouin and Jullien68, p. 362]

Yet in note 25 on the same page Rabouin appears to endorse Ishiguro’s reading: “It is, in Leibniz’ terminology, a ‘syncategorematic’ entityFootnote 19 see Ishiguro (1990) …” (ibid.). Rabouin goes on to claim the following:

It should then be clear why infinitesimals were called by Leibniz ‘fictions’. In and of itself, there is no such thing as a ‘quantity smaller than any other quantity’. This would amount to the existence of a minimal quantity and one can show that a minimal quantity implies contradiction. (ibid.; emphasis added)

What are we to make of Rabouin’s claimed detection of contradiction? While it is true that there is no such thing as a nonzero quantity smaller than any other quantity, Leibniz requires his inassignable infinitesimals to be smaller, not than every quantity, but rather than every assignable quantity; for an illustration in terms of hornangles see Section 4.5. This accords with a glossary entry in (Rabouin’s 2020 coauthor) Arthur’s volume of translations. Here an infinitesimal is defined as

a part smaller than any assignable (see INASSIGNABILIS), a definition to which Leibniz frequently has recourse.Footnote 20 [Reference Arthur2, p. 452]

Thus a particular infinitesimal $\epsilon>0$ will satisfy

(3.1) $$ \begin{align} \epsilon<\frac12,\; \epsilon<\frac13,\; \epsilon<\frac14,\; \text{etc.}, \end{align} $$

so long as the denominator is assignable. Due to what appears to be a mathematical misunderstanding, Rabouin is led to a conclusion that a bona fide infinitesimal would be contradictory and hence ‘fictional’.

Once one realizes that the contradiction is not there to begin with, there is no compelling reason to interpret Leibnizian fictionalism as the counterpart of an allegedly contradictory nature of infinitesimals, as Rabouin does in 2015. A geometric illustration of (3.1) in terms of hornangles appears in Section 4.5.

3.3 Letter to Masson and RA’s quantifiers

In Section 3.2, we examined Rabouin’s 2015 attempt to declare Leibnizian infinitesimals contradictory. Five years later in 2020, one finds a related attempt to declare Leibnizian infinitesimals contradictory by Rabouin and Arthur (RA) in [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71] (see also Section 4.2). Infinitesimals do contradict the Archimedean axiom, but if this is what RA mean by their contradictory claim, then their argument (in support of the contention that Leibnizian allegedly syncategorematic infinitesimals are ‘in keeping with the Archimedean axiom’) would be circular: the positing of the Archimedean axiom predetermines the conclusion that non-Archimedean infinitesimals are contradictory.Footnote 21

In search of evidence in support of an Ishiguroan interpretation, RA turn to the 1716 letter to Masson where Leibniz employs the quantifier clause

‘la multitude des choses passe tout nombre fini’.

Via the quantifier clause, RA seek to establish a connection between useful fictions and logical fictions, ‘in keeping with the Archimedean axiom’.

However, in his 1716 letter Leibniz is not referring to mathematical entities, whether fictional or ideal, when he employs the quantifier clause above. Rather, he is referring to natural phenomena and the monads which underlie them (see Section 2). Neither natural phenomena nor the monads are useful fictions, unlike infinitesimals. The quantifier clause in the 1716 letter therefore does not refer to mathematical entities such as infinitesimals and infinite quantities. Rather, it merely reasserts Leibniz’s opposition to infinite wholes as contradictory. RA claim the following similarity:

Leibniz insisted that since every body is actually divided by motions within it into further bodies that are themselves similarly divided without bound, bodies ‘are actually infinite, that is to say, more bodies can be found than there are unities in any given number whatever’ (A VI 4, 1393; LLC 235). That is, their multiplicity ‘surpasses every finite number’. $^{26}$

Similarly, when Pierre Varignon asked Leibniz for clarification of his views on the infinitely small in 1702, Leibniz replied (February 2, 1702) that it had not been his intention ‘to assert that there are in nature infinitely small lines in all rigor, or compared with ours, nor that there are lines infinitely greater than ours’. [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 412] (emphasis on ‘Similarly’ added)

Here RA’s note 26 contains the following text:

“26 Cf. what Leibniz wrote to Samuel Masson in the last year of his life: ‘Notwithstanding my Infinitesimal Calculus, I do not at all admit a genuine infinite number, although I confess that the multiplicity of things surpasses every finite number, or rather, every number.’ (GP VI 629)”

We can agree with RA’s comments on Leibniz’s understanding of actual subdivision of bodies. However, RA also claim a similarity in reference to the following Leibnizian texts:

  1. (1) his Actu infinitae sunt creaturae (1678–81);

  2. (2) letter to Varignon (1702);

  3. (3) letter to Masson (1716).

The alleged similarity is apparently based on Leibniz’s calling into question certain notions of infinity in these texts. We analyze their claim in Section 3.4.

3.4 Comparison of letters to Varignon and Masson

In connection with the comparison of the letters, we note the following three points.

1. Notwithstanding the fact that Leibniz briefly mentions the infinitesimal calculus in the 1716 passage, the substance of the sentence is not concerned with infinitesimal calculus, but rather is a reflection on the philosophy of nature that Leibniz deliberately contrasted with the calculus. What is put into question in the 1716 letter is the concept of an infinite taken as a whole (deemed contradictory by Leibniz), in the context of a metaphysical analysis of body and substance.

Meanwhile, the 1702 comment addressed to Varignon deals, not with metaphysics, but with mathematical fictions (the relevant passage from the letter to Varignon appears in Section 5.2 at note 53). Notice that, unlike the 1716 passage, the 1702 passage does not even mention ‘number’, but speaks rather of geometric objects, such as infinitely large lines (i.e., line segments), which are instances of Leibnizian bounded infinity contrasted with unbounded infinite wholes (see Sections 4.3 and 4.4). The 1702 passage reasserts the Leibnizian position that infinitesimal lines need not idealize anything in nature to be useful, and in this sense can be taken to be fictional; see Section 4. Therefore RA’s claimed similarity has no basis.

2. A similar conflation affects RA’s use of the Leibnizian phrase

“So bodies are actually infinite, i.e., more bodies can be found than there are unities in any given number” (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 235])

part of which is quoted in the passage from RA appearing in Section 3.3. The phrase concerns bodies (in rerum natura) and not infinitesimals. The distinction was emphasized by both Antognazza and Levey (see Section 2.2).

3. Referring to possible connections between mathematics and philosophy in Leibniz and the interpretation that puts differential calculus at the core of Leibniz’ philosophy, Rabouin solo writes:

Leibniz was … very explicit about some connections which he resisted making—although modern commentators tend to put a lot of emphasis on them. [Reference Rabouin, Goethe, Beeley and Rabouin69, note 47, p. 69] (emphasis on ‘resisted making’ ours)

Rabouin goes on to quote Passage II from the 1716 letter (see Section 2.2) as evidence (for a reluctance on the part of Leibniz to make certain connections between mathematics and philosophy). Rabouin’s interpretation of Passage II, insisting on a segregation of mathematics and philosophy, is compatible with our view, but not with the approach pursued by Rabouin and Arthur in [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 412] that seeks to enlist the 1716 letter as evidence in favor of a syncategorematic reading of the Leibnizian calculus. In Sections 4 and 5, we develop an interpretation of Leibnizian infinitesimals that is more faithful to the Leibnizian texts.

4 Well-founded fictions: the mathematics

Leibniz described the infinitesimals of his calculus as well-founded because they perform successfully within the system of rules he developed for the calculus. Similarly, imaginaries are well-founded because mathematical experience shows that they are useful in the solution of the cubic equation and other problems.

Leibniz’s choice of the term multitude in Passage I (Section 2.1) is significant. Here Leibniz reinforces his rejection of a punctiform conception of extension by reminding the reader that he rejects a real infinite number, meaning that he rejects an infinite multitude taken as a whole (implied by the punctiform view of the continuum) as contradictory.

4.1 Part–whole principle

Leibniz held that infinite wholes would contradict the part–whole principle. Already in 1672 Leibniz wrote:

[T]here are as many squares as numbers, that is to say, there are as many square numbers as there are numbers in the universe. Which is impossible. Hence it follows either that in the infinite the whole is not greater than the part, which is the opinion of Galileo and Gregory of St. Vincent, and which I cannot accept; or that infinity itself is nothing, i.e., that it is not one and not a whole. Or perhaps we should say, distinguishing among infinities, that the most infinite, i.e., all the numbers is something that implies a contradiction, … (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 9]; emphasis added)

Thus already in 1672, Leibniz held that the infinity of all numbers—that we may today refer to as an infinite cardinalityFootnote 22 —contradicts the part–whole principle.Footnote 23 To explain Leibniz’ rejection of infinite wholes in modern terms, one could perhaps surmise that Leibniz would have rejected as incoherent the modern notion of infinite cardinality or cardinal number (a point painstakingly argued in [Reference Arthur and De Risi6]).

While Leibniz himself of course does not distinguish between infinite number and infinite cardinality, he does mention a related distinction between infinite magnitude and infinite multitude in a letter to des Bosses [Reference Leibniz53, p. 31]. The correspondence between Leibniz and Bernoulli indicates that Leibniz was clearly aware of the difference between infinite multitude and infinite number.Footnote 24 The distinction is important because Leibniz’s rejection of an infinite multitude, or collection, does not entail a rejection of infinite magnitude, or quantity, or number, provided they are not considered as a whole. What leads to contradiction is not infinity in itself but an infinity taken as a whole. Regrettably, the notions of infinite whole and infinite quantity have been conflated in recent literature. In particular, such a conflation is at the root of the Ishiguro-syncategorematic interpretation of infinitesimals, analyzed in Section 3.

4.2 Infinite wholes and infinite numbers

Both Arthur [Reference Arthur7] and Rabouin and Arthur [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71] seek to connect the Leibnizian rejection of infinite wholes and his description of infinitesimals as fictional, and to document Leibnizian rejection of infinite number. Thereby they seek to assimilate infinitesimals to infinite wholes.Footnote 25 RA claim the following:

Leibniz never changed his mind and always claimed that such entities do not exist because they imply a contradiction. One can nonetheless use infinities and infinitely small quantities in a calculation provided one can furnish a way of doing correct demonstrations with them; that is, as long as one can identify conditions under which their use will not lead to error. [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 413] (emphasis on ‘such entities’ and ‘conditions’ added)

While no such conditions are ever identified by RA, in their Conclusion they speak of using infinitesimals ‘under certain specified conditions’ [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 441], again unspecified.Footnote 26 The key issue, however, is what is meant exactly by “such entities” mentioned by RA. While Leibniz rejected as contradictory an infinite multitude taken as a whole (see Section 2), RA provide no evidence that Leibniz viewed infinitesimal and infinite quantities as contradictory (and not merely as well-founded fictions).Footnote 27

A similar conflation appears in Rabouin solo, who claims that

[Leibniz] regularly stumbled upon the fact that an ‘infinite number’ or multitude was a notion entailing a contradiction. Infinitely small numbers, of the kind introduced by Wallis in his Arithmetics of the infinites $($ Arithmetica infinitorum $)$ as inverse of infinite number, naturally inherited this qualification. [Reference Rabouin70]

The contradictory nature of infinite wholes is ‘inherited’ not by infinitesimals but by minima, i.e., points viewed as the simplest constituents of the continuum.Footnote 28

Arthur similarly conflates infinite collections and infinite number when he claims the following:

[Leibniz] held that there are actually infinitely many substances, actually infinitely many parts of matter, and actually infinitely many terms in an infinite series:Footnote 29 that is, there are so many that, however many are assigned, there are more, but there is no infinite collection of them, and therefore no infinite number. [Reference Arthur7, p. 152] (emphasis added)

Arthur’s final ‘therefore’ is a non-sequitur if the expression ‘infinite number’ is meant to include infinite quantity (in addition to infinite wholes).

The related issue of nominal definitions is discussed in Section 5.3.

4.3 Bounded and unbounded infinity

A Leibnizian distinction of long standing—at least since his De Quadratura Arithmetica (DQA), Propositio XI and the Scholium following it—is between bounded infinity and unbounded infinity; see, e.g., [Reference Knobloch33, p. 42], [Reference Knobloch, Gavroglu, Christianidis and Nicolaidis34, pp. 266–267]. In this text of fundamental importance for the foundations of the calculus, Leibniz contrasts bounded infinity and unbounded infinity in the following terms:

But as far as the activity of the mindFootnote 30 with which we measure infinite areas is concerned, it contains nothing unusual because it is based on a certain fiction and proceeds effortlessly on the assumption of a certain, though bounded, but infinite line; therefore it has no greater difficulty than if we were to measure an area that is finite in length. … Just as points, even of infinite numbers, are unsuccessfully added to and subtracted from a bounded line, so a bounded line can neither form nor exhaust an unbounded one; however, many times it has been repeated. This is different with a bounded but infinite line thought to be created by some multitude of finite lines, although this multitude exceeds any number. And just as a bounded infinite line is made up of finite ones, so a finite line is made up of infinitely small ones, yet divisible. (Leibniz, DQA [Reference Leibniz59], Scholium following Propositio XI; translation ours; emphasis added)

It is worth noting that bounded/unbounded infinity is not the same distinction as potential/actual infinity. While actual infinity (understood distributively) is possible in the material realm (see Section 2.3), unbounded infinity (understood collectively, i.e., as a whole) is a contradictory concept to Leibniz. Bounded infinity is a term Leibniz reserves mainly to discuss the well-founded fictions used in his infinitesimal calculus, namely the infinitely large and (its reciprocal) infinitely small. In one of his early articles, Knobloch observes:

[Leibniz] distinguished between two infinites, the bounded infinite straight line, the recta infinita terminata, and the unbounded infinite straight line, the recta infinita interminata. He investigated this distinction in several studies from the year 1676. Only the first kind of straight lines can be used in mathematics, as he underlined in his proof of Theorem 11 [i.e., Propositio XI]. He assumed a fictive boundary point on a straight half line which is infinitely distant from the beginning: a bounded infinite straight line is a fictitious quantity. [Reference Knobloch35, p. 97]

An unbounded infinity, which Leibniz viewed as a contradictory concept, can be exemplified by the multitude of natural numbers (which seen as a whole would contradict the part–whole principle; see Section 4.1). A bounded infinity can be exemplified by an inassignable (see below) natural number, say $\mu $ , or the multitude of all natural numbers up to $\mu $ (and thus bounded by $\mu $ ).

Leibniz defines an infinitesimal as a “fraction infiniment petite, ou dont le denominateur soit un nombre infini” [Reference Leibniz49, p. 93], such as $\frac 1\mu $ . Such infinitesimals are routinely used in computing, e.g., the differential ratio $\frac {dy}{dx}$ , as in the passage from Cum Prodiisset [Reference Leibniz48] (circ. 1701), where Leibniz also mentions the assignable/inassignable dichotomy:

[A]lthough we may be content with the assignable quantities $(d)y$ , $(d)v$ , $(d)z$ , $(d)x$ , etc., … yet it is plain from what I have said that, at least in our minds,Footnote 31 the unassignables [inassignabiles in the original Latin] $dx$ and $dy$ may be substituted for them by a method of supposition even in the case when they are evanescent … (Leibniz as translated in [Reference Child20, p. 153]).

A similar passage appears in Historia et Origo calculi differentialis a G. G. Leibnitzio conscripta.Footnote 32 The assignable/inassignable dichotomy was analyzed in the seminal study by Bos [Reference Bos15].Footnote 33 See [Reference Bair, Błaszczyk, Ely, Katz and Kuhlemann9, sec. 4] for a formalization of the dichotomy in modern mathematics.

4.4 Instances of infinita terminata

In a February 1676 text, Leibniz provided a colorful example of a bounded infinity as follows:

This is a wonder, too: that someone who has lived for infinitely many years can have begun to live, and that someone who lives for a number of years that is greater than any finite number can at some time die. From which it will follow that there is an infinite number.Footnote 34 (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 51])

In a text Numeri infiniti dated April 10, 1676, Leibniz envisioned the possibility that such numbers—examples of bounded infinities—may be prime:

Two infinite numbers which are not as two finite numbers can be commensurable, namely, if their greatest common measure [i.e., divisor] is a finite number—for instance, if both are prime. (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 87])

The dating of Numeri infiniti is significant since Arthur commits himself to a tight timeframe for an alleged switch in Leibniz’s thinking about infinitesimals.Footnote 35

RA mention the term terminata (bounded) three times in their article [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71] and specifically in the context of Propositio XI and its Scholium in DQA, but do not pay sufficient attention to the dichotomy of bounded versus unbounded infinity and fail to appreciate its significance.

Thus, in an analysis of Propositio XI involving the evaluation of a (finite) area of a region extending to infinity, Leibniz introduces

a point $(\mu )$ at infinitely small distance from the axis. In this case, indeed, the straight line $(\mu )\lambda $ will still be infinite. (Leibniz as translated by RA in [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 421]).

RA go on to explain this infinity “in the sense that it can be made greater than any given quantity (major qualibet assignabili), yet will be bounded (terminata)” (ibid.; emphasis added). However, there is no source in Leibniz for the clause “it can be made greater than any given quantity.” Rather, Leibniz wrote “it is greater than any given quantity”; RA added the clause “can be made greater, etc.” to help Leibniz conform to the Ishiguro-syncategorematic interpretation (see Section 3). RA’s addition distorts Leibniz’ intended meaning.

Leibniz concludes the discussion of bounded infinities in the Scholium following Propositio XI with the following comment:

Déterminer si la nature [natura rerum] souffre des quantités de ce genre est l’affaire du Métaphysicien; il suffit au Géomètre de démontrer ce qui résulte de leur supposition.Footnote 36 (Leibniz as translated by Parmentier in [Reference Leibniz59, p. 101]).

Here Leibniz observes that, though bounded infinities may not be found in rerum natura, their usefulness to the geometer is independent of the metaphysician’s task of elucidating their relation to natural phenomena.Footnote 37 To be useful, they needn’t be found in nature:

… Therefore everything else will also exist in the mind: and in it everything that I denied to be possible will now be possible.Footnote 38 (Leibniz, Numeri infiniti, as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 91])

The reference is to a discussion on the previous page of a circle as a fictional polygon with an infinite number of sides:

The circle—as a polygon greater than any assignable, as if that were possible—is a fictive entity, and so are other things of that kind. (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 89])

4.5 Hornangles and inassignables

Leibnizian hornangles exhibit non-Archimedean behavior (when compared to ordinary angles) not easily paraphrasable in Archimedean terms, and shed light on Leibniz’s attitude toward infinitesimals in general. We provide a geometric illustration of the phenomenon of magnitudes smaller than all assignables (see equation (3.1) in Section 3.2), in terms of the hornangle (also known as angle of contact or angle of contingence), much discussed in thirteenth to seventeenth century literature. Thus, Campanus of Novara (1220–1296) wrote that “any rectilinear angle is greater than an infinite number of angles of contingence” [Reference Murdoch, Kretzmann, Kenny, Pinborg and Stump66, pp. 580–581].

The hornangle is the “angle,” or crevice, between an arc of a circle (or a more general curve) at a point P, and its tangent ray r at P. According to Leibniz, such a hornangle is smaller than every ordinary rectilinear angle formed by the ray r and a secant ray at P.Footnote 39 Meanwhile, the hornangle is certainly not smaller than all other hornangles (including itself).

In a 1686 article, Leibniz considered a more general notion of hornangle, or angle of contact, between a pair of curves with a common tangent at P.Footnote 40 Leibniz defined the osculating circle of a curve at P as the circle forming the least angle of contact with the curve:

Circulus autem ille lineam propositam ejusdem plani in puncto proposito osculari a me dicitur, qui minimum cum ea facit angulum contactus. [Reference Leibniz42]

Choosing the least one among the angles of contact, as Leibniz does here, presupposes that such “angles” are nonzero. A few lines later, Leibniz renames such entities “angle of osculation” to distinguish them from angles of contact in the classical sense (crevice between curve and tangent ray).

Leibniz explicitly compares angles of contact to inassignables in the 1671 text Theoria motus abstracti (TMA). In this early text, Leibniz still composes the continuum of indivisible infinitesimals which he refers to as “points.” Speaking of the space filled by an infinitesimal motion of a body, Leibniz writes:

… this space is still inassignable … although the ratio of a point of a body … to the [part]Footnote 41 of space it fills when moving, is as an angle of contact to a rectilinear angle … (Leibniz as translated by Loemker [Reference Leibniz57, p. 140], TMA, Predemonstrable Foundation 13, A VI.ii N41)

In his mature period, Leibniz’s view of the continuum changes (see Section 2.3), but the non-Archimedean behavior of hornangles in comparison with ordinary rectilinear/assignable angles remains. There are at least three indications that Leibniz viewed hornangles as being nonzero.

1. Choosing the smallest one of the angles of contact as Leibniz does in 1686 presupposes that they are nonzero.

2. In a 1696 letter, Leibniz makes it clear that angles of contact are nonzero:

Our infinitesimal calculus allows us to see that one can only ignore differentias incomparabiliter minores rebus differentiatis (the differences which are incomparably smaller than the differentiated things). So, it does not follow that there is no considerable difference between the degrees of force in the object from each blow by gravitating matter. Otherwise, this would be as if one wanted to prove that angles of contact do not differ amongst themselves because they do not compare with rectilinear angles. (Leibniz to Papin, March 1696, A III, 6, 698).

Here Leibniz uses the term incomparable in the technical sense (akin to inassignable) used in his formulation of the violation of the Archimedean property in a 1695 letter to L’Hôpital.Footnote 42 Of course, they can still be compared to rectilinear angles.Footnote 43

3. A careful analysis of the two passages in [Reference Leibniz42] where Leibniz asserts that they are “nothing” reveal that his intention is to say that they are negligible vis-à-vis incomparably larger quantities: first, angles of contact are negligible vis-à-vis rectilinear angles, and second, angles of osculation are negligible vis-à-vis angles of contact.

We note the unavailability of the option of representing a hornangle by rectilinear angles—either arranged in a sequence or assorted with logical quantifiers. The non-Archimedean behavior of Leibnizian hornangles is not easily paraphrasable in Archimedean terms, suggesting similar behavior of Leibnizian inassignable infinitesimals. A similar situation exists with respect to comparison of infinitesimals and imaginary roots.Footnote 44

Infinitesimals, hornangles, and imaginaries are well-founded fictions that facilitate the art of discovery. Leibnizian well-founded fictions are at most accidentally impossible (they are not contradictory; see Section 5.3). Meanwhile, there are entities that Leibniz sometimes refers to as fictions, such as infinite wholes, which are absolutely impossible (contradictory).Footnote 45 This crucial distinction is not sufficiently taken into account by advocates of the Ishiguro-syncategorematic interpretation.

5 Well-founded fictions: the philosophy

5.1 Instantiation in rerum natura ?

On a number of occasions, Leibniz spoke of infinitesimals as not necessarily found in nature. Thus, in the Specimen Dynamicum of 1695, he concluded his analysis of infinite degrees of impetus as follows:

Hence the nisus is obviously twofold, an elementary or infinitely small one which I also call a solicitation and one formed by the continuation or repetition of these elementary impulsions, that is, the impetus itself. But I do not mean that these mathematical entities are really found in nature as such but merely that they are means of making accurate calculations of an abstract mental kind. (Leibniz [Reference Leibniz47] as translated by Loemker in [Reference Leibniz57, p. 438]; emphasis on solicitation in the original; emphasis on really found in nature and abstract mental kind added)

Over a decade later, des Bosses questioned Leibniz concerning the above passage from Specimen Dynamicum. Leibniz responded as follows concerning the fictionality of infinitesimals:

For I consider both [infinitely small and infinitely large magnitudes] as fictions of the mind, due to abbreviated ways of speaking, which are suitable for calculation, in the way that imaginary roots in algebra are.Footnote 46 (Leibniz as translated by Look and Rutherford in [Reference Leibniz53, p. 33]; emphasis added)

Arthur quotes this passage in [Reference Arthur, Nachtomy and Winegar5, p. 176] and concludes: “This is the syncategorematic infinitesimal described above” (ibid.).Footnote 47 Is it indeed? First, in this passage Leibniz refers to both infinitesimals and imaginary roots as compendia (abbreviations), undermining an Ishiguro-syncategorematic reading (see Section 3) since it is unavailable for imaginary roots.Footnote 48 Furthermore, des Bosses, in formulating his question on March 2, 1706, specifically raised the possibility of the syncategorematic infinite:

I would have conjectured that the infinite that you add can be confined to the syncategorematic; … (des Bosses as translated by Look and Rutherford in [Reference Leibniz61, p. 27])

In his answer 9 days later, on March 11, 1706, Leibniz says not a word about the syncategorematic infinite, and rather speaks of fictions of the mind as quoted above.

Levey reproduces a longer passage from the March 11, 1706 letter containing the one we quoted, and claims that it supports the syncategorematic reading [Reference Levey, Shapiro and Hellman64, p. 146]. However, such a claim overlooks the fact that Leibniz specifically ignored des Bosses’ question about the syncategorematic infinite, as noted above. Levey concludes his Section 2.1 on infinitesimals as follows:

They can be replaced by proofs given in Leibniz’s updated style of Archimedes if full rigor is wanted, and the mathematics in which they figure is not committed to the existence of ‘actual’ infinitesimals in nature for its justification. (op. cit., p. 148; emphasis added)

As Levey appears to acknowledge in his concluding sentence, it is in nature that there may be no infinitesimals; Leibniz viewed them as mentis fictiones. Levey’s stated conclusion is mainly in accord with our reading of Leibnizian infinitesimals. Meanwhile, the Ishiguro-syncategorematic hypothesis pursued elsewhere in Levey’s Section 2.1 remains unsupported.

5.2 Well-founded fictions in relation to rerum natura

The fictional nature of infinitesimals is a constant theme in Leibnizian thought. Thus, in a April 14, 1702 letter to Varignon, Leibniz wrote:

[L]es infinis et infiniment petits pourroient estre pris pour des fictions, semblables aux racines imaginaires, sans que cela dût faire tort à nostre calcul, ces fictions estant utiles et fondées en realité.Footnote 49 [Reference Leibniz50, p. 98]

In this passage, Leibniz asserts that interpreting the infinite and infinitely small as useful fictions would cause no harm to ‘our calculus’.Footnote 50 In a June 20, 1702 letter to Varignon, Leibniz wrote:

Entre nous je crois que Mons. de Fontenelle … en a voulu railler, lorsqu’il a dit qu’il vouloit faire des elemens metaphysiques de nostre calcul. Pour dire le vray, je ne suis pas trop persuadé moy même, qu’il faut considerer nos infinis et infiniment petits autrement que comme des choses ideales ou comme des fictions bien fondées.Footnote 51 [Reference Leibniz51, p. 110] (emphasis added)

In this case Leibniz adds a qualification: infinitesimals are well-founded fictions (‘fictions bien fondées’). It is difficult to see how fictions that are, according to Leibniz, well-founded could also be, as per RA, contradictory.Footnote 52 On the contrary, for Leibniz consistency is a requirement for a well-founded fiction and thus for mathematical existence. In this respect Leibniz is closer than many mathematicians of subsequent generations to Hilbert’s formalism (where existence depends on consistency alone). By ascribing to Leibniz the use of contradictory concepts, RA rule out an interpretation whereby Leibniz, like Hilbert, views conception of mathematical existence as consistency; see [Reference Katz and Sherry32] for details.

Leibniz expressed similar sentiments concerning ideal notions in a February 2, 1702 letter to Varignon:Footnote 53

D’où il s’ensuit, que si quelcun n’admet point des lignes infinies et infiniment petites à la rigueur metaphysique et comme des choses reelles, il peut s’en servir seurement comme des notions ideales qui abregent le raisonnement,Footnote 54 semblables à ce qu’on appelle racines imaginaires dans l’analyse commune (comme par exemple $\sqrt {-2}$ ), …Footnote 55 [Reference Leibniz49, p. 92] (emphasis added)

The idea of imagining infinitesimals also appears in a March 30, 1699 letter to Wallis, where Leibniz rejects Wallis’ position that infinitesimals are nothings:

[F]or the calculus it is useful to imagine Footnote 56 infinitely small quantities, or, as Nicolaus Mercator called them, infinitesimals, such that when at least the assignable ratio between them is sought, they precisely may not be taken to be nothings. (Leibniz as translated by Beeley in [Reference Beeley12, note 38]; emphasis added)

In the same letter, Leibniz makes a revealing comment concerning the status of inassignables:

Whether inassignable quantities are real or fictions, I will not argue for now; it is enough that they serve as a help for thinking, and that they always carry a proof with them, with only the style changed; and so I have noted, that if anyone should substitute incomparably or sufficiently small (quantities) for infinitely small ones, I do not object. (Leibniz to Wallis, March 30, 1699, GM [Reference Gerhardt25] IV, 63; translation ours)

Here Leibniz refuses to commit himself to either a realist or a fictionalist position. Beeley offers the following intriguing speculation:

This of course opens up the whole question of whether Leibniz really held that infinitesimals could exist in nature. On some occasions he does indeed seem to be denying their existence. But I think that we need to be careful here, because denial of the existence of infinitesimals is generally coupled with the argument that the success of the calculus does not depend on metaphysical discussions concerning reality. When he makes such claims, this seems to be no more than a get-out clause vis-à-vis opponents who seek to provide metaphysical arguments against his calculus. Seen within the context of Leibniz’ dynamics, particularly in respect of dead force (vis mortua) it is evident that he must be committed in some way to the existence of infinitesimals.Footnote 57 [Reference Beeley and Leibniz13, p. 42]

Our main arguments in the present text are independent of resolving Beeley’s ‘get-out clause’ hypothesis. On many occasions, Leibniz did reject infinitesimal creatures. Thus, in a June 20, 1702 letter to Varignon, Leibniz wrote:

Je croy qu’il n’y a point de creature au dessous de la quelle il n’y ait une infinité de creatures, cependant je ne crois point qu’il y en ait, ny même qu’il y en puisse avoir d’infiniment petites et c’est ce que je crois pouvoir demonstrer. Il est que les substances simples (c’est à dire qui ne sont pas des estres par aggregation) sont veritablement indivisibles, mais elles sont immaterielles, et ne sont que principes d’action. [Reference Leibniz51, p. 110]

In the same vein, in a March 11, 1706 letter to des Bosses, Leibniz wrote:

Yet you see that it should not be concluded from this that an infinitely small portion of matter (such as does not exist) must be assigned to any entelechy, even if we usually rush to such conclusions by a leap. (Leibniz as translated by Look and Rutherford in [Reference Leibniz53, p. 35])

5.3 Theory of knowledge: two types of impossibility

The terms “contradictory” and “impossible” have different meanings for Leibniz. In Leibnizian theory of knowledge, the fact that something is (1) not possible does not mean that it is (2) absolutely impossible or contradictory.

Leibniz introduces a related distinction on several occasions. Thus, in the Confessio Philosophi [Reference Leibniz38, p. 128], he refers to (1) as “impossible by accident” and contrasts it with (2) “absolute impossibility,” i.e., contradiction. He gives the examples of a species with an odd number of feet, and an immortal mindless creature, which are, according to him, harmoniae rerum adversa, i.e., “contrary to the harmony of things” (trans. Sleigh in [Reference Leibniz60, p. 57]), but not contradictory.

In his 1683 text Elementa nova matheseos universalis, Leibniz explains that some mathematical operations cannot be performed in actuality, but nonetheless one can exhibit “a construction in our characters” (in nostris characteribus [Reference Leibniz41, p. 520])—meaning that one can carry out a formal calculation, such as those with imaginary roots, regardless of whether the mathematical notions involved idealize anything in nature. Leibniz goes on to discuss in detail the cases of imaginary roots and infinitesimals. For convenience of reference, we labeled four passages [A], [B], [C], and [D]. Leibniz mentions infinitesimals in passage [C]:

[A] And some extractions of roots are such that roots are surd and they do not exist in natura rerum, and we call them imaginary, and the problem is impossible, as when our analysis shows that the requested point must be exhibited by the intersection of a specific circle and a specific straight line, in which case it may happen that this circle by no means reaches this line, and then the intersection is imaginary …

[B] There is a big difference between imaginary quantities, or those impossible by accident, and absolutely impossible ones, which involve a contradiction: e.g., when it is found that solving a problem requires that 3 be equal to 4, which is absurd.

[C] But imaginary quantities, or [quantities] impossible by accident, namely quantities that cannot be exhibited for lack of a sufficient condition, which is required for having an intersection, can be compared with infinite and infinitely small quantities, which are generated in the same way.…

[D] And it is true that calculus necessary leads to them, and people who are not sufficiently expert in such matters get entangled and think they have reached an absurdity [absurdum]. Experts know instead that this apparent impossibility [apparentem illam impossibilitatem] only means that a parallel line is traced instead of a straight line making the required angle, and this parallelism is the required angle, or quasi-angle.Footnote 58 [Reference Leibniz41, pp. 520–521]Footnote 59

Passages [B] and [C] indicate that (natural instantiations of) infinitesimals are only impossible by accident, or only apparently impossible. Therefore there are no grounds for attributing absolute impossibility or contradiction to them, or for lumping them with infinite wholes, as per RA (see Section 3.3). Infinite wholes are absolutely impossible because they are contrary to the part–whole principle (see Section 4.1), which is a necessary truth. Thus, in a 1678 letter to Elisabeth [Reference Leibniz40], Leibniz described the concept of “the number of all possible units”Footnote 60 as impossible [Reference Leibniz58, p. 238]. In his Historia et Origo [Reference Gerhardt24], he presents a derivation of the part–whole principle from the principle of identities and the definitions of whole and part:

[T]hat mighty axiom, ‘The whole is greater than its part’, could be proved by a syllogism of which the major term was a definition and the minor term an identity. (Leibniz as translated by Child in [Reference Child20, pp. 29–30])

RA seek to undercut infinitesimals on the grounds that their definition, in terms of violation of Euclid’s Definition V.4,Footnote 61 is only nominal, and claim the following:

Although this concept contains a contradiction, other subsidiary concepts contained in it may permit the derivation of true entailments. [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 406]

Does the concept of infinitesimal contain a contradiction as claimed by RA? In his 1686 comments that shed light on the Leibnizian theory of knowledge, Leibniz wrote merely that a nominal definition could harbor contradictions, not that it must do so:

Et tandis qu’on n’a qu’une definition nominale, on ne se sçauroit asseurer des consequences qu’on en tire; car si elle cachoit quelque contradiction ou impossibilité, on en pourroit tirer des conclusions opposées. [Reference Leibniz43, pp. 1568–1569]

With regard to both imaginaries and infinitesimals, Leibniz makes it clear in the 1683 passage cited above (paragraph [C]) that their natural instantiations are (at most) only conditionally or accidentally impossible, rather than contradictory. Esquisabel and Raffo Quintana examine the issue and reach the following conclusion:

[U]nlike the infinite number or the number of all numbers, for Leibniz infinitary concepts do not imply any contradiction, although they may imply paradoxical consequences. [Reference Esquisabel and Raffo Quintana22, p. 641]Footnote 62

If “the principle of non-contradiction [is] the principle of the minimal condition of intelligibility” [Reference Grosholz and Yakira28, p. 44] then one can easily perceive why infinitesimals, unlike infinite wholes, are ubiquitous in Leibniz’s mathematical oeuvre.

5.4 Infinitesimals, infinite wholes, and nominal definitions

To summarize, in a 1672/3 text Confessio Philosophi, Leibniz speaks of the distinction between accidental impossibility and absolute impossibility (equivalent to contradiction), and mentions two examples of accidental impossibility, specifying that they are contrary to the principle of the harmoniae rerum.

Furthermore, in a 1683 text Elementa nova matheseos universalis Leibniz mentions that imaginary roots do not exist in rerum natura, and contrasts imaginary quantities impossible by accident, on the one hand, and absolutely impossible entities involving a contradiction such as $3=4$ , on the other. Leibniz goes on to compare imaginary quantities (impossible by accident) to infinitely small quantities, and points out that people who are not sufficiently expert tend to confuse apparent impossibility with absurdity.

Finally, in a 1686 text Discours de Metaphysique Leibniz speaks of nominal definitions and warns that they might harbor contradictions (but not that they must necessarily do so). Even if the definition of an infinitesimal as violating Euclid’s Definition V.4 were nominal (as RA claim), it would follow at most that infinitesimals, possibly contrary to the principle of the harmoniae rerum, may not idealize anything in nature, a state of affairs that can be described as accidental impossibility. Meanwhile, infinite wholes are contrary to the part–whole principle (which Leibniz consistently takes to be a necessary truth), and therefore do involve an absurdity.

6 Conclusion

Bassler [Reference Bassler11], Arthur [Reference Arthur and De Risi6] and Rabouin–Arthur [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71] attempt to enlist Leibniz’s 1716 letter to Masson in support of an Ishiguro-syncategorematic reading of the Leibnizian calculus, claiming that its procedures are in keeping with the Archimedean axiom.Footnote 63 Rabouin and Arthur assimilate Leibnizian infinitesimals to infinite wholes and surmise that Leibniz viewed infinitesimals as contradictory. Such a reading rules out an interpretation whereby Leibniz viewed mathematical existence as consistency, as did Hilbert.

Contextualizing the Leibnizian comments on the calculus in the 1716 letter suggests a different reading. The letter is consistent with Leibniz’s position in 1695 [Reference Leibniz44, Reference Leibniz45] that infinitesimals violate Euclid’s Definition V.4 when compared to assignable quantities (hardly in keeping with the Archimedean axiom).Footnote 64 Like imaginary roots, infinitesimals are useful fictions that are at most accidental impossibilities that violate the principle of the harmony of things if they do not idealize anything in nature. Infinitesimals are therefore to be contrasted with infinite wholes, which are absolute impossibilities since they contradict the part–whole principle, a necessary truth in Leibnizian thought. Our conclusions are compatible with those of Esquisabel and Raffo Quintana, who similarly reject the contention by Rabouin and Arthur that Leibniz viewed infinitesimals as contradictory.

Leibniz wrote to Huygens as follows:

[Nieuwentijt] me fait une objection sur un point qui m’est commun avec Messieurs Fermat, Barrow, Newton et tous les autres, qui ont raisonné sur les grandeurs infiniment petites. [Reference Leibniz46]

Here Leibniz asserts the existence of a point in common between his reasoning with infinitesimals and that of his illustrious predecessors. To maintain the syncategorematic hypothesis, its proponents Arthur, Bassler, Levey, and Rabouin would face an unenviable alternative: either (1) claim that Leibniz was untruthful in his letter to Huygens, or (2) argue that, in Leibniz’s view, the infinitesimals of Fermat, Barrow, and Newton were similarly syncategorematic.

The 1716 letter to Masson provides no basis for doubting that Leibniz based his calculus on a special kind of small magnitudes that he viewed as mentis fictiones.

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Roger Ariew and Philip Beeley for helpful suggestions, to David Schaps for expert advice on Greek spelling and Latin usage, and to Stephan Meier-Oeser for providing access to the autograph manuscripts of the letter from Leibniz to Masson relied upon in note 6.

Footnotes

1 Translation: “But to fancy themselves that they could account for the nature of things by such Calculations, that is precisely where their error lies.”

2 Beeley mistakenly attributes the criticism to Bayle in [Reference Beeley and Leibniz13, p. 26].

3 The date appearing at the end of Toland’s text is in 1703, but there is internal evidence that the piece was touched up in 1714 at the earliest; see [Reference Lamarra36, Reference Woolhouse78].

4 Woolhouse and Francks [Reference Woolhouse and Francks79] date the letter August 21, 1716.

5 See Section 5.1 for the full quotation.

6 Gerhardt’s edition [Reference Leibniz54] uses the erroneous spelling $\xi \tilde {\omega } o\nu $ (twice) on page 624. In the autograph manuscripts of Leibniz, the word appears as $\zeta \tilde {\omega }o\nu $ , without the iota subscript. The translation by Ariew [Reference Leibniz58, p. 225] uses the spelling zoon.

7 The term substance is used here in the technical sense of a metaphysical substratum of physical beings. See further in note 8.

8 Early work by Leibniz on substance dating from 1668 aimed “to effect a reconciliation between Roman Catholics and Protestants. … These works are especially valuable for what they reveal about the motivations behind Leibniz’s first account of substance” [Reference Mercer, Sleigh and Jolley65, p. 68]. In a letter to des Bosses dated September 8, 1709, Leibniz distances himself from both transubstantiation and consubstantiation, and sketches a monad-based approach [Reference Leibniz61, p. 153].

9 Toland’s criticism of Leibniz being so widely off the mark has led Stuart Brown to speculate that Toland “mistakenly supposed that Leibniz was cast in the same philosophical mould as [Joseph] Raphson” [Reference Brown19, note 51], and copied over some criticisms targeting Raphson from another text of Toland’s. Raphson was an associate of Newton’s.

10 See the 1668–9 correspondence with Thomasius, Leibniz [Reference Leibniz55] A2.1 $^2$ . 16–44; cf. [Reference Mercer, Sleigh and Jolley65, p. 71].

11 Resistance, antitypy, solidity, the property of filling space, and impenetrability are synonyms, and refer to the impossibility, for a physical body, of being in the same space with another thing, as Leibniz explains a few lines later.

12 “Spatium est Ens primo-extensum, seu corpus mathematicum, quod scilicet nihil aliud continet quam tres dimensiones, estque locus ille universalis omnium rerum. Materia est ens secundo-extensum, seu quod praeter extensionem vel corpus mathematicum habet et corpus physicum, id est, resistentiam, $\acute{\alpha} \nu \tau \iota \tau \upsilon \pi \acute \iota \alpha \nu $ , crassitiem, spatii-repletivitatem, impenetrabilitatem.”

13 “Quantitatem quoque habet materia, sed interminatam, ut vocant Averroistae, seu indefinitam, dum enim continua est, in partes secta non est, ergo nec termini in ea actu dantur.”

14 “At in realibus, nempe corporibus, partes non sunt indefinitae (ut in spatio, re mentali), sed actu assignatae certo modo, prout natura divisiones et subdivisiones actu secundum motuum varietates instituit, et licet eae divisiones procedant in infinitum, non ideo tamen minus omnia resultant ex certis primis constitutivis seu unitatibus realibus, sed numero infinitis. Accurate autem loquendo materia non componitur ex unitatibus constitutivis, sed ex iis resultat.”

15 “Caeterum ut ab ideis Geometriae, ad realia Physicae transeam; statuo materiam actu fractam esse in partes quavis data minores, seu nullam esse partem, quae non actu in alias sit subdivisa diversos motus exercentes. Id postulat natura materiae et motus, et tota rerum compages, per physicas, mathematicas et metaphysicas rationes.”

16 “Memini Aristotelem quoque Contiguum a Continuo ita discernere, ut Continua sint quorum extrema unum sunt, Contingua quorum extrema simul sunt.” Cf. Aristotle Physics VI.1 231a 22–3.

17 “Et c’est la confusion de l’ideal et de l’actuel qui a tout embrouillé et fait le labyrinthe de compositione continui.”

18 An alternative reading of Leibnizian useful fictions as pure fictions was developed in [Reference Sherry and Katz73]. For more details see [Reference Bascelli, Błaszczyk, Kanovei, Katz, Katz, Schaps and Sherry10].

19 No punctuation mark occurs between ‘entity’ and ‘see’ in [Reference Rabouin and Jullien68, note 25].

20 This entry from Arthur’s glossary indicates that he is aware of the Leibnizian assignable/inassignable dichotomy; see the main text at note 33.

21 Cantor’s published proof that infinitesimals are contradictory suffers from a related circularity; see [Reference Ehrlich21].

22 As noted correctly by Ishiguro, “Leibniz did not think that there should be what we call the cardinality of the set of all things” [Reference Ishiguro30, p. 80].

23 Commentators who wish to lump infinite wholes with infinitesimals encounter an immediate difficulty: if their fates were bound together in Leibniz’s mind, why did he reject infinite wholes as contradictory already in 1672 but waited until 1676 (see note 35 for Arthur’s tight timeframe) to rule on infinitesimals?

24 Thus, in a rebuttal of Bernoulli’s argument for the existence of infinitesimals based on an analysis of a geometric series, Leibniz points out: “I will concede the existence of the infinite multitude, but this multitude is neither a number nor a coherent whole. It means nothing more than that there are more parts, which could be referred to by any number at all, just as there is a multitude … of all numbers; this multitude, however, is itself neither a number nor a coherent whole” (Leibniz as translated by Sierksma in [Reference Sierksma and Sierksma74, p. 447]).

25 Leibniz rejected both minima and maxima for continua in the following terms: “Scholium. We therefore hold that two things are excluded from the realm of intelligibles: minimum, and maximum; the indivisible, or what is entirely one, and everything; what lacks parts, and what cannot be part of another” (Leibniz as translated by Arthur in [Reference Arthur2, p. 13]). The rejection of maxima is the rejection of infinite wholes (e.g., unbounded lines). The rejection of their counterparts, minima, is the rejection of putative simplest constituents of the continuum, i.e., the rejection of a punctiform continuum (see Section 2.1). To Leibniz, points play only the role of endpoints of line segments. Thus the rejected counterparts of the contradictory infinite wholes are, not infinitesimals as per RA, but rather points viewed as the simplest constituents of a continuum.

26 See also note 52 on well-foundedness and contradictions.

27 RA conflate multitudes and quantities when they claim that “[Leibniz] held that the part–whole axiom is constitutive of quantity, so that the concept of an infinite quantity, such as an infinite number or an infinite whole, involves a contradiction” [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 406]. The part–whole axiom is constitutive of multitude but not of quantity. As we mentioned in note 24, Leibniz clearly understood the difference between infinite multitude and infinite quantity.

28 RA’s confusion of minima and infinitesimals was already noted in note 25.

29 Arthur has never given any evidence for his claim that Leibniz viewed the terms of an infinite series as an actual infinity (even distributively). Antognazza notes that Leibniz “is offering a mathematical analogy, as opposed to maintaining that the actual infinite (even if thought of syncategorematically) applies to mathematical, abstract entities, and to the ideal, mathematical continuum” [Reference Antognazza1, p. 9]. See Section 2.3 for further details.

30 For Leibniz on minds, see Section 5.1 and the main text at note 38.

31 For Leibniz on minds, see Section 5.1 and the main text at note 38.

32 “Although we may be content with the assignable quantities $(d)y$ , $(d)v$ , $(d)z$ , and $(d)x$ , since in this way we can perceive the whole fruit of our calculus, namely a construction using assignable quantities, still it is clear from this that we may, at least by feigning, substitute for them the unassignables $dx$ , $dy$ by way of fiction even in the case where they vanish, since $dy:dx$ can always be reduced to $(d)y:(d)x$ , a ratio between assignable or undoubtedly real quantities” (Leibniz as translated by RA in [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 439]).

33 The dichotomy is also mentioned in Arthur’s glossary of Leibnizian terms; see the main text at note 20.

34 Later Leibniz will use this example to illustrate the impossibility of infinita terminata in nature.

35 Thus, Arthur writes: “For some time, Leibniz appears to have hesitated over this interpretation, and as late as February 1676 he was still deliberating about whether the success of the hypothesis of infinities and the infinitely small in geometry spoke to their existence in physical reality too. But by April [1676], the syncategorematic interpretation is firmly in place” [Reference Arthur4, p. 559]. Here Arthur appears to acknowledge that Leibniz’s hesitation and deliberation concern “their existence [or otherwise] in physical reality”; the ease with which Arthur skips from denial of material existence to syncategorematics is surprising. Arthur’s dating clashes with Knobloch’s scenario placing the switch years earlier.

36 In the original Latin: “An autem hujusmodi quantitates ferat natura rerum Metaphysici est disquirere; Geometra sufficit, quid ex ipsis positis sequatur, demonstrare” [Reference Leibniz59, p. 98]. English translation: “Determining whether nature warrants quantities of this type is the business of the Metaphysician; for the Geometer it shall suffice to demonstrate what follows from their supposition.”

37 Arthur comments as follows on rerum natura in connection with Numeri infiniti: “In ‘Infinite Numbers’ of April 10th any entity such as a line smaller than any assignable, or the angle between two such lines, is firmly characterized as ‘fictitious’ (A VI, III, 498–99; LLC, 89). There are no such things in rerum natura, even though they express ‘real truths’” [Reference Arthur, Kulstad, Laerke and Snyder3, p. 28]. Arthur goes on to quote Leibniz as follows: “these fictitious entities are excellent abbreviations of propositions, and are for this reason extremely useful” (ibid.). Leibniz’s comment about infinitesimals being “excellent abbreviations” is readily appreciated by anyone with experience in teaching or research in infinitesimal analysis. Yet Arthur fails to consider the possibility that the absence of infinitesimals in rerum natura may not imply that they are placemarks for quantifier-equipped propositions. It takes some leap of Weierstrassian faith to see Leibniz’s comment on abbreviations as evidence for an Ishiguroan alternating quantifier reading of infinitesimals as logical fictions (see Section 3). Leibnizian analogies between infinitesimals and imaginaries similarly undercut Ishiguro’s reading; see note 48.

38 In the original Latin: “Erunt ergo in mente et caetera omnia: et in ea omnia jam fient, fieri quae posse negabam” [Reference Leibniz39, p. 499].

39 In the sense that a sufficiently short subarc at P will lie inside the rectilinear angle. See [Reference Thomason75] for a detailed discussion of the non-Archimedean nature of hornangles when compared to rectilinear angles.

40 From the viewpoint of modern geometry the angle between a pair of tangent curves is zero by definition, but Leibniz envisioned a more general notion of angle.

41 The term occurring in the original, point, seems to be a misprint.

42 See the quotation in note 64.

43 As explained in note 39.

44 See notes 37, 48, and 54.

45 Thus, analyzing the area under the hyperbola, Leibniz concludes: “By this argument it is concluded that the infinite is not a whole, but only a fiction, since otherwise the part would be equal to the whole” (A VII 3, 468; October 1674). Arthur [Reference Arthur4, p. 557] and Rabouin–Arthur [Reference Rabouin and Arthur71, p. 405] quote this passage but fail to account for the fact that Leibniz never refers to such entities as well-founded fictions. For more details see [Reference Katz, Kuhlemann, Sherry, Ugaglia and van Atten31].

46 In the original Latin: “Utrasque enim per modum loquendi compendiosum pro mentis fictionibus habeo, ad calculum aptis, quales etiam sunt radices imaginariae in Algebra” [Reference Leibniz53, p. 32]. Schubring quotes this sentence and claims that “Leibniz stressed that for himself the infinitely small quantities were not really existing mathematical quantities, but only fictions that had their uses in the course of calculus” [Reference Schubring72, p. 171] (emphasis in the original). It is correct that Leibniz referred to infinitesimals as fictions, but Schubring’s claim that to Leibniz they “were not really existing mathematical quantities” is unsupported and at best ambiguous. For a detailed critique of Schubring’s book see [Reference Błaszczyk, Kanovei, Katz and Sherry14].

47 Similar claims concerning this Leibnizian passage appeared 5 years earlier in [Reference Arthur4, p. 555].

48 Since Leibniz describes both as abbreviations, the absence of any plausible alternating quantifier account of imaginary roots in terms of more ordinary quantities suggests that it was not Leibniz’s intention in the case of infinitesimals, either. A similar comparison occurs in a February 2, 1702 letter to Varignon; see the main text at note 54.

49 Translation: “Infinities and the infinitely small could be taken for fictions, similar to imaginary roots, without it causing harm to our calculus, these fictions being useful and founded in reality.”

50 Inexplicably, Schubring’s rendition attaches the opposite meaning to the passage: “Infinities and infinitely small quantities could be taken as fictions, similar to imaginary roots, except that it would make our calculations wrong, these fictions being useful and based in reality” (Leibniz as rendered by Schubring in [Reference Schubring72, p. 171]; emphasis added). Only Schubring’s rendition makes the calculations wrong.

51 Translation: “Between us, I believe that Mr. Fontenelle … was joking when he said that he wished to develop metaphysical elements of our calculus. To tell the truth, I am not myself persuaded that it is necessary to consider our infinities and the infinitely small as something other than ideal things or well-founded fictions.”

52 RA attempt to sidestep the difficulty by claiming that contradictory infinitesimals can be used “under certain conditions” but don’t specify the latter; see the main text at note 26. In his letter to des Bosses dated March 11, 1706, Leibniz describes the rainbow as a well-founded phenomenon [Reference Leibniz53, p. 35]. Since Leibniz describes infinitesimals using the same expression “well-founded,” the question arises whether RA would be prepared to claim that to Leibniz, rainbows similarly were contradictory notions that can be used under certain unspecified conditions. Occasionally, Leibniz refers to infinite wholes as “fictions,” as in a 1674 text, but he never refers to them as well-founded fictions; see note 45.

53 RA’s interpretation of the letter is analyzed in Section 3.4.

54 “Notions ideales qui abregent le raisonnement” is Leibniz’s French equivalent of the Latin compendia; see note 48. In this passage also, infinitesimals and imaginaries are both described as abbreviations that facilitate reasoning.

55 Loemker’s translation: “It follows from this that even if someone refuses to admit infinite and infinitesimal lines in a rigorous metaphysical sense and as real things, he can still use them with confidence as ideal concepts which shorten his reasoning, similar to what we call imaginary roots in the ordinary algebra, for example, $\sqrt {-2}$ ” [Reference Leibniz57, p. 543].

56 Possibly: to feign; in the original Latin: fingere. See also the main text at note 38.

57 For related comments on dead force by Garber see Section 2.2.

58 “Et quaedam extractiones tales sunt, ut radices illae surdae nec in natura rerum extent, tunc dicuntur imaginariae, et problema est impossibile, ut cum analysis ostendit punctum quaesitum debere exhiberi per intersectionem certi circuli et certae rectae, ubi fieri potest ut ille circulus ad illam rectam nullo modo perveniat, et tunc intersectio erit imaginaria … Multum autem interest inter quantitates imaginarias, seu impossibiles per accidens, et impossibiles absolute quae involvunt contradictionem, ut cum invenitur ad problema solvendum opus esse, ut fit 3 aequ. 4 quod est absurdum. Imaginariae vero seu per accidens impossibiles, quae scilicet non possunt exhiberi ob defectum sufficientis constitutionis ad intersectionem necessariae, possunt comparari cum Quantitatibus infinitis et infinite parvis, quae eodem modo oriuntur. … quod adeo verum est ut saepe calculus ad eas necessario ducat, ubi harum rerum nondum satis periti mire torquentur et in absurdum se incidisse putant. Intelligentes vero sciunt apparentem illam impossibilitatem tantum significare, ut loco rectae angulum quaesitum facientis ducatur parallela; hunc parallelismum esse angulum illum seu quasi angulum quaesitum.”

59 This passage was translated into French by Rabouin in [Reference Leibniz62, pp. 107–109].

60 Here “number” refers to cardinality as per Ishiguro; see note 22.

61 See note 64.

62 Esquisabel and Raffo Quintana clarify: “[W]e disagree with the reasons [Rabouin and Arthur] gave for the Leibnizian rejection of the existence of infinitesimals, and in our opinion the texts they refer to in order to support their interpretation are not convincing. Since we argue that Leibniz did not consider the concept of infinitesimal as self-contradictory, we try to provide an alternative conception of impossibility” [Reference Esquisabel and Raffo Quintana22, p. 620].

63 Meanwhile, Rabouin solo [Reference Rabouin, Goethe, Beeley and Rabouin69] expressed a more cautious position with regard to the 1716 letter; see Section 3.4, item 3.

64 Thus, Breger writes: “In a letter to L’Hôpital of 1695, Leibniz gives an explicit definition of incomparable magnitudes: two magnitudes are called incomparable if the one cannot exceed the other by means of multiplication with an arbitrary (finite) number, and he expressly points to Definition 5 of the fifth book of Euclid” [Reference Breger and Li18, pp. 73–74].

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Antognazza, M. (2015). The hypercategorematic infinite. The Leibniz Review, 25, 530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, R., translator. (2001). G. W. Leibniz. The Labyrinth of the Continuum. Writings on the Continuum Problem, 1672–1686. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Arthur, R. (2009). Actual infinitesimals in Leibniz’s early thought. In Kulstad, M., Laerke, M., and Snyder, D, editors. The Philosophy of the Young Leibniz. Studia Leibnitiana Sonderhefte, Vol. 35. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner, pp. 1128.Google Scholar
Arthur, R. (2013). Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 67(5), 553593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, R. (2018). Leibniz’s syncategorematic actual infinite. In Nachtomy, O., & Winegar, R., editors. Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer, pp. 155179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, R. (2019). Leibniz in Cantor’s paradise. In De Risi, V., editor. Leibniz and the Structure of Sciences. Modern Perspectives on the History of Logic, Mathematics, Epistemology. Boston Studies in Philosophy and History of Science, Cham: Springer, pp. 71109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arthur, R. (2019). Review of Varieties of Continua—From Regions to Points and Back by Hellman and Shapiro [29]. Philosophia Mathematica, 27(1), 148152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bair, J., Błaszczyk, P., Ely, R., Henry, V., Kanovei, V., Katz, K., Katz, M., Kutateladze, S., McGaffey, T., Reeder, P., Schaps, D., Sherry, D., & Shnider, S. (2017). Interpreting the infinitesimal mathematics of Leibniz and Euler. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 195238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bair, J., Błaszczyk, P., Ely, R., Katz, M., & Kuhlemann, K. (2021). Procedures of Leibnizian infinitesimal calculus: An account in three modern frameworks. British Journal for the History of Mathematics, 36(3), 170209 https://doi. org/10.1080/26375451.2020.1851120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bascelli, T., Błaszczyk, P., Kanovei, V., Katz, K., Katz, M., Schaps, D., & Sherry, D. (2016). Leibniz versus Ishiguro: Closing a quarter century of syncategoremania. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 6(1), 117147.Google Scholar
Bassler, O. (1998). Leibniz on the indefinite as infinite. The Review of Metaphysics, 51(4), 849874.Google Scholar
Beeley, P. (2008). Infinity, infinitesimals, and the reform of Cavalieri: John Wallis and his critics. In Goldenbaum–Jesseph [27], pp. 31–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beeley, P. (2015). Leibniz, philosopher mathematician and mathematical philosopher. In Leibniz, G. W., editor. Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy. Archimedes, Vol. 41. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 2348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Błaszczyk, P., Kanovei, V., Katz, M., & Sherry, D. (2017). Controversies in the foundations of analysis: Comments on Schubring’s conflicts. Foundations of Science, 22(1), 125140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bos, H. (1974). Differentials, higher-order differentials and the derivative in the Leibnizian calculus. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 14, 190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosinelli, F. (1991). Über Leibniz’ Unendlichkeitstheorie. Studia Leibnitiana, 23(2), 151169.Google Scholar
Breger, H. (2016). Das Kontinuum bei Leibniz. In Li, W., editor. Kontinuum, Analysis, InformalesBeiträge Zur Mathemathik Und Philosophie von Leibniz. Berlin–Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 115126.Google Scholar
Breger, H. (2017). On the grain of sand and heaven’s infinity. In Li, W., editor. ‘Für Unser Glück Oder das Glück Anderer’ Vorträge Des X. Intemationalen Leibniz-Kongresses Hannover, 18–23 Juli 2016, Vol. VI. Hildesheim–Zurich–New York: Georg Olms, pp. 6479. In collaboration with Ute Beckmann, Sven Erdner, Esther-Maria Errulat, Jürgen Herbst, Helena Iwasinski und Simona Noreik.Google Scholar
Brown, S. (1999). Two papers by John Toland. I Castelli di Yale, IV(4), 5579.Google Scholar
Child, J., editor. (1920). The Early Mathematical Manuscripts of Leibniz. Chicago–London: The Open Court Publishing. Translated from the Latin texts published by Carl Immanuel Gerhardt with critical and historical notes by J. M. Child. Reprinted by Dover in 2005.Google Scholar
Ehrlich, P. (2006). The rise of non-Archimedean mathematics and the roots of a misconception. I. The emergence of non-Archimedean systems of magnitudes. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 60(1), 1121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esquisabel, O., & Raffo Quintana, F. (2021). Fiction, possibility and impossibility: Three kinds of mathematical fictions in Leibniz’s work. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 75(6), 613647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, D. (2008). Dead force, infinitesimals, and the mathematicization of nature. In Goldenbaum–Jesseph [27], pp. 281–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerhardt, C., editor. (1846). Historia et Origo Calculi Differentialis a G. G. Leibnitio Conscripta. Hannover: Hahn. Translated in Child [20].Google Scholar
Gerhardt, C., editor. (1849–63). Leibnizens mathematische Schriften. Berlin: Asher and Halle: H. W. Schmidt (cited as [GM]).Google Scholar
Gerhardt, C., editor. (1875–90). Die Philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Berlin: Weidmann (cited as [GP]).Google Scholar
Goldenbaum, U., & Jesseph, D., editors. (2008). Infinitesimal Differences. Controversies Between Leibniz and His Contemporaries. Berlin–New York: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grosholz, E., & Yakira, E. (1998). Leibniz’s Science of the Rational. Studia Leibnitiana Sonderheft, Vol. 26. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.Google Scholar
Hellman, G., & Shapiro, S. (2018). Varieties of Continua. From Regions to Points and Back. Chapter 3 with Øystein Linnebo. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ishiguro, H. (1990). Leibniz’s Philosophy of Logic and Language (second edition). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Katz, M., Kuhlemann, K., Sherry, D., Ugaglia, M., & van Atten, M. (2022). Two-track depictions of Leibniz’s fictions. The Mathematical Intelligencer. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-021-10140-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, M., & Sherry, D. (2013). Leibniz’s infinitesimals: Their fictionality, their modern implementations, and their foes from Berkeley to Russell and beyond. Erkenntnis, 78(3), 571625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobloch, E. (1990). L’infini dans les mathématiques de Leibniz. In L’infinito in Leibniz, Problemi e Terminologia. Roma: Edizioni dell’ Ateneo, pp. 3351. Simposio Internazionale Roma, 6–8 Novembre 1986, a Cura di Antonio Lamarra.Google Scholar
Knobloch, E. (1994). The infinite in Leibniz’s mathematics—The historiographical method of comprehension in context. In Gavroglu, K., Christianidis, J., & Nicolaidis, E., editors. Trends in the Historiography of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 265278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobloch, E. (1999). Galileo and Leibniz: Different approaches to infinity. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 54(2), 8799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lamarra, A. (1990). An anonymous criticism from Berlin to Leibniz’s philosophy: John Toland against mathematical abstractions. Studia Leibnitiana, 16, 89102.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1669). Letter to Thomasius, April 20–30, 1669. In Leibniz [55] (A2.12. 23–38).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1672/3. Confessio Philosophi. In Leibniz [55] (A.VI. 3. 115–149).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1676). Numeri Infiniti. In Leibniz [55] (A.VI. 3. 496–504).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1678). Letter to Elisabeth. A.2.12. 659–666. Translated in [58].Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1683). Elementa nova matheseos universalis. In Leibniz [55] (A.VI. 4A. 513–524).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1686). Meditatio nova de natura anguli contactus et osculi, horumque usu in practica mathesi ad figuras faciliores succedaneas difficilioribus substituendas. Act. Erudit. Lips. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. VII. Berlin: Asher and Halle: H. W. Schmidt, pp. 326329. English translation available from: http://www.17centurymaths.com/contents/Leibniz/ae4.pdf.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1686). Discours de Metaphysique. In Leibniz [55] (A.VI. 4B2. 1529–1589).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1695). Letter to l’Hospital, June 14/24, 1695, in Gerhardt [25], Vol. I, pp. 287–289.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1695). Responsio ad nonnullas difficultates a Dn. Bernardo Niewentiit circa methodum differentialem seu infinitesimalem motas. Act. Erudit. Lips. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. V, pp. 320–328. A French translation by Parmentier is in [56], pp. 316–334].Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1695). Letter to Huygens, July 1, 1695. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. II, p. 205 and Briefwechsel, p. 757. Available from: https://dbnl.nl/tekst/ huyg003oeuv10_01/huyg003oeuv10_01_0239.php.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1695). Specimen dynamicum, pro admirandis naturae legibus circa corporum vires et mutuas actiones detegendis, et ad suas causas revocandis. Acta Eruditorum. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. VI, pp. 234–254. Translated in Loemker [57], pp. 435–444 (Part I).Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1701). Cum Prodiisset… mss Cum prodiisset atque increbuisset Analysis mea infinitesimalis…. In Gerhardt [30], pp. 39–50. Available from: http://books.google.co.il/books?id=UOM3AAAAMAAJ.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1702). Letter to Varignon, February 2, 1702. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. IV, pp. 91–95.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1702). Letter to Varignon, April 14, 1702. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. IV, pp. 97–99.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1702). Letter to Varignon, June 20, 1702. In Gerhardt [25], Vol. IV, pp. 106–110.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1704). Letter to de Volder, June 30, 1704. In Gerhardt [26], Vol. II, pp. 267–272.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1706). Letter to Des Bosses, March 11, 1706. In Gerhardt [26], Vol. II, pp. 304–308. Translated in Look and Rutherford’s Leibniz [61], pp. 30–39.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1716). Letter to Samuel Masson. In Gerhardt [26], Vol. VI, pp. 624–629. Translated in Ariew–Garber’s Leibniz [58], pp. 225–230.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1923). Sämtliche Schriften Und Briefe. Darmstadt–Leipzig–Berlin: Akademie (cited as A. series, volume, page number). Available from: https://leibnizedition.de.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1989). La Naissance du Calcul différentiel. 26 Articles Des Acta Eruditorum. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. Translated from the Latin and with an introduction and notes by Marc Parmentier. With a preface by Michel Serres. Mathesis. Available from: https://books.google.co.il/books?id=lfEy-OzaWkQC.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1989). Philosophical Papers and Letters (second edition). Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 2. Dordrecht–Boston–London: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Translated and edited by Leroy E. Loemker.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (1989). Philosophical Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett. Translated and edited by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber. Available from: https://books.google.co.il/books?id=1xEeAt6FUl8C.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (2004). Quadrature arithmétique du cercle, de l’ellipse et de l’hyperbole. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. Translated and edited by Marc Parmentier/Latin text by Eberhard Knobloch (editor). Available from: https://books.google.co.il/books?id=fNTUULXHmQ0C.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (2004). Confessio Philosophi: Papers Concerning the Problem of Evil, 1671–1678 (The Yale Leibniz Series), by G. W. Leibniz (author) and Robert C. Sleigh Jr. (translator). Available from: https://books. google.co.il/books?id=Jj3Z0dHp6_MC.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (2007). The Leibniz–Des Bosses Correspondence. New Haven: Yale University Press. Translated, edited, and with an Introduction by Brandon C. Look and Donald Rutherford.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. (2018). Mathesis universalis. Écrits sur la mathématique universelle. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. Translated from the Latin and with an introduction and notes by David Rabouin. Mathesis.Google Scholar
Levey, S. (1998). Leibniz on mathematics and the actually infinite division of matter. The Philosophical Review, 107(1), 4996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levey, S. (2021). The continuum, the infinitely small, and the law of continuity in Leibniz. In Shapiro, S., & Hellman, G., editors. The History of Continua: Philosophical and Mathematical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 123157.Google Scholar
Mercer, C., & Sleigh, R. (1994). Metaphysics: The early period to the Discourse on Metaphysics . In Jolley, N., editor. Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 67123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, J. (1982). Infinity and continuity. In Kretzmann, N., Kenny, A., Pinborg, J., & Stump, E., editors. The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy: From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 564592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabouin, D. (2013). “Analytica Generalissima Humanorum Cognitionum”. Some reflections on the relationship between logical and mathematical analysis in Leibniz. Studia Leibnitiana, 45(1), 109130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabouin, D. (2015). Leibniz’s rigorous foundations of the method of indivisibles or how to reason with impossible notions. In Jullien, V., editor. Seventeenth-Century Indivisibles Revisited. Science Networks. Historical Studies, Vol. 49. Basel: Birkhäuser, pp. 347364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabouin, D. (2015). The difficulty of being simple: On some interactions between mathematics and philosophy in Leibniz’s analysis of notions. In Goethe, N., Beeley, P., & Rabouin, D., editors. G. W. Leibniz, Interrelations Between Mathematics and Philosophy, Archimedes, Vol. 41, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 4972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabouin, D. (2021). Can one be a fictionalist and a platonist at the same time? Lessons from Leibniz.Google Scholar
Rabouin, D., & Arthur, R. (2020). Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals II: Their existence, their use and their role in the justification of the differential calculus. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 74, 401443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schubring, G. (2005). Conflicts Between Generalization, Rigor, and Intuition. Number Concepts Underlying the Development of Analysis in 17–19th Century France and Germany. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sherry, D., & Katz, M. (2012). Infinitesimals, imaginaries, ideals, and fictions. Studia Leibnitiana, 44(2), 166192. Available from: http://www. jstor.org/stable/43695539 (Article was published in 2014 even though the journal issue lists the year as 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sierksma, G., & Sierksma, W. (1999). The great leap to the infinitely small. Johann Bernoulli: Mathematician and philosopher. Annals of Science, 56(4), 433449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, S. (1982). Euclidean infinitesimals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 168185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toland, J. (1716). Remarques Critiques sur le Systême de Mr. Leibnitz de l’Harmonie préétablie; où l’on recherche, en passant, Pourquoi les Systêmes Metaphysiques Des Mathematiciens Ont Moins de clarté Que Ceux Des Autres: écrites Par Ordre de Sa Majesté la feuë Reine de Prusse. Histoire Critique de la Republique Des Lettres, Tome XI, pp. 115–133 (published anonymously).Google Scholar
Ugaglia, M. (2022). Possibility vs iterativity: Leibniz and Aristotle on the infinite. In Ademollo, F., Amerini, F., & De Risi, V., editors. Thinking and Calculating. Essays on Logic, Its History and Its Applications in Honor of Massimo Mugnai. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Woolhouse, R. (1998). John Toland and ‘Remarques critiques sur le Systême de Monsr. Leibnitz de l’Harmonie préétablie’. The Leibniz Review, 8, 8087.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woolhouse, R., & Francks, R., editors. (1997). Leibniz’s ‘New System’ and Associated Contemporary Texts. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar