1. Introduction
Throughout this paper, G always denotes a finite group. As usual,
$\mathrm {Irr}(G)$
denotes the set of complex irreducible characters of G and
$\mathrm {cd}(G)=\{\chi (1)\mid \chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)\}$
the set of character degrees. A number of papers, such as [Reference Isaacs and Passman5–Reference Lewis7], have studied the influence of the set
$\mathrm {cd}(G)$
on the structure of
$G.$
In particular, Huppert in [Reference Huppert3, Theorem 32.1] considered finite groups whose irreducible character degrees are consecutive integers and showed that if
$\mathrm {cd}(G)=\{1,2,\ldots , k-1, k\},$
then G is solvable if and only if
$k\leqslant 4,$
and that if
$k>4,$
then
$k=6$
and
$G=HZ(G),$
where
$H\cong \mathrm {SL}(2,5).$
Inspired by these results, we consider the analogous problem related to the character codegrees. The concept of character codegrees was first introduced by Qian et al. in [Reference Qian, Wang and Wei9] as follows. For
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G),$
the codegree of
$\chi $
is defined to be

Recently many papers have studied character codegrees (see, for instance, [Reference Isaacs4, Reference Lewis and Yan8, Reference Yang and Qian10]). Let
$\mathrm {Cod}(G)=\{\mathrm {cod}\,\chi \mid \chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)\}$
be the set of irreducible character codegrees of
$G.$
The aim of this paper is to investigate finite groups whose irreducible character codegrees are consecutive integers. We have the following result.
Theorem 1.1. Let G be a group with
$\mathrm {Cod}(G)=\{1,2,\ldots , n-1, n\},$
where n is a positive integer. Then
$n\leqslant 3$
and one of the following holds:
-
(1) if
$n=1,$ then
$G=1$ ;
-
(2) if
$n=2,$ then G is an elementary abelian
$2$ -group;
-
(3) if
$n=3,$ then
$G=N\rtimes H$ is a Frobenius group with an elementary abelian
$3$ -group as its kernel,
$N=G'$ and H is cyclic of order
$2.$
2. Preliminaries
We begin with the following basic lemma concerning character codegrees, which will be used frequently in our proofs.
Lemma 2.1 [Reference Qian, Wang and Wei9, Lemma 2.1].
Let G be a group and
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G).$
-
(1) If N is a normal subgroup of
$G,$ then
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N) \subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(G).$
-
(2) If N is subnormal in G and
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$ is a constituent of
$\chi _N,$ then
$\mathrm {cod}\,\phi \mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi .$
Next we recall the concept of the codegree graph, which was first introduced in [Reference Qian, Wang and Wei9]. The codegree graph
$\Gamma (G)$
is a graph whose vertex set
$V(G)$
is the set of all primes dividing
$\mathrm {cod}\,\chi $
for some
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)$
and there is an edge between two distinct primes p and q if
$pq$
divides
$\mathrm {cod}\,\chi $
for some
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G).$
We present the following facts on the codegree graph
$\Gamma (G).$
Lemma 2.2 [Reference Qian, Wang and Wei9, Theorems A and E].
Let G be a group and
$\pi (G)$
be the set of prime divisors of
$|G|.$
-
(1)
$\pi (G)$ coincides with
$V(G),$ the vertex set of
$\Gamma (G).$
-
(2) For any subset
$\Delta \subseteq \pi (G)$ with
$|\Delta |\geqslant 3,$ there are two distinct primes
$p,q\in \Delta $ so that there is an edge between p and
$q.$
-
(3)
$\Gamma (G)$ is not connected if and only if G is a Frobenius group or a
$2$ -Frobenius group.
3. Proof of Theorem 1.1
We start by proving the following result concerning number theory, which plays a very important role in determining the integer n when
$\mathrm { Cod}(G)=\{1,2,\ldots , n-1, n\}.$
Proposition 3.1. Let n be an integer and
$r,q,p$
be three consecutive primes so that
$2<r<q<p\leqslant n$
and p is the largest prime less than or equal to
$n.$
Then
$n<2p$
and
$n<rq.$
Proof. Assume that
$n\geqslant 2p.$
Then
$p<2p\leqslant n.$
By Bertrand’s postulate, there exists a prime, say
$s,$
so that
$p<s<2p.$
This contradicts the hypothesis that p is the largest prime less than or equal to
$n.$
Hence,
$n<2p.$
Now assume that
$n\geqslant rq.$
Applying Bertrand’s postulate again, we see that
${q<p<2q}$
and so
$q<p<2q<3q\leqslant rq\leqslant n.$
By [Reference El Bachraoui1, Theorem 1.3], there is a prime between
$2q$
and
$3q.$
This is a contradiction. Thus,
$n<rq.$
Proposition 3.1 enables us show that the integer n will not be too large.
Proposition 3.2. Let G be a group with
$\mathrm {Cod}(G)=\{1,2,\ldots , n-1, n\},$
where n is a positive integer. Then
$n\leqslant 6$
and
$n\not =5.$
Proof. Assume that
$n\geqslant 7.$
Then there are three consecutive primes
$r,q,p$
as defined in Proposition 3.1. Thus,
$n<2p$
and
$n<rq.$
Consider the subset
$\Delta =\{r,p,q\}\subseteq V(G)=\pi (G).$
By Lemma 2.2(2), there exists
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)$
so that
$pq\mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi $
,
$rq\mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi $
or
$rp\mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi .$
It follows from Proposition 3.1 that
$n\geqslant \mathrm { cod}\,\chi \geqslant \min \{pq,rq,rp\}>n.$
This is a contradiction. Thus,
$n\leqslant 6.$
Similarly, by Lemma 2.2(2),
$n\not = 5.$
With the above proposition, to prove Theorem 1.1, we only need to classify the groups when
$1\leqslant n\leqslant 3$
and show that
$n\not =4,6.$
Notice that if
$n\leqslant 6$
, the codegree graph
$\Gamma (G)$
is not connected. Then by Lemma 2.2(3), G is a Frobenius group or a 2-Frobenius group. So we need to understand the structure of Frobenius groups. In particular, we give the following proposition.
Proposition 3.3. Let
$G=N\rtimes H$
be a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
Suppose that
$\pi (N)=\{p_1, p_2,\ldots ,p_s\}.$
Then the following statements hold.
-
(1) If
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N),$ then
$\mathrm {cod}\,\phi \mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi $ for some
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G).$ In particular,
$\prod _{i=1}^{s}p_i\mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi $ for some
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G).$
-
(2)
$\mathrm {Cod}(G){\kern-0.5pt}={\kern-0.5pt}\mathrm {Cod}(G/N)\bigcup \{\mathrm {cod}(\phi ^G)\mid 1_N{\kern-0.5pt}\not ={\kern-0.5pt}\phi {\kern-0.5pt}\in{\kern-0.5pt} \mathrm {Irr}(N)\}.$ Furthermore,
$\mathrm {cod}(\phi ^G)$ divides
$|N|$ if
$1_N\not =\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N).$
Proof. (1) The first part follows from Lemma 2.1(2) immediately. Notice that N is nilpotent. Then
$N=P_1\times P_2\times \cdots \times P_s,$
where
$P_i$
is a Sylow
$p_i$
-subgroup of
$N.$
Let
$1_{P_i}\not =\lambda _i\in \mathrm {Irr}(P_i)$
and set
$\phi =\lambda _1\times \lambda _2\times \cdots \times \lambda _s.$
Then
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$
and
$ \mathrm {cod}\,\phi =\prod _{i=1}^{s}\mathrm {cod}\,\lambda _i$
with
$p_i\mid \mathrm { cod}\,\lambda _i.$
Hence, by Lemma 2.1(2),
$ \prod _{i=1}^{s}p_i\mid \mathrm {cod}\,\chi $
for some
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G),$
as required.
(2) It is well known that
$\mathrm {Irr}(G)=\mathrm {Irr}(G/N)\bigcup \{\phi ^G\mid 1_N\not =\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)\}.$
Thus, the first part is true. Notice that
$\phi ^G(1)=|G:N|\phi (1).$
Then

divides
$|N|,$
as required.
Proposition 3.4. Let G be a group with
$|\pi (G)|=3.$
Suppose that
$\mathrm {Cod}(G)\subseteq \{1,2,3,4,5,6\}.$
Then G is not a Frobenius group.
Proof. We work by contradiction. Assume that
$G=N\rtimes H$
is a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
By Lemma 2.2(1) and (2),
$\pi (G)=\{2,3,5\}$
and
$6\in \mathrm {Cod}(G).$
First we consider the case when
$|\pi (N)|=2.$
Since N is nilpotent, it follows from Proposition 3.3(1) that
$\pi (N)=\{2,3\}$
and N is a direct product of an elementary abelian 2-group and an elementary abelian 3-group. Notice that the complement H is a cyclic 5-group and
$\mathrm {Cod}(H)\subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(G).$
Then H must be cyclic of order 5. Since there is
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$
so that
$\mathrm {cod}(\phi ^G)=|N|/|\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G|=6,$
we have
$\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G<N$
and so
$G/\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G=N/\mathrm { ker}\phi ^G\rtimes H\mathrm {ker}\phi ^G/\mathrm {ker}\phi ^G\cong C_6\rtimes C_5\cong C_{30}.$
Hence,
$30\in \mathrm {Cod}(G),$
a contradiction.
Assume now that
$|\pi (N)|=1.$
By Proposition 3.3(2),
$\pi (N)=\{5\}$
and so N is elementary abelian. Since there is
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$
so that
$\mathrm {cod}(\phi ^G)=|N|/|\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G|=5,$
we have
$\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G<N.$
Let
$\overline {G}=G/\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G.$
Then
$\overline {G}=\overline {N}\rtimes \overline {H}$
is a Frobenius group with kernel
$\overline {N}\cong C_5$
and
$\overline {H}\cong H$
. Let
$\overline {Q}$
be a Sylow 3-subgroup of
$\overline {H}.$
Then
$\overline {Q}$
is cyclic of order 3. It follows that
$\overline {N}\overline {Q}$
is a Frobenius group of order 15. This is a contradiction since such a group does not exist.
Both cases are impossible. The proof is completed.
For convenience, here we introduce the notation of 2-Frobenius groups. If G is a 2-Frobenius group, then there are normal subgroups
$N, M$
of G so that
$G/N$
is a Frobenius group with kernel
$M/N$
, and M is a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
We write
$G=\mathrm {Frob}_2(G,M,N)$
to denote such a 2-Frobenius group.
Proof of Theorem 1.1.
We first introduce two basic facts.
-
(A)
$\mathrm {cod}\,\chi> \chi (1)$ if
$1_{G}\not = \chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)$ .
-
(B) If G is abelian, then
$\mathrm {cod}\,\chi $ is equal to the order of
$\chi $ in the group
$\mathrm {Irr}(G)\cong G.$
There is nothing to prove when
$n=1.$
Assume that
$n\geqslant 2.$
Applying fact (A), together with
$2\in \mathrm {Cod}(G),$
we see that there exists a linear character
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G)$
such that
$\mathrm {cod}\,\chi =2$
and hence
$\chi \in \mathrm {Irr}(G/G').$
Then it follows from fact (B) that
$2\mid |G:G'|.$
If
$n=2,$
then by facts (A) and (B), G is an elementary abelian
$2$
-group and (2) follows.
Assume that
$n=3.$
Then by Lemma 2.2(1) and (3),
$\pi (G)=\{2,3\}$
and G is a Frobenius group or a 2-Frobenius group. First suppose that
$G=N\rtimes H$
is a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
Since
$2\mid |G:G'|,$
it follows that H is a 2-group and N is a 3-group. By Proposition 3.3,
$\mathrm {Cod}(N)=\{1,3\}$
and
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N)=\mathrm {Cod}(H)=\{1,2\}.$
Therefore, N is an elementary abelian 3-group and H is an elementary abelian 2-group. Notice that the complement H must be cyclic or a generalised quaternion group (see [Reference Grove2, Theorem 9.2.10]). Hence, H is cyclic of order 2. Since
$6\not \in \mathrm { Cod}(G),$
we have
$G'=N.$
To complete the proof of (3), we only need to show that G is not a 2-Frobenius group. Assume that
$G=\mathrm {Frob}_2(G,M,N)$
is a 2-Frobenius group. It follows from Proposition 3.3 that
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N)=\mathrm {Cod}(M)=\{1,2,3\}.$
Similarly,
$G/N\cong C_3^s\rtimes C_2$
and
$M\cong C_3^t\rtimes C_2$
for some positive integers s and
$t.$
This is a contradiction. Hence, (3) follows.
Now we show that
$n\not =4.$
If
$n=4,$
then
$\pi (G)=\{2,3\}$
and G is a Frobenius group or a 2-Frobenius group. First assume that
$G=N\rtimes H$
is a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
Then by a proof similar to that above, N is an elementary abelian 3-group and H is a 2-group with
$\mathrm {Cod}(H)=\{1,2,4\}.$
Together with the fact that the complement H must be cyclic or a generalised quaternion group, we have
$H\cong C_4$
or
$Q_8.$
Notice that there exists
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$
so that
$\mathrm {cod}(\phi ^G)=|N|/|\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G|=3.$
It is obvious that
$\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G<N.$
Then
$G/\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G=N/\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G\rtimes H\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G/\mathrm {ker}\,\phi ^G\cong C_3\rtimes C_4$
or
$C_3\rtimes Q_8$
is a Frobenius group, which is a contradiction. Thus, G cannot be a Frobenius group. Assume that
$G=\mathrm {Frob}_2(G,M,N)$
is a 2-Frobenius group. Since
$G/N$
is Frobenius and
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N) \subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(G),$
we have
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N)=\{1,2,3\}.$
Similarly,
$\mathrm {Cod}(M)=\{1,2,3\}.$
This cannot happen by statement (2) of this theorem. Hence,
$n\not =4.$
By Proposition 3.2, it remains to show that
$n\not =6.$
If
$n=6,$
then
$\pi (G)=\{2,3,5\}$
and G is a Frobenius group or a 2-Frobenius group. It follows by Proposition 3.4 that G is not a Frobenius group. We may assume that
$G=\mathrm {Frob}_2(G,M,N)$
is a 2-Frobenius group. By Proposition 3.3(1) and (2),
$\mathrm {Cod}(G/N) \subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(G)$
and
$\mathrm {Cod}(M/N) \subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(M) \subseteq \mathrm { Cod}(G).$
Since both
$G/N$
and M are Frobenius groups, it follows by Proposition 3.4 that
$|\pi (G/N)|=|\pi (M)|=2.$
Write
$\overline {G}=G/N$
and then
$\overline {G}=\overline {M}\rtimes \overline {K},$
where
$\overline {K}$
is the Frobenius complement. First consider the case when
$\pi (\overline {K})\not =\{2\}.$
As
$\overline {K}$
is cyclic and
$\mathrm {Cod}(\overline {K}) \subseteq \mathrm {Cod}(G),$
we have
$G'\leqslant M$
and
$\overline {K}$
is cyclic of order 3 or 5. Notice that
$2\mid |G:G'|.$
Then
$\overline {K}\cong C_3$
and
$\overline {M}$
is a 2-group. Since M is Frobenius and
$\overline {M}$
is isomorphic to its complement, it follows that
$\overline {M}$
is cyclic or a generalised quaternion group and hence
$\overline {M}\cong C_2, C_4$
or
$Q_8.$
But
$\overline {G}\cong \overline {M}\rtimes C_3$
is Frobenius, which is impossible. Assume now that
$\pi (\overline {K})=\{2\}.$
It is obvious that
$\pi (M)=\{3,5\}.$
Let
$M=N\rtimes H$
be a Frobenius group with kernel
$N.$
By a similar proof, there exists
$\phi \in \mathrm {Irr}(N)$
so that
$G/\mathrm { ker}\phi ^G\cong N/\mathrm {ker}\phi ^G\rtimes H\cong C_{15}.$
It follows that
$15\in \mathrm {Cod}(G),$
a contradiction. Hence,
$n\not =6.$
The proof is completed.