Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T15:41:21.687Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The neutral theory of conceptual complexity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2023

Rose Novick*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Washington, Seattle, WA, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Philosophical studies of complex scientific concepts are predominantly “adaptationist,” arguing that conceptual complexity serves important purposes. This is a historical artifact. Having had to defend their views against a monist presumption favoring simpler concepts, pluralists and patchwork theorists felt compelled to show that complexity can be beneficial. This neglects an alternative possibility: Conceptual complexity is largely neutral, persisting simply because it does little harm. This article defends the neutral theory of conceptual complexity in two forms: (a) as a plausible theory in its own right and (b) as a useful foil for adaptationist arguments.

Type
Contributed Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. The onion test

Consider the onion. Not merely the edible bulb, but the entire plant: Allium cepa. The onion possesses a great deal of DNA: Its haploid genome size is 15.9 gb (Ricroch et al. Reference Ricroch, Yockteng, Brown and Nadot2005). Humans, by contrast, have a piddling 3.1 gb haploid genome size (Genome Reference Consortium 2022)—roughly one-fifth as much as A. cepa. This disparity motivates Ryan Gregory’s onion test (Palazzo and Gregory Reference Palazzo and Ryan Gregory2014). The test is simple: Those who deny the existence of nonfunctional, “junk” DNA (e.g., Pennisi Reference Pennisi2012) must explain what, exactly, the onion is doing (and the human is not) that requires five times as much of the stuff. Failing this, we should acknowledge that a great deal of DNA is—from the host organism’s perspective (cf. Doolittle and Sapienza Reference Ford and Sapienza1980)—junk, in onions and humans alike.

Recent work highlights the complexity of important scientific concepts (Brigandt Reference Brigandt2003a, Reference Brigandt2003b; Jamniczky Reference Jamniczky2005; Griffiths and Stotz Reference Griffiths and Stotz2013; Bursten Reference Bursten2018; Haueis Reference Haueis2018, Reference Haueis2021a; Novick Reference Novick2018). Some regard conceptual complexity as a problem to be resolved by conceptual fragmentation (Ereshefsky Reference Ereshefsky1992, Reference Ereshefsky2010; Machery Reference Machery2009; Taylor and Vickers Reference Taylor and Vickers2017); others defend it as valuable for scientific reasoning and communication (Wilson Reference Wilson2006, Reference Wilson2018; Neto Reference Neto2020; De Benedetto Reference Benedetto2021; Haueis Reference Haueis2021b). But, whether friend or foe to conceptual complexity, all share a basic “adaptationist” presupposition: Conceptual complexity should be tolerated, if at all, only if it serves some valuable function. The disagreement largely concerns whether or not it does.

Complex scientific concepts may, however, be like onions: bloated with junk that neither serves much of a purpose nor does much harm. Just as much of molecular evolution is neutral (Kimura Reference Kimura1983) or nearly neutral (Ohta Reference Ohta1992), the same may be true of conceptual complexity: It may arise independent of its value and it may (justifiably) persist simply because getting rid of it is more trouble than it’s worth. Call this the neutral theory of conceptual complexity. This article defends that theory.

2. Monist hangover

That ordinary language concepts are messy is uncontroversial. That the same is true of core scientific concepts, as they appear in practice, is foundational to philosophy of science: It justifies the practice of explication, both historically (Carnap Reference Carnap1962) and presently (Justus Reference Justus2012). In speaking of conceptual “complexity,” I mean to include a range of phenomena, including vagueness, polysemy, imprecision, and anything else that prevents a concept from admitting of a single, relatively simple definition that lays down definite criteria of application. I shall refer to all views that favor replacing complex concepts with one or more simpler, more definite, disambiguated concepts as “monist.” In this sense, self-styled eliminative pluralists are a type of monist (cf. Ereshefsky Reference Ereshefsky1992, 688).

Monists can point to several advantages of such conceptual clean-up work. Carnap’s (Reference Carnap1962, ch. 1) classic defense of explication identifies two: (a) bringing the concept into a well-connected conceptual system and (b) allowing for the statement of (a greater number of) universal laws.

Explication also allows one to disentangle distinct but related uses of the same term. Wherever such uses coexist, there is risk of conflation. For instance, Ereshefsky (Reference Ereshefsky1992, 680) argues that

The term “species” is superfluous beyond the reference to a segmentation criterion; and when the term is used alone it leads to confusion. The term “species”… should be replaced by terms that more accurately describe the different types of lineages that biologists refer to as “species.”

Likewise, Machery (Reference Machery2009, 220) argues that

The notion of concept ought to be eliminated from the theoretical vocabulary of psychology because it might prevent psychologists from correctly characterizing the nature of the knowledge in long-term memory and its use in cognitive processes.

Carnap, Ereshefsky, and Machery are all alike concerned that inexact and polysemous concepts hinder clear communication and fruitful theoretical development.

Pluralists (e.g., Brigandt Reference Brigandt2003b; Jamniczky Reference Jamniczky2005; Currie Reference Currie2016; Neto Reference Neto2019) and patchwork theorists (e.g., Wilson Reference Wilson2006; De Benedetto Reference Benedetto2021; Haueis Reference Haueis2021b) show greater appreciation for messiness. This appreciation, however, rests on the belief that there is greater order within the mess than meets the eye. The gambit is that messiness and polysemy can be functional in ways that monists have failed to appreciate.

The proposed functions of complexity are various. Jamniczky (Reference Jamniczky2005, 694; cf. Brigandt Reference Brigandt2010) views the plurality of “homology” concepts as an array of “investigative tools” for the study of biological similarity; the messiness allows each discipline to use the specific tool best suited to its purposes. Neto (Reference Neto2020, 57) argues that the imprecision of “lineage” “helps biologists integrate theoretical principles and methodologies into different areas of biology.” Novick and Doolittle (Reference Novick and Ford Doolittle2021, 75, 72) contend that the patchwork structure of “species” facilitates “the transfer of reasoning patterns” developed for macrobes to the study of microbes (and vice versa), and so helps “manage inquiry into processes of speciation.”

This emphasis on the functionality of complexity is meant as a defense against monist critiques. Neto (Reference Neto2020, 57–58), for instance, writes:

Imprecision typically leads to miscommunication, reasoning errors, and similar problems in science. For these reasons, imprecise concepts seem to be obstacles to scientific knowledge, and thus scientists should avoid them.

There should thus be a prima facie presumption against tolerating imprecision. Neto’s defends the imprecision of “lineage” on the grounds that the ways it facilitates important forms of integration is sufficient to overcome this presumption. Novick and Doolittle (Reference Novick and Ford Doolittle2021, Section 7) likewise take the transfer of reasoning patterns between patches of “species” to impose a cost on eliminativist views.

Examples might be multiplied, but the point is clear: Monists and pluralists share the adaptationist presumption that complexity is prima facie undesirable, that it should be tolerated only if it can be shown to serve some valuable function. This, I suggest, is a historical artifact, a hangover from the period of monist dominance, a side effect of having had to make the case for complexity against a backdrop of suspicion.

This monist hangover has led to the neglect of the view that conceptual complexity is predominantly not problematic, not functional, but rather benign. Or, to continue the analogy with evolutionary theory, that conceptual complexity is by and large neutral.

3. Conceptual adaptationism: A critique

The adaptationist presupposition, shared by monists and critics alike, might seem unobjectionable. Imprecision and polysemy inherently create at least the possibility of confusion. This provides prima facie reason to distrust them. However, uncritical acceptance of this presupposition disposes us to accept weak arguments for the functional value of conceptual complexity, much as Gould and Lewontin (Reference Gould and Lewontin1979) worried that defaulting to evolutionary adaptationism led to the too easy acceptance of particular adaptationist hypotheses.

Before defending the neutral theory directly, therefore, I will raise general concerns about arguments that purport to show that conceptual complexity is functional. Such arguments may concern either or both the origin and the present value of conceptual complexity. About the present value of some instance of conceptual complexity, they claim, first, that this complexity serves some function and, second, that serving that function provides a net benefit. One may also go further and claim, third, that this complexity arose for the sake of serving that function. Accepting the first two claims while rejecting the third leaves the present function an exaptation (Gould and Vrba Reference Gould and Vrba1982).

Adaptationist arguments defending conceptual complexity generally successfully establish only the first claim. They fail to successfully establish the second claim because they are selective. They fail to successfully establish the third claim because they are insufficient to eliminate neutralist interpretations.

Arguments defending the present value of conceptual complexity tend to be selective. They do not provide anything like a global cost-benefit analysis of the trade-offs involved in managing complex concepts. Rather, they focus on establishing that conceptual complexity serves some particular function (first claim). Even if the case for functionality is compelling, however, such an argument will not show that it is adaptive on the whole because it will not show that the benefits of serving that function outweigh the costs imposed by complexity.

Consider Novick and Doolittle’s (Reference Novick and Ford Doolittle2021) arguments concerning “species.” Their target is Ereshefsky’s view that different species concepts—because they pick out different biological properties—are distinct concepts. Granting Ereshefsky’s (Reference Ereshefsky1992, Reference Ereshefsky2010) claims about the relationship between species concepts and real-world properties, they reject the inference to conceptual distinctness.

Instead, they argue, the species concept has a patchwork structure (Wilson Reference Wilson2006; Haueis Reference Haueis2021b) and that this structure allows it to serve the function of managing inquiry into speciation (clustering) processes. Because evolutionary processes work differently in different domains of life (Novick and Doolittle Reference Novick and Ford Doolittle2019), the resulting clusters can vary: “Species” in macrobes need not be the same kind of cluster as “species” in microbes. However, reasoning strategies concerning the role of gene flow in macrobes have been successfully applied to microbes, and reasoning strategies about species pangenomes developed in studies of microbes have been successfully applied to macrobes. Thus, even though “species” does not display a neat one-predicate-meets-one-property alignment (Wilson Reference Wilson1982), it facilitates transfer of reasoning patterns between domains, and so helps manage inquiry into speciation.

Suppose that Novick and Doolittle are correct that “species” serves this function. This is still insufficient to establish that the benefits of serving this function outweigh complexity’s costs, for two reasons. First, they do not consider the direct costs of complexity. Referring to both macrobial and microbial clusters as “species,” for instance, risks encouraging meaningless comparisons (e.g., “are there more macrobial or microbial species in the world?”). How we use species concepts also matters for conservation purposes (Frankham et al. Reference Frankham, Ballou, Dudash, Eldridge, Fenster, Lacy, Mendelson, Porton, Ralls and Ryder2012)—this is not considered at all. Without considering these costs, Novick and Doolittle fail to provide a compelling defense of the overall value of the concept’s complexity.

Second, they do not consider whether the complexity serves this function comparatively well. It is one thing to show that the complexity of “species” facilitates transfer of reasoning patterns between different regions of inquiry into speciation. It is another to show that this function could not be served equally well or better using multiple simpler concepts. In the case of “species,” some of the transfer of reasoning patterns between domains does occur in the course of asking questions about the extent to which macrobial and microbial species are similar (Bobay and Ochman Reference Bobay and Ochman2017). However, what is crucial to this transfer is that similar reasoning strategies work in both domains. This does not require that we regard both macrobial and microbial clusters as “species.”

These weaknesses are not limited to Novick and Doolittle. A global assessment of the value of using any given complex concept requires considering and weighting a wide range of factors—no mean task. Note that eliminativists and other proponents of fragmentation do not escape this charge: Emphasizing the potential for confusion—even pointing to actual confusion—is insufficient to establish that complexity is harmful overall. While much valuable work has been done by friends and foes alike, establishing the overall value of any given instance of complexity is more difficult than either side has appreciated.

Arguments about the value of conceptual complexity are also generally insufficient to support adaptationist accounts of the origin of that value over neutralist alternatives. Even if it is established that a complex concept serves some function, it is rarely satisfactorily demonstrated that the function could not be served with multiple simpler concepts. Further, it is rarely shown that the complexity exists for the sake of serving the function, in the sense that serving the function plays a role in its origin or even its maintenance.

There is a difference between conceptual complexity serving some function and its existing for the sake of serving that function. Where functional roles for conceptual complexity exist (regardless of whether or not they outweigh complexity’s costs), they may be exaptations at best. On this view, conceptual complexity may be latently present for nonfunctional reasons and may be called on to serve some function simply because it is available, not because it is especially well suited for that purpose. On this view, reasoning transfer about speciation processes occurs under the aegis of a complex species concept merely because biologists happen to refer to both macrobial and microbial clusters as “species.” This alternative is compatible with Novick and Doolittle’s arguments showing that “species” plays a role in facilitating this transfer. As with the worry about selectivity, this concern is general. While adaptationist explanations of the origin of conceptual complexity are not essential to taking an adaptationist view of the present value of complexity, rejecting such claims will be an important aspect of the neutral theory.

In raising these critiques, my aim has been neither to show that all arguments for the functional value of conceptual complexity fail, nor to argue that conceptual complexity is never functional. Rather, I have sought to illustrate the difficulty of assessing the functional value of conceptual complexity at all. That this difficulty has hitherto been insufficiently appreciated is at least partially due to the general neglect of the neutralist alternative, for it is precisely this alternative that throws the relevant standards into sharp relief.

4. The neutral theory of conceptual complexity

The neutral theory of conceptual complexity has both descriptive and normative elements. The descriptive element is a neutralist account of the origin of conceptual complexity. The normative element is a neutralist account of the present value of conceptual complexity, which should in most instances be tolerated rather than eliminated.

There is reason to believe that complex scientific concepts arise through largely neutral processes. For instance, there are two basic ways in which patchwork concepts form—both plausibly neutral. The first way involves a concept that is initially applied in a loose way across a range of domains, then is rendered more precisely measurable (e.g., “temperature,” Chang Reference Chang2004; “hardness,” Wilson Reference Wilson2006, ch. 6). If the worldly supports of the initial uses vary across domain, the term can naturally settle into local patches of use that behave in importantly different ways (e.g., “hardness” picks out different physical properties when applied to different classes of materials). The second way involves the precisification of a concept within one domain, followed by an extension to new domains (e.g., “cortical column,” Haueis Reference Haueis2016; “homology,” Novick Reference Novick2018). In these cases, what seems like a conceptually straightforward extension may prove in retrospect to have substantially increased the complexity of the concept.

Both processes involve ignorance of complexity on the part of concept users. Both involve the application of a concept to a domain before it is known exactly how the concept will behave in that domain. “Hardness” was applied to various materials well before people had any deep understanding of its physical underpinnings (let alone reason to suspect that these differ by material). “Homology”—initially a morphological concept—was applied to genes well before the discovery of the nature of DNA replication. In hindsight, however, these details cause gene homology to work in importantly different ways from morphological homology.

When conceptual extension proceed in advance of detailed knowledge about how the concept will adapt to new domains, concept users have little ability to consider the potential costs and benefits of rendering the concept more complex through such extension. Such extensions often seem straightforward when they occur, precisely because the complexifying factors are unknown (Wilson Reference Wilson1982). Only after struggling to accommodate the concept to the new domain does the complexity reveal itself, at which time the complexity may be entrenched and difficult to eliminate.

Consideration of these processes of complexification provides prima facie reason to accept a neutralist account of the origin of conceptual complexity. Complexity arises, not because it is advantageous as such, but rather because, once the extension has happened, it is required to make the concept function at all in the new domain. Some nuance is required here. In speaking of conceptual extensions “adapting” or being “accommodated” to a new domain, this model may seem adaptationist after all. I am not denying that language users in these scientific communities consciously try to make their local uses of a concept fit the domain. My point is that the complexity plays no role in this process; it is a by-product, not a cause.

Transposable elements furnish an evolutionary analogy. The processes by which transposable elements spread are adaptive for the transposable element. This generates genomic complexity for the organism as a by-product. From the organism’s perspective, most transposable element insertions are neutral. Likewise, complexity-increasing conceptual extensions may be adaptive at the level of the local use, but this does not mean that the complexity is adaptive. Indeed, this should be expected, for most of the pressures driving such conceptual adaptations function within the local communities. A global linguistic regulatory structure that spans subcommunities of researchers is rare.

But, if complex concepts arise using neutral processes, why tolerate them? If they offered an especially good way of dealing with a complex world, that would be one thing. But if they are the unforeseen consequence of deceptively simple-seeming extensions, why not replace them with an array of more cleanly defined concepts (as eliminativists favor)?

Enter the normative element of the neutral theory of conceptual complexity: Conceptual complexity is probably net neutral or, more precisely, nearly neutral, and is therefore not worth eliminating. In evolutionary biology, the neutral theory predicts that most mutations are selectively neutral, and so spread (or not) through genetic drift. The nearly neutral theory extends the neutral theory, recognizing that, as effective population size decreases, genetic drift becomes more powerful. For any given effective population size, then, there is a range of selective values (positive and negative) where selection is weaker than drift. Mutations in that range—nearly neutral mutations—will evolve as if they are neutral (Ohta Reference Ohta1992).

The neutral theory of conceptual complexity suggests that most conceptual complexity is nearly neutral in an analogous sense. Using complex concepts may be slightly beneficial or slightly deleterious, compared with other ways of conceptualizing a domain, but these (dis)advantages are not so large as to occasion much worry. It just doesn’t really matter which we use, so we can follow whatever the contingent historical development of our conceptual toolkit has left us. Conceptual housekeeping (Haueis and Novick Reference Haueis and Novickforthcoming) is rarely worth the effort.

There are a few reasons to think this. Some follow from what has already been discussed. The weakness of adaptationist arguments provides reason to be sympathetic to the neutralist view. Likewise, the account just given of how conceptual complexity arises is readily compatible with the normative aspect of the neutral theory. Both of these reasons, however, cut only against the idea that conceptual complexity is beneficial, without addressing its costs. Thus, they might equally be taken to support eliminativism.

There is, however, reason to think that conceptual complexity is not especially harmful. Humans are competent navigators of polysemy, they are able to determine relevant uses from context (Falkum Reference Falkum2015). Biologists researching speciation, for instance, recognize the differences between macrobes and microbes. While conceptual complexity may pose greater difficulty for nonspecialists (who are more susceptible to problematic conflations of distinct uses), there are at least two reasons not to worry overly much about this. First, the obvious alternative (replacing a complex concept with multiple simpler concepts) comes with challenges of its own. Second, the differences between specialized uses are often not relevant. Outside of engineering contexts, the differences between the hardness of plastic and of metal are of limited importance, and even biologists can often skate over the fine differences between species concepts (Currie Reference Currie2016).

Furthermore, while conceptual complexity may not be of much value, what is valuable is familiarity. By the time the complexities introduced by a given conceptual extension reveal themselves, the new use may be entrenched: The relevant speakers will have habituated to it (and to switching between uses). Changing the linguistic behavior of an entire community is difficult, and is worth the effort only where complexity is causing significant, demonstrable confusion (Haueis and Novick Reference Haueis and Novickforthcoming). In other words, by the time the value of a particular instance of conceptual complexity can be explicitly assessed, it may be too late to change by deliberate effort. This may be understood as a conceptual analog of constructive neutral evolution (Stoltzfus Reference Stoltzfus1999; Wideman et al. Reference Wideman, Novick, Muñoz-Gómez and Doolittle2019; Muñoz-Gómez et al. Reference Muñoz-Gómez, Gaurav, Wideman and Geiler-Samerotte2021), in which complexity increases using neutral processes such that later changes “lock in” earlier ones by rendering reversion to the former, simpler state deleterious.

If the preceding reasoning is cogent, then the neutral theory of conceptual complexity is at worst plausible. There is good reason to suspect that conceptual complexity emerges, not because it is beneficial, but rather as the by-product of neutral processes. Furthermore, once it has emerged, there is good reason to think that it is neither advantageous enough to celebrate nor deleterious enough to eliminate.

5. Conclusion: Using the neutral theory

This article is short and polemical. Its arguments are intended to motivate the plausibility of the neutral theory of conceptual complexity; I harbor no delusions that they definitively establish it. For my purposes, plausibility suffices: The neutralist perspective has been unduly neglected. It deserves more, and more serious, consideration. I would like to conclude by discussing two roles for the neutral theory going forward.

As with neutralism-selectionism debates in evolutionary theory, discussion of the respective roles of neutral and adaptive processes in generating and sustaining conceptual complexity will take the form of a relative frequency debate (Beatty Reference Beatty1997). Almost certainly, some conceptual complexity is adaptive, some is harmful, and some is neutral. I have provided reason to think that more of it falls into the last category than has generally been recognized. The first role for the neutral theory is thus as a viable candidate explanation for particular interesting cases of conceptual complexity.

The second role for the neutral theory of conceptual complexity is methodological. While the neutral theory of molecular evolution is still the subject of intense debate (Kern and Hahn Reference Kern and Hahn2018; Jensen et al. Reference Jensen, Payseur, Wolfgang Stephan, Aquadro, Charlesworth and Charlesworth2019), its value is partially independent of its truth. By establishing on theoretical grounds the potential power of genetic drift, the neutral theory raised the standards for attributing evolutionary change to selection (Dietrich Reference Dietrich2006). The neutral theory of conceptual complexity can play a comparable role. We have already seen that adaptationist arguments about the value of conceptual complexity are generally insufficient to rule out neutralist alternatives. This is, in part, due to the fact that the neutralist view has simply not been considered. Even if, on further study, the neutral theory proves to fit only a limited range of cases, explicitly including it as a possibility can force adaptationist arguments (monist and pluralist alike) to greater sophistication, and so can yield a clearer picture of the conditions under which complexity of all three kinds arises (Kovaka Reference Kovaka2021).

Is this enough? Does this secure the importance of the neutral theory of conceptual complexity? Or is conceptual complexity an interesting topic for philosophical reflection only when it is either especially valuable or especially harmful? My own view is that what is important is to find the truth, and that if the neutral theory is a valid investigative hypothesis, then to establish the theory, test it against particular cases, and defend it is a worthwhile philosophical exercise.

Acknowledgments

The author thanks Philipp Haueis, Ford Doolittle’s research group, the audience at the 2022 PSA conference, and an anonymous reviewer for Philosophy of Science for helpful feedback on written and spoken versions of this paper.

References

Beatty, John. 1997. “Why Do Biologists Argue Like They Do?Philosophy of Science 64 (December):S43243. https://doi.org/10.1086/392620 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobay, Louis-Marie, and Ochman, Howard. 2017. “Biological Species Are Universal across Life’s Domains.” Genome Biology and Evolution 9 (3):491501. https://doi.org/10.1093/gbe/evx026 Google Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2003a. “Homology in Comparative, Molecular, and Evolutionary Developmental Biology: The Radiation of a Concept.” Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution 299B (1):917. https://doi.org/10.1002/jez.b.36 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2003b. “Species Pluralism Does Not Imply Species Eliminativism.” Philosophy of Science 70 (5) 1305–16. https://doi.org/10.1086/377409 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2010. “The Epistemic Goal of a Concept: Accounting for the Rationality of Semantic Change and Variation.” Synthese 177 (1):1940. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9623-8 Google Scholar
Bursten, Julia R. 2018. “Smaller Than a Breadbox: Scale and Natural Kinds.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (1):123. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axw022 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1962. The Logical Foundations of Probability. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok. 2004. Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0195171276.001.0001 Google Scholar
Currie, Adrian M. 2016. “The Mystery of the Triceratops’s Mother: How to Be a Realist About the Species Category.” Erkenntnis 81 (4):795816. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9769-3 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benedetto, De, Matteo. 2021. “Taming Conceptual Wanderings: Wilson-Structuralism.” Synthese 199 (5):13225–46. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03374-3 Google Scholar
Dietrich, Michael R. 2006. “Three Perspectives on Neutrality and Drift in Molecular Evolution.” Philosophy of Science 73 (5):666–77. https://doi.org/10.1086/518521 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, Doolittle, W., and Sapienza, Carmen. 1980. “Selfish Genes, the Phenotype Paradigm and Genome Evolution.” Nature 284 (5757):601–3. https://doi.org/10.1038/284601a0 Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, Marc. 1992. “Eliminative Pluralism.” Philosophy of Science 59 (4):671–90. https://doi.org/10.1086/289701 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ereshefsky, Marc. 2010. “Microbiology and the Species Problem.” Biology & Philosophy 25 (4):553–68. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9211-9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkum, Ingrid Lossius. 2015. “The How and Why of Polysemy: A Pragmatic Account.” Lingua, Polysemy: Current Perspectives and Approaches 157 (April):8399. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2014.11.004 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankham, Richard, Ballou, Jonathan D., Dudash, Michele R., Eldridge, Mark D. B., Fenster, Charles B., Lacy, Robert C., Mendelson, Joseph R., Porton, Ingrid J., Ralls, Katherine, and Ryder, Oliver A.. 2012. “Implications of Different Species Concepts for Conserving Biodiversity.” Biological Conservation 153 (September):2531. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biocon.2012.04.034 Google Scholar
Genome Reference Consortium. 2022. “GRCh38.P14.” https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/assembly/GCA_000001405.29 Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen J., and Lewontin, Richard C.. 1979. “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme.” Proceedings of the Royal Society B 205 (1161):581–98. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.1979.0086 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, Stephen J., and Vrba, Elisabeth S.. 1982. “Exaptation—A Missing Term in the Science of Form.” Paleobiology 8 (1):415. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0094837300004310 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., and Stotz, Karola. 2013. Genetics and Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511744082CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haueis, Philipp. 2016. “The Life of the Cortical Column: Opening the Domain of Functional Architecture of the Cortex (1955–1981).” History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 38 (3):2. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-016-0103-4 Google Scholar
Haueis, Philipp. 2018. “Beyond Cognitive Myopia: A Patchwork Approach to the Concept of Neural Function.” Synthese 195 (12):53735402. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01991-z Google Scholar
Haueis, Philipp. 2021a. “The Death of the Cortical Column? Patchwork Structure and Conceptual Retirement in Neuroscientific Practice.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 85 (February):101–13. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2020.09.010 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haueis, Philipp. 2021b. “A Generalized Patchwork Approach to Scientific Concepts.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/716179 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haueis, Philipp, and Novick, Rose. Forthcoming. “Conceptual Patchworks and Conceptual Housekeeping.” In Concepts, Induction, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge, edited by Theodore Arabatzis and Corinne Bloch-Mullins.Google Scholar
Jamniczky, Heather A. 2005. “Biological Pluralism and Homology.” Philosophy of Science 72 (5):687–98. https://doi.org/10.1086/508108 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, Jeffrey D., Payseur, Bret A., Wolfgang Stephan, Charles F. Aquadro, Michael Lynch, Charlesworth, Deborah, and Charlesworth, Brian. 2019. “The Importance of the Neutral Theory in 1968 and 50 Years On: A Response to Kern and Hahn 2018.” Evolution 73 (1):111–14. https://doi.org/10.1111/evo.13650 Google Scholar
Justus, James. 2012. “Carnap on Concept Determination: Methodology for Philosophy of Science.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (2):161–79. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0027-5 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kern, Andrew D., and Hahn, Matthew W. 2018. “The Neutral Theory in Light of Natural Selection.” Molecular Biology and Evolution 35 (6):1366–71. https://doi.org/10.1093/molbev/msy092 Google Scholar
Kimura, Motoo. 1983. The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511623486 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovaka, Karen. 2021. “Fighting about Frequency.” Synthese 199 (3):7777–97. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03139-y CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard. 2009. Doing without Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195306880.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muñoz-Gómez, Sergio A., Gaurav, Bilolikar, Wideman, Jeremy G., and Geiler-Samerotte, Kerry. 2021. “Constructive Neutral Evolution 20 Years Later.” Journal of Molecular Evolution 89 (3):172–82. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00239-021-09996-y CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Neto, Celso. 2019. “What Is a Lineage?Philosophy of Science 86 (5):10991110. https://doi.org/10.1086/705511 Google Scholar
Neto, Celso. 2020. “When Imprecision Is a Good Thing, or How Imprecise Concepts Facilitate Integration in Biology.” Biology & Philosophy 35 (6):58. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09774-y Google Scholar
Novick, Aaron. 2018. “The Fine Structure of ‘Homology.’Biology & Philosophy 33 (1–2):6. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9617-3 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Novick, Aaron, and Ford Doolittle, W.. 2019. “How Microbes ‘Jeopardize’ the Modern Synthesis.” PLOS Genetics 15 (5):e1008166. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.1008166 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Novick, Aaron, and Ford Doolittle, W.. 2021. “‘Species’ without Species.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 87 (June):7280. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2021.03.006 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ohta, Tomoko. 1992. “The Nearly Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution.” Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 23:263–86.10.1146/annurev.es.23.110192.001403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palazzo, Alexander F., and Ryan Gregory, T.. 2014. “The Case for Junk DNA.” PLOS Genetics 10 (5): e1004351. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.1004351 Google Scholar
Pennisi, Elizabeth. 2012. “ENCODE Project Writes Eulogy for Junk DNA.” Science 337 (6099):1159–61. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.337.6099.1159 Google Scholar
Ricroch, A., Yockteng, R., Brown, S. C., and Nadot, S.. 2005. “Evolution of Genome Size across Some Cultivated Allium Species.” Genome 48 (3):511–20. https://doi.org/10.1139/g05-017 Google Scholar
Stoltzfus, Arlin. 1999. “On the Possibility of Constructive Neutral Evolution.” Journal of Molecular Evolution 49 (2):169–81. https://doi.org/10.1007/PL00006540 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Taylor, Henry, and Vickers, Peter. 2017. “Conceptual Fragmentation and the Rise of Eliminativism.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 7 (1):1740. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-016-0136-2 Google Scholar
Wideman, Jeremy G., Novick, Aaron, Muñoz-Gómez, Sergio A., and Doolittle, W. Ford. 2019. “Neutral Evolution of Cellular Phenotypes.” Current Opinion in Genetics & Development 58–59 (October):8794. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gde.2019.09.004 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, Mark. 1982. “Predicate Meets Property.” The Philosophical Review 91 (4):549. https://doi.org/10.2307/2184801 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Mark. 2006. Wandering Significance: An Essay on Conceptual Behaviour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Mark. 2018. Physics Avoidance: And Other Essays in Conceptual Strategy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar