Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T22:35:45.691Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Smells and politics of Utopia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 March 2024

Babette Babich*
Affiliation:
Fordham University, New York, NY, USA

Abstract

Utopia is nominally a ‘nowhere’ that is also, as Thomas More tells us, a ‘good’ place. Although there are competing cognate notions, the Greek description looms large in most accounts of utopia. The details of this ideal are so specified that utopic literature consists in a catalogue (and critique) of specifications. This essay draws attention to the fragrance attributed to Lucian’s ‘Isles of the Blest’ together with Ivan Illich’s attention to ‘atmosphere’ and to the aura and the nose along with Nietzsche’s emphasis on the sense of smell. Utopic suspicion is discussed as parallels are drawn with pragmatic critiques of utopia as inherently totalitarian along with the ‘good life’ in political theory and the programmatic default of techno-utopic fantasy. In the historical context of ‘conspiracy’ and the politics of living and breathing together in community, I conclude with Illich on pax and breath.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Fédération Internationale des Sociétés de Philosophie / International Federation of Philosophical Societies (FISP).

Tracy Burr Strong (1943-2022), in memoriam.

ναυσὶ δ᾽ οὔτε πεζὸς ἰών κεν εὕροις

ἐς Ὑπερβορέων ἀγῶνα θαυμαστὰν ὁδόν.Footnote 1

— Pindar, 10th Pythian Ode

Ein Gewitter war in unsrer Luft, die Natur, die wir

sind, verfinsterte sich — denn wir hatten keinen Weg.

— Nietzsche

Archetypes

Utopia is a ‘nowhere’ locus articulated as a fantasy projection. Thus the 2nd Century C.E. Lucian of Samosata wrote one of the first accounts of utopia, also regarded as first in the genre of science-fiction: his ‘true history’ (or ‘story’) (Ἀληθῆ διηγήματα/Vera Historia) also included in the genre of tall tales as Lucian tells the reader that everything he says is a lie.Footnote 2

Described from antiquity as an ‘ideal’ locale beyond everyday life, utopia is associated with paradise and Lucian lists: ‘three hundred and sixty and five springs of water and as many more of honey’, and ‘of perfume five hundred, though these indeed are smaller than the springs of water and honey’, and ‘seven rivers of milk and of wine eight’ (Church Reference Church1880: 67-68), numerically, volumetrically more than anyone could drink, with geographical details fulsome, glossy as a travel brochure. Tabulated abundance is a utopian signature, a ‘standing reserve’ – not unlike Heidegger’s formula for modern technology – calculated to offset, in security and perpetuity, any imaginable lack.

Other characteristics of utopia are rules not to be broken. Paradise has a totalitarian dimension and by the same token dissonance if not predictable failure seems to haunt the story of the original paradise (Gen. 2-3) and so too Lucian’s ‘Blessed Isles’ or Thomas More’s Utopia. Thus fated, satire has been argued to have been More’s original intention.Footnote 3 To the genre of satire or folly or ‘light’ literature must be added a roster of roles in Greek and Celtic epic traditions, continuing in gaming culture which may likewise be regarded as a scopic (and competitive) ‘staging’ of utopia.Footnote 4

There is a variously specialized literature commenting on Homer, on Hesiod, on the excesses of Plato’s ideal city or, on the lie as lie in the (tautologous) paradox of Lucian’s True History. The liar who revels in details – details making, so Kant reminds us, the telling of a lie such a challenge to maintain – flaunts his prowess. Accordingly, Lucian is celebrated as ‘lover of lies’, title of a dialogue translated by Thomas More. Other authors drawing on Lucian have included Erasmus and Swift along with Goethe and Nietzsche. And Lucian draws on Pindar, thus today’s science fantasy industry, including Lovecraft’s Cthulhu, features Hyperborea, here to recall the Song of a Hyperborean by the Irish Thomas Moore (1779-1852) and in pulp fantasy literature of the mid-20th century, Conan the Cimmerian who would surely have known, to echo Pindar’s 10th Pythian, the way to HyperboreaFootnote 5: right next door to Cimmeria on the map in Robert E. Howard’s Conan the Conqueror (Reference Howard1950 but cf. Bridgman Reference Bridgman2002). And on a map reproduced on the book jacket of the late Henry Kissinger’s (1923-2023), World Order: Reflections on the Character of Nations and the Course of History, ‘Hyperborea’ appears directly under the author’s name (Kissinger Reference Kissinger2015).

The first part of Lucian’s A True Story takes the narrator’s ship to the moon via whirlwind to witness a variety of stellar battles – complete with cosmic spiders – between the inhabitants of the moon and the sun (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 260ff). In the second part, after relating how a seafaring vessel would be tricked out for a passage over ice and the sojourns of the crew in a leviathan and in caves beneath the ice, and including reports of islands of cheese and of cork and passing a pair of mountainous islands, crowned with smoking fire (usually assumed an allusion to Stromboli, famous to this day), the seafarers spy a flat, low-lying, i.e., conveniently accessible island:

When at length we were near it, a wonderful breeze blew about us, sweet and fragrant like the one that, on the word of the historian Herodotus, breathes perfume from Araby the blest. (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 309)

The travelogue continues, there are ‘transparent rivers emptying softly into the sea’, such that a ‘rare, pure atmosphere enfolded the place and sweet breezes’ added to a ‘whisper of delightful unbroken music’ (ibid.: 311). This, Lucian tells the reader, is ‘the Isle of the Blest, and … the ruler was the Cretan Rhadamanthus’ (ibid.). As Rhadamanthus judges the dead, Lucian explains that the crew has been ‘translated’ (Rohde Reference Rohde1894: 1) to one of the more fortunate loci (there are several) of Greek afterlife. Law and justice are key not unlike the model of Homer’s account of the Isle of Scheria where Odysseus is similarly judged (cf. Welcker Reference Welcker1833). Although Lucian and his companions are reminded that they will be judged again ‘after death’ and are thus permitted exceptional ‘leave to remain’ on the island for a period of ‘not more than seven months’ (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 309), from the point of view of Greek Orphism and the mystery cults (and Plato’s Phaedrus), the achievement is quasi-divine, including Empedoclean and Zoroastrian overtones as these recur in Hölderlin and Nietzsche.

The atmosphere includes botanical fragrances wafted by gentle breezes or zephyrs and Lucian inspires Goethe when he asks, and his query likewise echoes Pindar, if one ‘knows the land, where lemon trees blossom’.Footnote 6 Lucian reports rivers of ‘the finest myrrh’ in which one can swim ‘comfortably’, bathhouses of ‘glass warmed by burning cinnamon’ (ibid. 315). Geographic and agricultural details, one more fantastic than the other (bettering the harvests of the Phaeacians referenced in Homer’s Odyssey), with the grapevines of the Isle of the Blest yielding ‘twelve vintages a year’, with fields of wheat bearing ‘loaves of bread all baked’ (ibid.) etc. There is dining in ‘thick meadows’ with ‘thick woods of all sorts round about it’. Lush and comfortable, domesticated and abundant, this ‘nature’ is utterly tamed, no dissonance, everything we want, nothing we don’t (cf. Paquot Reference Paquot2005). Milk and honey: perfection piled on perfection.

Lucian’s Isle of the Blest is an island of perpetual, if dim light, specified down to the totalitarian restrictions that are also characteristic of ‘smart’ architecture, with complicated echoes of Le Corbusier (Reference Corbusier1930; cf. Sobin Reference Sobin, Kinnard and Schwartz1996; Addington Reference Addington, Lightman, Sarewitz and Desser2003; Babich Reference Babich2023b). Exactly to spec: not too bright, not too dark. ‘Perfect weather’, there are no seasons: it is always spring. And timewise, no one ages, as in death: everyone stays the same age they were when they arrived (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 315). Every day given over to conversation and sensual enjoyment: no pain, no war, no work.

In Lucian’s tale, the narrator reports his encounters with past famous personages, including ‘demigods’ and philosophers and – inspiring ‘quotations’ up to Woody Allen to this day – arranges a dialogue in which Homer himself settles all ‘Homeric questions’.

On their departure, to the day and date specified, the changing smells around Lucian and his companions indicate their progress. No sooner had they

passed out of the fragrant atmosphere when of a sudden a terrible odour greeted us as of asphalt, sulfur and pitch burning together, and a vile, insufferable stench as of roasting human flesh… (335)

These two regions border one another, very heaven and very hell.

Politically, the desire for sweets and the delights of sensual indulgence interrupts Plato’s Republic. Upon hearing Socrates’ description of a balanced and ‘just’ state, his two main interlocutors, Glaucon and Adeimantus, object, instigating Socrates to describe an imaginary city of ‘inflamed’ injustice (Rep.: 372e), with junior guardians sent off to war in search of unguents, perfumes, courtesans and sweets ‘of all kinds’ (373a), the accoutrements of the ‘good’ life. Socrates’ interlocutors know that no matter how harmonious, a life in a sober ‘state of nature’, sleeping on beds ‘of bryony and myrtle’ and ‘for dessert … figs and chickpeas’ will not cut it. The young men in Plato’s Polity know they will not be happy there. No more than Satan was inclined, as Milton has expounded, ‘to serve in heaven’ (Reference Milton1667: 1.263), no more could Adam and Eve successfully remain in the paradise in which/for which they were created to dwell.

Thomas More titled his 1518 satire, Utopia (More Reference More and Malsbary2020; and see Reference More, Surtz and Hexter1965), as a ‘nowhere’, speaking from the start of an Eu-Topia. Advertising his book (along with himself, its author), More tells us his topic is

‘The best/state of a commonwealth/and the new island of Utopia,/a truly golden handbook,/no less beneficial than entertaining/by the most distinguished and eloquent man/Thomas More,/citizen and sheriff of the famous city of London’. (More Reference More and Malsbary2020)

Learned commentary on More’s book echoes More’s own gloss, which he sets as legend beneath his map of the island (Figure 1):

Figure 1. Map of Utopia in More’s 1516 edition.

Called Utopia [‘No Place’] by the ancients for my under-population,
Now, I am a rival to Plato’s city, perhaps its victor:
What that city depicted with words, I alone have produced
With men and resources and the best laws
I should be called, deservedly, by the name Eutopia [‘Good Place’]. (ibid.: 7)

The island speaks, and the ‘under-population’ that drives Malthus and the dreams of today’s globalists, the point regarding the ou [‘No’] and the eu [‘Good’] is here (Cf. Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1987: 270). Qua just-so story, qua make-believe, the reader is thereby informed that the author knows that what he says is ‘fabulous’ from the outset.

This fabulosity is Lucian’s signature. We encounter his apology, or ‘conceit’, at the outset of A True Story, modelled as he says on the practice of sport as athletes emphasize intervals of relaxation (essential for bodybuilding, an art invented by the Greeks). Telling us that ‘philosophers’ tell any number of lies, as Plato and Plutarch echo the proverbial: πολλὰ ψεύδονται ἀοιδοὶ, ‘many lies tell the poets’, Lucian assures the reader that the poet, if seeking no less ‘relaxation’ than the philosopher, is more trustworthy: ‘telling the truth in nothing else’ (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 253), the poet admits that he is a liar.

Lucian (and More and Swift) let the reader in on the joke and stylistic connivance is part of utopic literature. In a darker mode, Goethe’s Faust and Die Zauberlehrling are indebted to Lucian’s Lucius or the Ass. Similar ‘dark arts’ are key to the popular fiction of Hogwarts, with Professor Severus Snape teaching the secrets of potions to idealized (British school style) modern ‘sorcerer’s apprentices’,Footnote 7 along with the complexities of love and the heart’s forbearance conveyed by Goethe’s Verweile doch, du bist so schön. For the classicist, Pierre Hadot, forbearance is key to Goethe’s ‘The present is our only happiness’ (Hadot Reference Hadot2008), as Hadot reflects his own apprenticeship to the Stoic counsel (Hadot Reference Hadot1992) of Marcus Aurelius.

‘Yes-saying’ attends the first day in Genesis. Along with forbearance, Nietzsche recognized benediction as inviting the moment to stay as a tension for human impermanence in Plato’s spirit. Thus we read the section of Thus Spoke Zarathustra titled, after Lucian, ‘On the Blessed Isles [Auf den glückseligen Inseln]’, beginning with the figs that for Marcus Aurelius signified the complicated beauty of age: ‘they are good and sweet, and in that they fall their red skin tears. A north wind am I to ripe figs’ (1980, 4: 109). To the sweetness of fallen figs, Nietzsche’s Zarathustra adds: ‘Autumn is about us and pure sky and afternoon’, reading atmospheric signifiers illuminated in the paintings of the American engineer, Maxfield [Frederick] Parrish (1870-1966) (Figure 2).

Figure 2. Maxfield Parrish, Dream Castle in the Sky, 1908. Public Domain.

Directionally associated with the Blessed Isles, as Ivan Illich will later speak of the ‘rivers north of the future’, Nietzsche adds the image of distant seas (ferne Meer). Echoing both the Pre-Platonic Philosophers and Plato contra God as a ‘thought’ that is, as such, so Nietzsche writes: ‘evil and menschenfeindlich’, unthinkable, we know, post-Kant, for humanity:

– all this teaching of the One and the Plenum and the Unmoved and the Satisfied and the Permanent [Unvergänglichen]! All the Permanent – that is only a parable [Gleichniss]. And the poets lie too much. – (Nietzsche Reference Nietzsche, Colli and Montinari1980, 4: 110)

Nietzsche emphasizes the importance of ‘impermanence’ and dissonance in the context of the Blessed Isles: ‘Yes, much bitter dying must be in your life, you creators! Thus are you a prophet and redeemer of all impermanence’ (ibid.: 110). Nietzsche’s tone echoes Empedocles’ lament:

‘Verily, through a hundred souls I have already passed on my way and through a hundred cradles and birth pangs. Many farewells have I taken already, I know the heartbreaking last hours.’ (ibid.)

Utopias, like the Isle of the Blest, have rigid laws. Similarly, Adam and Eve are created – not born – into a consumer’s paradise complete with a consumer’s catch. And just as the Phaeacians cannot but offend Poseidon, restoring Odysseus in one of their thought-guided transports to Ithaca, they suffer the consequences of their kindness even as their beneficiary rewards their generosity with angry incomprehension, cursing them as after so much time away (he has been gone two decades), Odysseus barely recognizes his home. Adam and Eve may eat from every tree with the exceptions of the tree of knowledge of good and evil and the tree of life, which forbidden fruit is just as automatically desired. The only reason paradise will need a snake is to have someone to blame for the inevitable transgression.

Adam and Eve are unhappy: they were disinclined, think of Goethe’s formula as Hadot emphasises, to beg the beauties at their disposal to ‘stay’. They wanted more. We hear the same impatient desire at the inception of the second book of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra, ‘Like a cry and a jubilation I want to travel across wide seas, until I find the blessed isles where my friends dwell: –’ (1980, 4: 107) Signifiers of utopian voyage, suitably Lucianic, Nietzsche reflects that in addition to his friends, his enemies, likewise, belong ‘to my bliss’ (ibid.).

Walter Benjamin, reflecting happiness in a historical context, reminds us that the ‘past can be seized only as an image which flashes up at the instant when it can be recognized and is never seen again’ (Benjamin Reference Benjamin and Arendt1969: 255). The messianic promise which, post-Nietzsche, Benjamin describes as ‘the subduer of the Antichrist’, epitomizes Klee’s Angelus Novus, the strobe lightning flash of the moment illuminating the storm ‘blowing from paradise, that has got caught in his wings with such violence that the angel can no longer close them’ (ibid.: 259). For Benjamin, ‘this storm is what we call progress’ (ibid.) and Benjamin’s cousin, Günther Anders, younger by a decade, takes this up in The Antiquatedness of Humanity (Anders Reference Anders1956a). In this way, via Anders, critical theory features elements of utopic thought, just as other political readings connect utopia with Marx together with the pragmatic imperative and tech-promise of ‘changing’ the world.Footnote 8

Along with the fragrance of the blessed, the ‘odor of sanctity’ (i.e., the sweetness of death as Ivan Illich and Michel de Certeau remind us) is the anticipation of disappointment. Benjamin’s storm blowing from paradise is the worm of unhappiness in what should have been bliss in the garden of Eden but was not for the first created lovers who, given one another, should have had all they needed. Again: they did not. No sooner do we hear of a paradise be it in folkloric French-English: Cockaigne or in German: Schlaraffenland or today’s restricted ideal of an ecological utopia (the long-promised Green revolution that never came and is now replaced by anxiety over Climate Change), like any manner of politically minded utopias from Plato to Augustine, Campanella and Voltaire, than we find ourselves sharing the spirit of Glaucon and Adeimantus: raising personally minded objections.

Darko Suvin has observed the relation between ‘the Greek and Hellenistic “blessed island” stories, the “fabulous voyage” from Antiquity on, the Renaissance and Baroque “utopia” and “planetary novel”, the Enlightenment “state (political) novel”, the modern “anticipation”, anti-utopia, etc.’ (Suvin Reference Suvin1972: 372; cf. Suvin Reference Suvin2010). Political connections are key from the start yet before a theorist can finish articulating his/her schematism for a perfect land (or life or ‘new world order’), his interlocutors, we, the readers, already guess its defects. Homer writes the objection into Odysseus’ mouth with his insistence on home (and L. Frank Baum’s Dorothy in his 1910 Emerald City of Oz likewise transfigures the ordinary by contrast with the phantasmagoric). Achilles who had raged at the beginning of the Iliad, laments at the end, longing for the life of an anyman, a day labourer. The presentiment of disappointment, badness of fit, links utopic tales with the dystopic. Above I recalled Benjamin’s angel and I mentioned the ironic articulations of SwiftFootnote 9 as Lucian links Swift and Nietzsche (and Goethe). Nor as we have seen, can satire be separated from the dream of utopia (see further, Babich Reference Babich2011, Reference Babich, Hutter and Friedland2013).

The same disconnect inspires the utopian vision of messianic paradise that is, as Max Brod heard it from Kafka, ‘nicht für uns’.Footnote 10 In the same way, a catalogue of negations constitutes the second 1980 volume of Günther Anders’ Die Antiquirtheit des Menschen, from the ‘looks’ of things to materialism (think Baudrillard or Bourdieu), listing mass produced products, the human world, the masses, work, machines, philosophical anthropology, the individual, ideology, conformism, limitations, the private (think the opposition as Arendt would speak of this between the public and the private), death, reality. Etc., etc., all the way to evil and all of it antiquated, périmée.

The roster was already present for Anders in his first collapsed utopia (Anders Reference Anders1956a and Reference Andersb). The problem is the promise/disappointment of nature as ‘paradise’, as free good, repository of a largesse of and from which one may take what one will, ad libitum. This conviction, underwriting Locke’s vision, regards ‘nature’ as ‘raw material’, as Anders writes, calculated as resource, existent (Sein) or else to be cultivated in terms of value (Wert). Thus ‘a glance at the Milky Way’ offers a much-too-much vision of utopia, the ‘vielzuviel des Universums’ (Anders Reference Anders1956a: 184), which can lead in Kant’s phrase to a confession of ‘the’ moral law as much as to Nietzsche’s refusal in his Gay Science description of a playing machine (§109), a music-box (Spielwerk).

Anders varies Schopenhauer’s estimation of life as a ‘business enterprise’ that does not cover its costs, a ‘metaphysical scandal’ corresponding to the cosmos as spectacular waste. In a footnoted poem, Anders recounts the phantasms of a ‘feverish’ Columbus. Anders’s poem relates the story of an explorer of coasts, Vespucci is not named any more than Herschel is in Anders’s annotation-embedded poem, but he gives to such human, all too human explorers the task of recording angels – this is, after all, the project of the television fantasy series, Star Trek – asking a question fit for Gödel: who counts the recorders in the list of lists?

Anders’ poem has apocalyptic and cosmological, metaphysical, eschatological overtones as he asks, and note the charting reference as this is also a link with More (and Anders can do with such a link as he writes his own novel, The Molussians (Anders Reference Anders1992), complete with their own language, again like More, based on a Greek metric form, which Anders devises (see Babich Reference Babich2022: 30ff):

Which cartographer maps the anonymous
Coral reefs, standing at the bottom of the sea,
Veins of gold that have yet to be seen,
Constellations still needing naming – (Anders Reference Anders1980: 341)

In addition to Star Trek, one reads geography as archive: a catalogue of exotic loci throughout the 19th and 20th centuries. Anders listing cartographic details at the bottom of the sea, Star Trek mapping the stars, utopic geography catalogues exotic loci as standing reserve, for future development. As one candidate for Utopia, the 20th century highlights Tibet (‘the mysterious’) and the not-insignificant role (for Anders and others) of triangulation of maps and radio for the purpose of aerial bombardment in Richards Reference Richards1992, ‘Archive and Utopia’, here with reference to James Hilton’s Lost Horizon re the bombing of Shanghai, thence to Shangri-La. If the locale retains its mythic allure, political conflicts continue to this day via the more domesticated image of the no less politically problematic, Dalai Lama (Bernis Reference Bernis1999).

Like modern Europe, like the maps of all the world, Tibet’s maps have been redrawn for political purposes and the cartographer’s outline matters for More’s Utopia. And travel accounts from antiquity give directions such that we can find Homer’s Scheria (said to be Corfu) and even where we are told, as in the case of Pindar, with respect to Hyperborea, that the way cannot be found by land or sea: negation captures imagination.

Nietzsche tells us that we ourselves, as he speaks of his Germans, are Hyperboreans (Reference Nietzsche, Colli and Montinari1980, 6: 169), allied to a race about whom we know everything and nothing. If the path is accessible, so Pindar tells us, ‘by neither ship nor foot’, the focus on the air and the winds, the atmospheric, implies the need to fly and thus Lucian outfits his Icaromenippus, or the Sky Man, and has his Menippus fashion one pinion on ‘the right’ from an eagle, motley as he flew, ‘the left wing’ from a vulture (Lucian Reference Harmon1915: 285-287). But that, we know, is a lie.

Utopic utility and tech apocalypse

Es beginnet nemlich der Reichtum For Wealth begins in

Im Meere. Sie, The sea. And they,

Wie Maler, bringen zusammen Like painters, bring together

Das Schöne der Erd … The beautiful things of the earth

— Hölderlin, Andenken/Remembrance

As nowhere, Utopia is cloud-cuckoo-land, clouds being key as Pindar warned Hieron of Syracuse in a darkly lyric mode for failing to value his poet’s work. Hieron had commissioned two poems from two different poets and did not, when he won, opt for Pindar’s ode as his victory ode, which injury prompted Pindar to expand his original ode for free, adding to the 2nd Pythian the famous Castor song, repeating and intensifying the parallel with Ixion who as a mortal dwelling among the Olympian Gods sought to seduce Hera.

Deities outdoing poets and philosophers in deceptive prowess, Zeus (Figure 3) replaced Hera, the goddess, his spouse, object of Ixion’s desire, with a phantom, Νεφελη, such that Ixion embraced a cloud, fruit of which atmospheric congress was a mongrel monster who proceeded, accelerating bastardy, to mate with Magnesian mares, engendering the race of centaurs.

Figure 3. Peter Paul Rubens, Juno’s Deception, 1620-1624. Print. British Museum.

The cautionary element in the Castor song is manifest in political genres of the utopic as ‘monstration,’ here in Bertrand de Jouvenal’s sense:

If you can endow your ‘philosophical city’ with the semblance of reality, and cause your reader to see it, as if it were actually in operation, this is quite a different achievement from a mere explanation of the principles on which it should rest. This ‘causing to see’ by means of a feigned description is obviously what More aimed at: It is also the essential feature of the utopian genre. (de Jouvenal Reference de Jouvenal and Manuel1965: 220)

George Kateb, the Princeton political theorist, invokes utopia in a pragmatic vein via John Stuart Mill, reflecting on utilitarian definitions of the ‘good life’ post-cold war, conscious of the allure of socialist utopian claims exemplified on the left by Herbert Marcuse’s indictment of a ‘comfortable, smooth, reasonable, democratic unfreedom’ (Marcuse Reference Marcuse1964: 19), token of a then ‘new’ totalitarianism. Problematic for Kateb, who draws Schiller to his aid, is satisfaction, assuming such a ‘good life’ can be attained, a mere ‘ideal of appetite’ (Kateb Reference Kateb1965, 459).Footnote 11

Kateb is one of only few political theorists of his day and continuing to date, apart from Anders – Carl Schmitt, earlier, would be an exceptionFootnote 12 – to write about technology. In the early to mid-1960s, Kateb was fairly sure, as was Anders and Ellul along with Horkheimer and Adorno, just a little earlier, that the culture of the West was on the brink of technologically delivered ‘desublimation’: everything, instantly, seamlessly in our grasp. For his part, Anders in 1956 had foregrounded the apocalyptic, emphasizing that the exemplar of human finitude is thus become ‘Abel not Adam’. After August 6, 1945, the mortal syllogism has a new permutation:

  1. 1. All men are mortal.

  2. 2. All men are killable.

  3. 3. Humanity as a whole is killable. (Anders Reference Anders1956a, 243)

Anders reads this claim to different ends and Kateb, who writes about Arendt, does not refer to Anders. For Kateb, in a later reflection on his 1963, Utopia and its Enemies, assuming the attainability of ‘a world permanently without strife, poverty, constraint, stultifying labor’, the question would remain: is this goal desirable? Note that Kateb is not pointing to the troubles compounding paradise but the compatibility of the political ‘good life’ with the lack of virtue:

There need be no creativity involved, no esthetic significance; just easy pleasure taken in novelty, gadgetry, silly refinements of useless objects, the flash and roar of progress in transportation and communication; in self-indulgence, satiety, waste, and pretense. Given the presence of educated mind, these delights can be delights and still known for what they are. A utopian society could provide these delights recklessly, and without the motivations of planned obsolescence, maximization of profit, and the stultification of rebellious or disturbing impulses. Thus, by the standard of human felicity, which is the essential Utopian standard, the life of mind can plausibly (at least) be described as the best life. (Kateb Reference Kateb1965: 470-471)

For Kateb, what’s missing in the good life is (or can be) the ‘good’.

Hans Jonas, writing post Anders’ 1951 Kafka and post Ellul’s 1954 technological gamble and post Heidegger on science and technology,Footnote 13 along with the gnostic reflections Jonas had earlier elaborated, reminds us that

A critique of utopia has become necessary with the seeming possibility of its realization. For the first time in the annals of man, thanks to the powers of technology, the dream appears to be capable of turning into a task, and Marxism has seized on this novel chance to give its political gospel eschatological exaltation and pragmatic credibility at the same time. (Jonas Reference Jonas1981: 435)

Illich, deferring for his own part to Ellul’s earlier argument, had already observed the utopic technical promise along with its messianic default. As Illich writes in Tools of Conviviality:

The hypothesis was that machines can replace slaves. The evidence shows that, used for this purpose, machines enslave men. Neither a dictatorial proletariat nor a leisured mass can escape the dominion of constantly expanding industrial tools. (Illich Reference Illich1973: 23)

The ‘good life’ in ‘utopia’, specified as the ‘life of human felicity’, is what is problematic on Kateb’s reading, articulated for Marx, as ‘the embodiment of appetitive indulgence’ (Kateb Reference Kateb1965: 460) but refused by a number of thinkers including Marcuse and Arendt both of whom share ‘a contempt for the consumer’s paradise’ (ibid.: 465), as Kateb quotes W. H. Auden’s Vespers, epitomizing an epoch of jaded decadence and ‘some august day of outrage when hellikins cavort through ruined drawing-rooms’ (ibid.: 460).

Writing about utopia, similar reservations are common: leisure sounds like laziness and self-satisfaction. The threat of boredom encroaches on the second half of Auden’s line, matched with an artless misogyny coupled with what this ‘fine political poet’, here in Kateb’s words, can do with a hyphen and well-placed majuscule: ‘…and fish-wives intervene in the Chamber’.

If Ellul and Anders were raising questions, if Horkheimer and Adorno were already challenging the ideal of technological utopia (including Odysseus), Nietzsche in the closing decades of his 19th century mocked the technological promise of the universal ‘grüne Weide-Glück’ of the herd, featuring ‘security, safety, comfort and an easier life for all’ (Reference Nietzsche, Colli and Montinari1980, 5: 61), coupled with what Nietzsche calls the ‘blessing of work’, ‘den Segen der Arbeit’ (ibid.: 382), i.e., ‘mechanical activity’, that is, the ‘narcotization-effect’ of technology. Alongside pop culture distraction, we need to hear such specifically philosophical voices post Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, post George Orwell’s 1984. As if anticipating the last three years of global ‘pandemic’, extended in climate change, print and cinematic fantasy, including science, fiction continues to paint a dismal future. Thus Blade Runner (1982) already anticipates the genesis of its own future-dated sequel, Blade Runner 2049 (2017). The ‘bad future’ with its crack in technologically adumbrated promises of utopia is a given, as one critic of popular fiction observed even before the 2011 British sci-fi series, Broken Mirror: ‘Utopian writing has gone dark’ (O’Har Reference O’Har2004: 480).

At issue is less what does utopia mean, how can it be attained, than whether to bother at all? Like digitally-induced impotence, boredom is not the decay of desire but its extinction, Auden’s flatly misogynistic, domestic paradise attained:

Every work-day Eve fares
Forth to the stores her foods to pluck,
While Adam hunts an easy dollar:
Unperspiring at even tide
Both eat their bread in boredom of spirit.
– Auden, City without Walls

Writing utopia, writing about utopia, is typically read as code for writing about something else: socialism perhaps (as in Kateb above) or, eschatologically minded, the after-life and this too is part of political utopic schemes as a sounds like, seems like, danger. This is the difference once again between the ou and eu, to recall the life-and-death-bet Socrates proposes as the last of what he tells his Athenians: none have returned from death with a report confirming or contravening any of the tales told.

As a word, we quoted More’s gloss on ambiguity above, utopia localizes paradise. Thus it has been argued that Judeo-Christian cults derive from archaic visions of Hesiod’s ‘golden age’ and ‘satellite myths of Elysium, Blessed Isles, Fortunate Isles, enchanted gardens’ (Manuel and Manuel Reference Manuel and Manuel1972: 87).Footnote 14 This is significant as references to the mythic are likewise marked as geographic loci. Directionally, as Adolf Schulten emphasizes:

for almost all peoples where the sun sinks down into the sea, one encounters the idea that in the far west, where the sun is extinguished, lies another, better world: the isles of the blest. (Schulten Reference Schulten1926: 229; cf. Frenschkowski Reference Frenschkowski and Jaspert2016)

The problem with a utopia that cannot be attained and not less, this would be Kateb’s point, one that cannot be ensured as ‘good’, even should we approximate to it, is that efforts to do so might lead, so Anders has argued since 1956, to the production of nothing: annihilation. This is compounded by accidental obliteration. What we know of the past, of Greek and Latin antiquity, noted by Erasmus and More and Milton, is incidental, fortuitous. Quoting Kittler quoting Goethe (on how we come to have many of the Pre-Platonic/Pre-Aristotelian ‘fragments’ we have):

Literature, Goethe wrote, is the fragment of fragments; the least of what had happened and of what had been spoken was written down; of what had been written down, only the smallest fraction was preserved. (Kittler Reference Kittler, von Mücke and Similon1987: 105)

In this connection, Anders meditates on the prospect of apocalypse, a Nuclear Armageddon. And now that we can speak of Covid Armageddon or Climate Change Armageddon, the point remains the same (see Babich Reference Babich2023a: Reference Babich2022). Thus, echoing Anders, Kittler’s citation from Goethe’s Wilhelm Meisters Lehrjahre reminds us that everything (even had it been in fact) is and will ‘be’ ‘as if’ it had never been.

I noted above that the Isle of the Blest [Μακάρων νῆσος],Footnote 15 ruled by Rhadamanthus, a locus of judgment and law, are characterized as literally ethereal in Lucian’s atmospheric roster of roses, narcissi and hyacinths, lilies and violets, myrrh and laurel, soft winds and birdsong, an allusion to the Elysian fields (Figure 4). If I also noted that Lucian’s city of gold and emeralds inspired Baum’s Emerald City of Oz, the phantom detail that the inhabitants are clothed in ‘purple spider-webs’ inspires the colors of the science fantasy of Jack Vance’s The Dying Earth:

they have no bodies but are intangible and fleshless, with only shape and figure. Incorporeal as they are, they nevertheless live and move and talk. In a word, it would appear that their naked souls go about in the semblance of their bodies. Really, if one did not touch them, he could not tell that what he saw was not a body, for they are like upright shadows only not black. Nobody grows old, but stays the same age on coming there. (Lucian Reference Harmon1913: 315).

Figure 4. Albert Joseph Moore, The Loves of the Winds and the Seasons (1893) Blackburn Museum, Lancashire, UK. Public Domain.

Violet, ethereal, waited on by winds – cinematically realized in the disembodied servants in Cocteau’s 1946 La Belle et la Bête, – with wine goblets that grow on trees, such is their life, drinking not only wine at table but drinking above all, as Lucian adds, from two springs: ‘Laughter and Enjoyment’. Thus Lucian depicts a phenomenologically telematic vision similar to virtual reality, but physiologically augmented as in Orwell’s 1984 or the dangers of nanotech adjuvants that fall from the sky.

On smell and atmosphere and the spirit

ναυσὶ δ᾽ οὔτε πεζὸς ἰών κεν εὕροις

ἐς Ὑπερβορέων ἀγῶνα θαυματὰν ὁδόν.

– Pindar, 10th Pythian, 29-30

I have been noting that no sooner has the prospect of utopia been described than one already guesses its deficits: ‘nowhere’ is characterized by what is not there. Politically minded thought turns, as in Plato, to remedial praxis. More emphasizes that, beyond ‘words’ but given ‘men and resources and the best laws’ (More Reference More and Malsbary2020: 7), the task will be a matter of drafting a contract for a polity such that goodness might be maintained. The remedial project has many representations. One theorist, largely concerned with fantasy utopias like the ‘Wellsian utopias of science and socialism’ (Kumar Reference Kumar2010: 554) lists additional articulations

in the tradition of social thought that includes such works as Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s Social Contract (1762), Nicolas de Condorcet’s Sketch for a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind (1793), Robert Owen’s A New View of Society (1813), and the works of ‘utopian socialists’. (ibid.: 556)

Here, again, we recall Kateb’s question: would the ‘good life’, seemingly within our technical reach (Kateb does not note that Ellul in his 1954 La Technique ou l’enjeu du siècle elaborates systematically endemic doubts),Footnote 16 actually be ‘good’?

The project of remediation, designing a state of the art but classically political, technological utopia, corrected or updated for projected deficits (think Glaucon and Adeimantus) may itself be the problem. Perfection by design seems to fail before it begins. Thus well mindful of the technical meaning of the contingent, Ivan Illich refuses to offer utopic prescriptions in Tools for Convivality: it ‘would not serve my purpose to describe in detail any fictional community of the future. I want to provide guidelines for action, not for fantasy’ (Illich Reference Illich1975: 27; cf. Gómez Reference Gómez2006, Babich Reference Babich, Mazzini and Glyn-Williams2017). Illich’s caution here contra fantasy or the distractions of fiction (he also warns against the scopic an sich) is perhaps beginning to make sense beyond a romantic projection of ascetic or priestly proscription, given Herbert A. Simon’s ‘attention economy’, since become the competitive basis for business/marketing theory (Wu Reference Wu2016). The more time we spend ‘online’, the more depleted we become: screen-time contracts, along with our acuity, and is lost (Babich Reference Babich2021a; Reference Babich2022). Nor, as in a horror story, do we notice what is lost until too late.

Illich, reflecting in his 1998 Bremen lecture, ‘The Cultivation of Conspiracy’ on the genius loci of his youthful sojourns on the islands around the Dalmatian coastline, Illich confesses the contrastive utopic longing for atmosphere that cannot but accompany age and the depredations of memory. Parodic at his own expense, Illich finds himself walking

through the pastures along the Wümme that are flooded twice a day by the tide from the North Atlantic? I who, as a boy, had felt exiled in Vienna, because all my senses were longingly attached to the South, to the blue Adriatic, to the limestone mountains in the Dalmatia of my early childhood. (2002: 234)

The reference to atmosphere runs throughout his Bremen Peace Prize lecture and Illich recalls his reasons for dissolving the apparently ‘utopic’ institution he founded, his ‘“thinkery” (‘Denkerei’) in Mexico, … the Centro Intercultural de Documentación or CIDOC’:

…. atmosphere invites the institutionalization that will corrupt it. You never know what will nurture the spirit of philia, while you can be certain what will smother it. Spirit emerges by surprise, and it’s a miracle when it abides; it is stifled by every attempt to secure it; it’s debauched when you try to use it. (ibid.: 236)

Illich here writes in praise of friendship, the same friends Nietzsche longed for, the friends Illich’s friends insist Illich had constantly around him. Yet for Illich, the emergence of spirit cannot neither be claimed nor prescribed by law or rule. Once again: it is ‘a miracle when it abides’. If Illich refers to Goethe he has no need to be told that the spirit blows ‘where it will’.

Illich’s reflections on ‘atmosphere’ are offered ‘faute de mieux’:

In Greek, the word is used for the emanation of a star, or for the constellation that governs a place; alchemists adopted it to speak of the layers around our planet. Maurice Blondel reflects its much later French usage for bouquet des esprits, the scent those present contribute to a meeting. I use the word for something frail and often discounted, the air that weaves and wafts and evokes memories, like those attached to the Burgundy long after the bottle has been emptied. (ibid.: 237)

Illich had already remembered his childhood tutor who accompanied his family on holiday, teaching him, chemist by early inclination, how to paint watercolours, ‘how to mix different pigments for the contrasting atmospheres of a Mediterranean and an Atlantic shore’ (ibid.: 234).

For atmospheric aura, Illich tells us, color will not be enough, at stake is breath and smell. Blocking contact with one another as we have now factively done, keeping our distance, wearing masks for weeks, months at a time, is not only bodily avoidance but a spiritual avoidance. Hence where we typically invoke Benjamin to discuss ‘aura’, Illich reminds us that to

sense an aura, you need a nose. The nose, framed by the eyes, runs below the brain. What the nose inhales ends in the guts; every yogi and hesichast knows this…. To savor the feel of a place, you trust your nose; to trust another, you must first smell him. (ibid.: 237)

Illich thus invokes his own Austro-German linguistic sensibilities:

Some of that sense of mimesis comes out in an old German adage, Ich kann Dich gut riechen (I can smell you well), which is still used and understood. But it’s something you don’t say to just anyone; it’s an expression that is permissible only when you feel close, count on trust, and are willing to be hurt. (ibid.)

Here Illich shifts from the sensually indulgent earmark of utopia to the vulnerability of what we are willing to risk and thus to lose for friendship, where possibilities are open-ended, that is, again: ‘when you feel close, count on trust, and are willing to be hurt’.

Illich’s emphasis on intimacy, trust, as on vulnerability is part of the reason Giorgio Agamben argues we might do well to return to Illich during the current political circumstance that is the global change in rule and power, for the sake of supposed ‘security’ (Agamben Reference Agamben and Dani2021). For Illich, the willingness ‘to be hurt’ is a prerequisite for friendship as for Illich’s vocational attention to those who count as ‘the least of our brethren’.

Like Illich, Nietzsche spoke of taste and smell inherent in the word ‘sapio: I taste’ (Reference Nietzsche, Colli and Montinari1980, 1: 816), emphasizing the nose as the most sensitive of our sense organs, quite to the level of the nose hairs (akin to cat vibrissae), capable of sensing volcano explosions at a distance (1980, 9: 548). Thus Nietzsche writes in Twilight of the Idols:

This nose for example, of which as yet no philosopher has spoken with esteem and gratitude is by far the most delicate instrument at our disposal: it is able to detect the smallest differentials in movement which even the spectroscope cannot detect. (1980, 6: 76)

The physiological science of Nietzsche’s day reflected that even a tiny percentage of rose oil in a volume of air ‘1/200000 Mgrm’ may be detected (Vintschgau Reference von Vintschgau and Herman1880: 279), as the perfume industry can confirm (with a corollary, as Vintschgau immediately notes, that most rose oils need contain little ‘actual’ oil).

Smelling the other is not a thing (Illich underlines the point recalling his own prejudices in a missionary context) we suppose ourselves to want, yet, these days, we are beginning to learn the connection between cognitive faculties and olfactory sensitivity.Footnote 17 Thus that we would subject ourselves, as we did and sometimes still do, to the repeated physical invasion of our noses to a degree and on a scale never before encountered, remains difficult to fathom. And that we would have masked ourselves and blocked our breath, likewise.

Towards the end of his Bremen lecture, Illich, a historian, takes his audience back in time:

The medieval town of central Europe was indeed a profoundly new historical gestalt; the conjuratio conspirativa makes European urbanity distinct from urban modes elsewhere. It also implies a peculiar dynamic strain between the atmosphere of conspiratio and its legal, contractual constitution. Ideally, the spiritual climate is the source of the city’s life that flowers into a hierarchy, like a shell or frame, to protect its order. Insofar as the city is understood to originate in a conspiratio, it owes its social existence to the pax, the breath, shared equally among all. (Illich Reference Illich, Hoinacki and Mitcham2002: 242)

This conspiratio, the breath shared together, may be found in Benjamin as hope – along with Bloch and Adorno – the same hope that takes Anders to an attempt that, if predictably unassured, is ‘morally impossible to renounce….’ (Anders Reference Anders1980: 428; cf. Babich Reference Babich2022: 225).

If utopia tends toward ‘totalitarianism’, as we learnt from Huxley and as we live its expression in our day, Illich reminds us of a complex ‘pax’ that cannot be separated from convivial life: that is: ‘the breath, shared equally by all’ (Illich Reference Illich, Hoinacki and Mitcham2002: 242). Here, for Illich, everything will turn on what he calls Umsonstigkeit – utter swerve, clinamen, gratuitous grace.Footnote 18

Footnotes

1 William H. Race translates: ‘And traveling neither by ships nor on foot could you find / the marvelous way to the assembly of the Hyperboreans’ (Pindar Reference Race1997: 361). Hölderlin offers us: ‘In schiffen aberˑ nicht zu füsse wandelnd / möchtest du finden zu der Hyperboreer kampfspiel / Einen wunderbaren weg’ (Pindar 1910: 56).

2 See Branham Reference Branham1989; Ebner et al. Reference Ebner2001, and reading Lucian’s Πῶς δεῖ ἱστορίαν συγγράφειν/De Historia Conscribenda as historiography, Georgiadou and Larmour Reference Georgiadou and Larmour1994; Kirkland Reference Kirkland2022, 186f; and Anderson Reference Anderson1980.

3 This is an established tradition. See, among many others, some to be cited below, Sylvester Reference Sylvester1968; Schoeck Reference Schoeck1978; and, comparing More and Swift, Reilly Reference Rielly1992.

4 See gaming studies by McGonigal Reference McGonigal2011, Bogost Reference Bogost2011, and Bateman Reference Bateman2011 in addition to others like Kłosiński Reference Kłosiński2018, Roth Reference Roth2017, Wagner Reference Wagner2015, as well as, critically, Carr Reference Carr2016.

5 Cf., reading philology as ‘travel narrative’, Gagne Reference Gagné2021: 203-225.

6Kennst du das Land, wo die Zitronen blühn, Im dunkeln Laub die Goldorangen glühn, Ein sanfter Wind vom blauen Himmel weht, Die Myrte still und hoch der Lorbeer steht? Kennst du es wohl? Dahin! Dahin möcht’ ich mit dir, o mein Geliebter, ziehn.’ Cited after Wilhelm Meister’s Lehrjahre (Goethe Reference von Goethe1827: 177). For a discussion, see, broadly, Kolb Reference Kolb2014 and, on the halcyonic, the final chapter of Shapiro’s thus titled Alcyone (Reference Shapiro1991).

7 See overall for a connection with Illich (and Milton and flowers), my ‘Weinberg und Rhythmus: Ivan Illich, Friedrich Nietzsche – und Harry Potter’ in Babich (Reference Babich2021b: 283-314).

8 Here, emphasizing the influence of the Bilderverbot on critical theory, see Benzaquén Reference Benzaquén1998. Cf. Babich Reference Babich, Mazzini and Glyn-Williams2017 and Reference Babich2022.

9 There are many discussions but for a comprehensive and insightful overview, here to note its title: Swift as Nemesis (Boyle Reference Boyle2000) and including a focus on travel literature.

10 ‘“So gäbe es außerhalb dieser Erscheinungsform Welt, die wir kennen, Hoffnung?” – Er lächelte: “Hoffnung genug, unendlich viel Hoffnung, – nur nicht für uns”’. Cited from: Brod (Reference Brod and Krojanker1922: 58). I thank Tracy Strong for the variant formula: Nicht für uns, Max: nicht für uns.

11 Kateb Reference Kateb1965 here cites Schiller’s 24th Letter of On the Aesthetic Education of Man. See too Kateb Reference Kateb1963.

12 Other, more contemporary exceptions include, on the sociological side, the late Stanley Aronowitz in addition to the radically minded Paul Virilio and, more philosophically, Dominique Janicaud and Jean Baudrilliard along with Bruno Latour, and in political theory proper, Gilbert Germaine and Langdon Winner, among not too many others.

13 See for further references, Babich Reference Babich2023a.

14 I am inspired, solely on the periphery by the general reading offered in Ní Chuilleanáin (Reference Chuilleanáin E2007) but the connection is a glancing one as Chuilleanáin is concerned with More and his Latin just where reading Lucian (in Greek), the author is not wrong on this, is salutary quite as More already tells us.

15 See here broadly, Gelinne Reference Gelinne1988 and cf. Joly Reference Joly1956 and Mahn-Lot Reference Mahn-Lot1989.

16 ‘Whenever men have taken utopian descriptions seriously, the result has been disastrous’ (Ellul Reference Ellul and Bundy1976: 24-25). Cf. here too, influential for Ellul, Friedmann 1946 and on Friedmann, instructively, Vatin Reference Vatin2004. For coincident objections, beyond systematic Anglophone inattention, see Donskis Reference Donskis1996.

17 See for a start and for further references: Kostka and Bitzenhofer 2022.

18 I am grateful to Tracy Strong for his engagement with the original draft for this essay, especially for his discussion of Kateb and Auden but also More and Marcuse.

References

Addington, M (2003) Your breath is your worst enemy. In Lightman, A, Sarewitz, D and Desser, C (eds), Living with the Genie: Essays on Technology and the Quest for Human Mastery. Washington, DC: Island Press, 85104.Google Scholar
Agamben, G (2021) Where are We Now? The Epidemic as Politics, Dani, V (trans). London: Eris Press.Google Scholar
Anders, G (1956a) Die Antiquiertheit des Menschen, Bd. I: Über die Seele im Zeitalter der zweiten industriellen Revolution. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
Anders, G (1956b) The world as phantom and matrix. Dissent 3(1), 1424.Google Scholar
Anders, G (1980) Die Antiquiertheit des Menschen, Bd. II: Über die Zerstörung des Lebens im Zeitalter der dritten industriellen Revolution. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
Anders, G (1992) Die molussische Katakombe. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
Anderson, G (1980) Arrian’s “anabasis alexandri” and Lucian’s “historia”. Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 29(1), 119124.Google Scholar
Babich, B (2011) Nietzsche’s Zarathustra and parodic style: On Lucian’s Hyperanthropos and Nietzsche’s Übermensch. Diogenes 58(4), 5874.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babich, B (2013) Nietzsche’s Zarathustra, Nietzsche’s Empedocles: The time of kings. In Hutter, H, and Friedland, E (eds), Nietzsche’s Therapeutic Teaching. For Individuals and Culture. London: Routledge, 157174.Google Scholar
Babich, B (2017) Tools for subversion: Illich and Žižek on changing the world. In Mazzini, S and Glyn-Williams, O (eds), Making Communism Hermeneutical. Frankfurt: Springer, 95111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babich, B (2021a) On necropolitics and techno-scotosis. Philosophy Today 65(2), 305324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babich, B (2021b) Nietzsches Plastik: Ästhetische Phänomenologie im Spiegel des Lebens. Vorträge und Aufsätze. Oxford/Berlin: Peter Lang.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babich, B (2022) Günther Anders’ Philosophy of Technology: From Phenomenology to Critical Theory. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Babich, B (2023a) Gnosticism, political theory and apocalypse: Jacob Taubes and Günther Anders, Tracy Strong and Carl Schmitt. Philosophy & Social Cricicism. doi:10.1177/01914537231203551CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babich, B (2023b) Breath: Technology and built environments. https://www.academia.edu/110229945/Breath_Technology_and_Built_Environments.Google Scholar
Bateman, C (2011) Imaginary Games. Winchester: Zero Books.Google Scholar
Beil, B, Freyermuth, GS and Schmidt, HC (eds) (2019) Playing Utopia: Futures in Digital Games. Bielefeld: Transkript.Google Scholar
Benjamin, W (1969) Theses on the philosophy of history. In Arendt, H (ed), Illuminations. New York, NY: Schocken Books, 257258.Google Scholar
Benzaquén, AS (1998) Thought and Utopia in the writings of Adorno, Horkheimer, and Benjamin. Utopian Studies 9(2), 149161.Google Scholar
Bernis, U (1999) Research on Shugden controversy. Condemned to silence: A Tibetan identity crisis (1996-1999). https://www.dorjeshugden.com/all-articles/the-controversy/condemned-to-silence-part-1/Google Scholar
Bogost, I (2011) How to Do Things with Videogames. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyle, F (2000) Swift as Nemesis: Modernity and its Satirist. Stanford, CA: Stanford UP.Google Scholar
Branham, RB (1989) Unruly Eloquence: Lucian and the Comedy of Traditions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bridgman, TP (2002) Celts and hyperboreans: Crossing mythical boundaries. Proceedings of the Harvard Celtic Colloquium 22, 3955.Google Scholar
Brod, M (1922) Der Dichter Franz Kafka von Max Brod. In Krojanker, G (ed), Juden in der Deutschen Literatur. Essays über zeitgenössische Schriftsteller. Berlin: Welt-Verlag, 5562.Google Scholar
Carr, N (2016) Utopia Is Creepy: And Other Provocations. New York, NY: Norton.Google Scholar
Church, AJ (1880) A Traveller’s True Tale, After the Greek of Lucian of Samosata. New York, NY: Scribner and Welford.Google Scholar
Corbusier, L (1930) Précisions sur un état présent de l’architecture et de l’urbanisme. Paris: Crès.Google Scholar
de Jouvenal, B (1965) Utopia for practical purposes. In Manuel, FE (ed), Utopias and Utopian Thought. Boston: Beacon Press, 219238.Google Scholar
Didi-Huberman, G (2019) Ninfa fluida (a post-scriptum). In Debenedetti, A and Elam, C (eds), Botticelli Past and Present. London: UCL Press, 237265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donskis, L (1996) The end of Utopia. Soundings: An Interdisciplinary Journal 79(1/2), 197219.Google Scholar
Ebner, M, et al. (2001) Lukian: Die Lügenfreunde oder Der Ungläubige. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Ellul, J (1976) Search for an image. In Bundy, R (ed), Images of the Future. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 2425.Google Scholar
Frenschkowski, M (2016) Fortunatae Insulae: Die Identifikation mythischer Inseln mit realen geographischen Gegebenheiten in der griechischen und römischen Antike. In Jaspert, N et al. (ed), Konstruktionen mediterraner Insularitäten. Amsterdam: Brill, 4373.Google Scholar
Friedmann, G (1956) Problèmes humains du machinisme industriel. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Gagné, R (2021) Cosmography and the Idea of Hyperborea in Ancient Greece: A Philology of Worlds. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelinne, M (1988) Les Champs-Elysées et les îles des Bienheureux chez Homère, Hésiode et Pindare. Les Études Classiques 56(4), 225240.Google Scholar
Georgiadou, A and Larmour, DHJ (1994) Lucian and historiography: “De Historia Conscribenda” and “Verae Historiae”. ANRW II.34.2, 14481509.Google Scholar
Gómez, MS (2006) Sociedad, Utopía y Educación en Ivan Illich. Psicologia USP 17(3), 183201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hadot, P (1992) La Citadelle intérieure. Introduction aux Pensées de Marc Aurèle. Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
Hadot, P (2008) N’oublie pas de vivre. Goethe et la tradition des exercices spirituels. Paris: Albin Michel.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M (1975) The Anaximander fragment. In Krell, D, and Capuzzi, F (trans), Early Greek Thinking. New York, NY: Harper & Row, 1358.Google Scholar
Howard, RE (1950) Conan the Conqueror. New York, NY: Gnome Press.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, S (1987) Mapping Utopias. Modern Philology 85(2), 170185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Illich, I (1973) Tools for Conviviality. London: Calder and Boyars.Google Scholar
Illich, I (1985) H20 and the Waters of Forgetfulness. Reflections on the Historicity of ‘Stuff’. Dallas, TX: Dallas Institute of Humanities and Culture.Google Scholar
Illich, I (2002) The cultivation of conspiracy. In Hoinacki, L and Mitcham, C (eds), The Challenges of Ivan Illich: A Collective Reflection. Albany: SUNY Press, 233242.Google Scholar
Joly, R (1956) Vie idéale et apothéose philosophique. L’Antiquité Classique 25(1), 7384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jonas, H (1981) Reflections on technology, progress, and Utopia. Social Research 48(3), 411455.Google Scholar
Kateb, G (1963) Utopia and Its Enemies. New York, NY: Free Press of Glencoe.Google Scholar
Kateb, G (1965) Utopia and the good life. Daedalus 94(2), 454473.Google Scholar
Kirkland, NB (2022) Herodotus and Imperial Greek Literature: Criticism, Imitation, Reception. New York, NY: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kissinger, H (2015) World Order: Reflections on the Character of Nations and the Course of History. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Kittler, F, von Mücke, D and Similon, PL (1987) Gramophone, film, typewriter. October 41, 101118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kłosiński, M (2018) Games and Utopia. Acta Ludologica 1(1), 414.Google Scholar
Kolb, M (2014) Goethe’s citrus, Nietzsche’s figs, and Benn’s olive: Poetic reverie, erotic fantasy, and botanic agency. Monatshefte 106(2), 171199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumar, K (2010) The ends of Utopia. New Literary History 41(3), 549569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lucian (1913) A true story. In Harmon, AM (trans), Lucian, v. I. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 247358.Google Scholar
Lucian (1915) The downward journey or The Tyrant. In Harmon, AM (trans), Lucian, v. II. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 158.Google Scholar
Lucian (1915) Icaromenippus or the sky man. In Harmon, AM (trans), Lucian, v. II. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 267324.Google Scholar
Mahn-Lot, M (1989) Île des Bienheureux et Paradis terrestre. Revue Historique 281(1), 4750.Google Scholar
Manuel, FE and Manuel, FP (1972) Sketch for a natural history of paradise. Daedalus 101(1), 83128.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H (1964) One-Dimensional Man. Boston, MA: Beacon.Google Scholar
McGonigal, J (2011) Reality is Broken: Why Games Make Us Better and How They Can Change the World. New York, NY: Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Milton, J (1667) Paradise Lost: A Poem Written in Ten Books. London: Samuel Simmons.Google Scholar
More, T (1965) Utopia. In Surtz, E and Hexter, JH (eds), The Complete Works of St. Thomas More, Vol. 4. New Haven, CT: Yale UP.Google Scholar
More, T (2020) Utopia & Selected Epigrams, Malsbary, G (trans). Dallas: University of Dallas Press.Google Scholar
Chuilleanáin E, (2007) Motives of translation: More, Erasmus and Lucian. Hermathena 183, 4962.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F (1980) Sämtliche Werke, Colli, G and Montinari, M (eds). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
O’Har, G (2004) Technology and its discontent. Technology and Culture 45(2), 479485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paquot, T (2005) City and nature, a missed opportunity? Diogenes 52(3), 6574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pindar (1910) Hölderlins Pindar-Übertragungen. Berlin: Blätter für die Kunst.Google Scholar
Pindar (1997) Olympian Odes. Pythian Odes, Race, WH (trans). Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
Richards, T (1992) Archive and Utopia. Representations 37, 104135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rielly, EJ (1992) Irony in gulliver’s travels and Utopia. Utopian Studies 3(1), 7083.Google Scholar
Rohde, E (1894) Psyche. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Roth, M (2017) Thought-Provoking Play: Political Philosophies in Science Fictional Videogame Spaces from Japan. Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Mellon University, ETC Press.Google Scholar
Schoeck, RJ (1978) The ironic and the prophetic: Towards reading More’s “Utopia” as a multidisciplinary work. Albion: A Quarterly Journal Concerned with British Studies 10, 124134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schulten, A (1926) Die Inseln der Seligen. Geographische Zeitschrift 32(5), 229247.Google Scholar
Shapiro, G (1991) Alcyone: Nietzsche on Gifts, Noise, and Women. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Sobin, H (1996) From l’Air Exact to l’Aérateur: Ventilation and its evolution in the architectural work of Le Corbusier. In Kinnard, J and Schwartz, K (eds), Proceedings of the 84th ACSA Annual Meeting, 220227Google Scholar
Suvin, D (1972) On the poetics of the science fiction genre. College English 34(13), 372382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suvin, D (2010) Defined by a Hollow: Essays on Utopia, Science Fiction and Political Epistemology. New York, NY: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Sylvester, RS (1968) Si Hythlodaeo Credimus”: Vision and revision in Thomas More’s “Utopia”. Soundings 52(3), 272289.Google Scholar
Vatin, F (2004) Machinisme, marxisme, humanisme: Georges Friedmann avant et après-guerre. Sociologie du travail 46(2), 205223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Goethe, JW (1827) Goethe’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe letzter Hand, Erster Band. Stuttgart & Tübingen: J.G.Cotta’schen.Google Scholar
von Vintschgau, M (1880) Physiologie des Geschmacksinns und des Geruchsinns. In Herman, L (ed), Handbuch der Physiologie, Vol. 3. Leipzig: F.C.W. Vogel, 145288.Google Scholar
Wagner, R (2015) Video games and religion. In Oxford Handbook Topics in Religion.Google Scholar
Welcker, F (1833) Die homerischen Phäaken und die Insel der Seligen. Rheinisches Museum für Philologie 1, 219283.Google Scholar
Wu, T (2016) The Attention Merchants: The Epic Scramble to Get Inside Our Heads. New York, NY: Knopf.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Map of Utopia in More’s 1516 edition.

Figure 1

Figure 2. Maxfield Parrish, Dream Castle in the Sky, 1908. Public Domain.

Figure 2

Figure 3. Peter Paul Rubens, Juno’s Deception, 1620-1624. Print. British Museum.

Figure 3

Figure 4. Albert Joseph Moore, The Loves of the Winds and the Seasons (1893) Blackburn Museum, Lancashire, UK. Public Domain.

A correction has been issued for this article: