Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T11:22:31.701Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

AGAINST CUMULATIVE TYPE THEORY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2021

TIM BUTTON
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON LONDON, UK E-mail: [email protected]
ROBERT TRUEMAN
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF YORK YORK, UK E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Standard Type Theory, ${\textrm {STT}}$, tells us that $b^n(a^m)$ is well-formed iff $n=m+1$. However, Linnebo and Rayo [23] have advocated the use of Cumulative Type Theory, $\textrm {CTT}$, which has more relaxed type-restrictions: according to $\textrm {CTT}$, $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta>\alpha $. In this paper, we set ourselves against $\textrm {CTT}$. We begin our case by arguing against Linnebo and Rayo’s claim that $\textrm {CTT}$ sheds new philosophical light on set theory. We then argue that, while $\textrm {CTT}$’s type-restrictions are unjustifiable, the type-restrictions imposed by ${\textrm {STT}}$ are justified by a Fregean semantics. What is more, this Fregean semantics provides us with a principled way to resist Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument for $\textrm {CTT}$. We end by examining an alternative approach to cumulative types due to Florio and Jones [10]; we argue that their theory is best seen as a misleadingly formulated version of ${\textrm {STT}}$.

MSC classification

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Standard Type Theory, ${\textrm {STT}}$ , tells us that $b^n(a^m)$ is well-formed iff $n=m+1$ . However, Linnebo and Rayo Reference Linnebo and Rayo[23] have advocated the use of Cumulative Type Theory, $\textrm {CTT}$ , which has more relaxed type-restrictions: according to $\textrm {CTT}$ , $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta>\alpha $ . Other philosophers, including Williamson [Reference Williamson44, pp. 237–238], Krämer [Reference Krämer21, p. 527], and Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10], have since expressed sympathy for cumulative types.

We set ourselves against cumulative type theory. We begin our case by arguing against Linnebo and Rayo’s claim that $\textrm {CTT}$ sheds new philosophical light on set theory: in Section 2 we highlight some important mathematical differences between $\textrm {CTT}$ and set theory, and in Section 3 we explore the philosophical consequences of these differences. Then, in Section 4, we push our case against $\textrm {CTT}$ further, by arguing that the type-restrictions it imposes are unjustifiable. This marks an important difference between $\textrm {CTT}$ and ${\textrm {STT}}$ : a Fregean semantics justifies ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions (see Section 5), and this Fregean semantics also provides us with a principled way to resist Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument for $\textrm {CTT}$ (see Section 6). We end, in Section 7, by examining an alternative approach to cumulative types due to Florio and Jones Reference Florio and Jones[10]; we argue that their theory is best seen as a misleadingly formulated version of ${\textrm {STT}}$ .

1 Formal type theories

We start by outlining the formalisms of ${\textrm {STT}}$ and $\textrm {CTT}$ . For simplicity of exposition, in this paper we focus on monadic type theories. (We also only consider un-ramified type theories.)

1.1 ${\textrm {STT}}$

${\textrm {STT}}$ has a countable infinity of types, $0 \leq n < \omega $ . The type of a term is indicated with a numerical superscript: $a^n$ is a type n term. We have constants and variables of every type. Atomic formulas are made by combining a type $n\mathord {+}1$ term with a type n term: $b^n(a^m)$ is well-formed iff $n = m + 1$ . Intuitively, $b^{n+1}(a^n)$ applies a type $n\mathord {+}1$ entity to a type n entity, where an entity is of type n iff it is a value of a type n variable; however, exactly what this intuitive gloss amounts to will depend on your preferred interpretation of the types (see Sections 4 and 5).

Every type of variable can be bound by quantifiers. We here present the rules for $\forall $ ; the rules for $\exists $ are the obvious duals. For all types n, the following inferences are licensed, provided that (i) all expressions are well-formed and (ii) $b^n$ does not occur in any undischarged assumptions on which $\phi (b^n)$ depends:

To ensure that each level of the type hierarchy is well-populated, we have the following scheme, for each type n:

  1. ${{STT}}$ -Comprehension. $\exists z^{n+1}\forall x^n(z^{n+1}(x^n)\leftrightarrow \phi (x^n))$ , whenever $\phi (x^n)$ is well-formed and does not contain $z^{n+1}$ .

${\textrm {STT}}$ has the usual stock of logical devices: quantifiers, connectives, and the identity sign, $=$ . The identity sign can be flanked by a pair of terms of any type, but they must be terms of the same type; so $a^m=b^n$ is well-formed iff $m=n$ . Identity is governed by the following scheme, for each type n:

$$ \begin{align*}x^n=y^n \mbox{ iff}\ \forall z^{n+1}(z^{n+1}(x^n)\leftrightarrow z^{n+1}(y^n)).\end{align*} $$

We can treat this as an axiom scheme or an explicit definition. But, either way, $x^n=y^n$ is typically ambiguous: there is not a single identity relation that applies across all the types, but a different relation for each type.

1.2 $\textrm {CTT}$

Linnebo and Rayo Reference Linnebo and Rayo[23] ask us to consider an alternative, cumulative, type theory, $\textrm {CTT}$ . This type theory was formally developed by Degen and Johannsen Reference Degen and Johannsen[7]. (We discuss a different approach to cumulation, due to Florio and Jones Reference Florio and Jones[10], in Section 7.) The basic thought behind $\textrm {CTT}$ is that the entities cumulate as you ascend through the types. Let us see how this is implemented.

First, $\textrm {CTT}$ relaxes ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s syntax. In ${\textrm {STT}}$ , $b^n(a^m)$ is well-formed iff $n = m +1$ . But, if the types cumulate, then everything at level $0$ reappears at level $1$ ; so, since $c^2(a^1)$ is meaningful, $c^2(a^0)$ should be too. More generally, $\textrm {CTT}$ allows that $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta> \alpha $ . And note that we use ‘ $\alpha $ ’ and ‘ $\beta $ ’ rather than ‘n’ and ‘m’ here: if the types cumulate, we will want to be able to consider transfinite types, and so we must allow ourselves a transfinite stock of type-indices. (One obvious way to do this is to stipulate that the type-indices are von Neumann’s ordinals, but the only important constraint is that the type-indices be well-ordered.)Footnote 1

Second, $\textrm {CTT}$ has rather permissive inference rules for quantifiers. (Again, we only outline the rules for $\forall $ .) For all types $\beta \geq \alpha $ , the following inferences are licensed, provided that (i) all expressions are well-formed and (ii) $b^\beta $ does not occur in any undischarged assumption on which $\phi (b^\beta )$ depends:Footnote 2

These rules are intuitively sound, given the idea of cumulation: every type $\alpha $ entity is a type $\beta \geq \alpha $ entity too; so if $\phi $ holds of every type $\beta $ entity, then $\phi $ holds of each type $\alpha $ entity.

Third, to ensure that each successor-level of the type hierarchy is well-populated, $\textrm {CTT}$ has a Comprehension scheme, for each type $\alpha $ :Footnote 3

  • ${CTT}$ -Comprehension. $\exists z^{\alpha +1}\forall x^\alpha (z^{\alpha +1}(x^\alpha )\leftrightarrow \phi (x^\alpha ))$ , whenever $\phi (x^\alpha )$ is well-formed and does not contain $z^{\alpha +1}$ .

Fourth, $\textrm {CTT}$ has an infinitary inference rule for each limit type $\lambda $ :Footnote 4

Intuitively, this guarantees that nothing essentially ‘new’ happens at limit types, so that any type $\lambda $ entity is an entity of some type $\alpha < \lambda $ .

So far, we have identified entities across types quite freely. However, Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 281–283] retain the rule that a strict identity claim, $x^\alpha =y^\beta $ , is well-formed iff $\alpha =\beta $ . To deal with cross-type identity, they explicitly define a new sign, $\mathrel {\equiv }$ , for any types $\alpha $ and $\beta $ and where $\gamma = \max (\alpha , \beta )+1$ :Footnote 5

$$ \begin{align*} a^\alpha \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} \forall x^{\gamma}(x^{\gamma}(a^\alpha) \leftrightarrow x^\gamma(b^\beta)). \end{align*} $$

This definition is typically ambiguous: it defines different relations for different $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . But all of these relations behave like identity: if $\phi (a^\alpha )$ and $\phi (b^\beta )$ are both well-formed, then $\phi (a^\alpha )$ and $a^\alpha \equiv b^\beta $ together entail $\phi (b^\beta )$ .Footnote 6 Now we can prove the following theorem scheme, for all $\alpha \leq \beta $ :Footnote 7

  • Type-Raising Scheme. $\forall x^\alpha \exists y^\beta \phantom {(}x^\alpha \equiv y^\beta $

So, if $\alpha \leq \beta $ , then every type $\alpha $ entity is a type $\beta $ entity, in the sense of ‘is’ expressed by $\mathrel {\equiv }$ .

We also provide another (typically ambiguous) explicit definition, where $\gamma = \max (\alpha , \beta )+1$ :Footnote 8

$$ \begin{align*} a^\alpha \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^\beta & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} (\exists x^{\gamma} \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta)x^{\gamma}(a^\alpha). \end{align*} $$

This membership-like notion applies $b^\beta $ to $a^\alpha $ , but is well-formed for every $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . So $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ allows us to simulate $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ , even when $\alpha \geq \beta $ .

If we provide no further axioms, though, then $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ can be ill-founded. To rule this out, we lay down two final schemes, for all $\alpha , \beta $ :Footnote 9

  • Type-Founded. $\forall a^\alpha \forall b^{\beta +1}(a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{\beta +1} \rightarrow \exists x^\beta \ a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } x^\beta )$

  • Type-Base.

This completes the list of axioms and inference rules for $\textrm {CTT}$ .

It is worth making a brief observation about syntax. In moving from ${\textrm {STT}}$ to $\textrm {CTT}$ , we are asked to relax ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s syntax: $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta> \alpha $ . There is an obvious way to relax this further, whilst retaining a typed theory: allow that $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed for any $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . However, this further relaxation would have no real effect. As just noted, $\textrm {CTT}$ can simulate $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ using the formula $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ , where the latter is defined using the more stringent type-restrictions. Consequently, we can be largely indifferent on whether to use the stringent type-restrictions, so that $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta> \alpha $ , or the more liberal type-restrictions, so that $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed for any $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . In what follows, we will tend to adopt the stringent type-restrictions, but we will revisit this in Section 4.

For each type-index $\tau $ , the theory ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ has a countable infinity of distinct variables of every type $< \tau $ , and no variables of any type $\geq \tau $ . We refer to the cumulative type theories in general as ‘ $\textrm {CTT}$ ’, using ‘ ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ ’ with the superscript when it is important to pay attention to the bound.

2 The sets-from-types theorem

Degen and Johannsen Reference Degen and Johannsen[7] and Linnebo and Rayo Reference Linnebo and Rayo[23] note that $\textrm {CTT}$ interprets an iterative set theory. In this section, we present a strengthened version of their formal results. We discuss its philosophical significance in Section 3. For ease of exposition, we will consider set theories without urelements (and similar type theories); we could accommodate urelements if we liked, but it would complicate our discussion without adding any real insight.

2.1 The interpretation

We will focus on a ‘pure’ version of ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ , which we call ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . This augments ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ with principles guaranteeing that there is exactly one type $0$ entity, and that coextensive entities at higher-types are identical. (For details, see Appendix B.2.) The set theory that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ can interpret is ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , i.e., Zermelo set theory together with the principle that the sets are arranged into well-ordered ranks. This theory omits Replacement, and so is strictly weaker than ${\textrm {ZF}}$ . (For more details, see Appendix B; note that ${\textrm {ZF}}$ = ${\textrm {Zr}}$ + Replacement.)

To interpret ${\textrm {Zr}}$ with ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ , we first define a translation. For each ${\textrm {Zr}}$ -formula $\phi $ , let ${{\phi }^{(\kappa )}}$ be the formula which results by replacing each ‘ $\in $ ’ with ‘ $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ ’, each ‘ $=$ ’ with ‘ $\mathrel {\equiv }$ ’, and superscripting each variable with $\kappa $ . For example, the Axiom of ${\textrm {Powersets}^{(\kappa )}}$ is:

$$ \begin{align*}\forall a^{\kappa}\exists b^{\kappa}\forall x^{\kappa}(x^{\kappa} \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^{\kappa} \leftrightarrow (\forall v^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} x^{\kappa})v^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^{\kappa}).\end{align*} $$

Now we can prove the following result (see Appendix B, Theorem 13):Footnote 10

  • The Sets-from-Types Theorem. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {{\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}}}$ , for any limit $\kappa> \omega $ with $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

Otherwise put: ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves the translations of all theorems of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ .

2.2 Differences between ${\textrm {Zr}}$ and ${\textrm {Zr}}^{\boldsymbol{(\kappa )}}$

The proof of the Sets-from-Types Theorem involves establishing a tight association between two notions: an entity’s type, as in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ , and a set’s rank, as in ${\textrm {Zr}}$ . This sort of connection leads Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 289] to claim that ‘there is no deep mathematical difference between the ideological hierarchy of type theory and the ontological hierarchy of set theory’.

Whether to describe them as ‘deep’ may be a matter of taste, but it is worth noting three mathematical differences between ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , on the one hand, and ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ , on the other.Footnote 11 We summarize the differences in the following table:

We will now explain these three differences.

Concerning (1). The notion of rank is explicitly defined within ${\textrm {Zr}}$ itself, much as it is within ${\textrm {ZF}}$ .Footnote 12 By contrast, the notion of type is metatheoretic for both ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ . Every variable carries a type-index, and these type-indices are supplied externally. Indeed, when we take the very first step of describing the syntax of ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ , we assume as given all the type-indices $< \tau $ .

Concerning (2). ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is essentially untyped. It has exactly one kind of variable, which ranges over all sets of all ranks. By contrast, every variable in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ carries a type-index, and ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ ’s quantifier rules indicate that type $\alpha $ variables range only over entities of type $\leq \alpha $ . These theories have no untyped variables; that is, they have no variables which range over all entities of all types. (Note that, despite our use of the phrase ‘ranging over’, this difference shows up at the level of the formal theories, prior to interpretation. Indeed, none of the differences depend upon any semantic considerations.)

Concerning (3). Clearly, ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is recursively axiomatized (see Appendix B.1). However, neither ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ nor $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ is recursively axiomatizable, thanks to the intrinsically infinitary Limit-rules. Indeed, Limit $^\omega $ makes these theories arithmetically complete, since it simulates Hilbert’s $\omega $ -rule.Footnote 13

2.3 Mathematical foundations

We will now explain why these three differences are mathematically significant. In brief: the differences show that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is expressively richer but deductively weaker than $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ ; this makes ${\textrm {Zr}}$ much more suitable as a framework for considering mathematical foundations.

Differences (1) and (2) show that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is expressively richer than $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ . To see this, consider how we might formulate questions about the height of a hierarchy. In the case of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , we might ask a specific question like: Should we countenance a strongly inaccessible rank? That question is formulated within the object language of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , and this is possible because ${\textrm {Zr}}$ ’s untyped variables range over all the sets, whatever their rank. So, whilst ${\textrm {Zr}}$ does not settle whether there are any sets of strongly inaccessible rank, it does allow us to formulate the claim that there are, and tells us that any such sets obey Extensionality and Separation (for example). In the case of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , the analogous question about the height of a type-hierarchy would be: Should we countenance a strongly inaccessible type-index? But this question is, of course, formulated within a metalanguage. After all, each ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ has variables of all and only the types $< \tau $ , and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ has variables of all and only the types $\leq \kappa +2 < \tau $ ,Footnote 14 so neither theory allows us to formulate questions about entities of type $\tau $ ; they literally lack the vocabulary for doing so.

Difference (3), however, shows that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is deductively weaker than $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ . This is obvious—one is arithmetically complete, the other is not—but let us draw out a couple of consequences. The Sets-from-Types Theorem tells us that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ interprets ${\textrm {Zr}}$ . However, this interpretation is not faithful, i.e., some non-theorems of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ become theorems of $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ under interpretation; nor is the interpretation mutual, i.e., ${\textrm {Zr}}$ cannot interpret $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ .Footnote 15

This combination of expressive richness with deductive weakness makes ${\textrm {Zr}}$ much more suitable as a framework for mathematical foundations than $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ or ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ .Footnote 16 Concerning expressive strength: if our hierarchy is to serve as any kind of mathematical foundation, then questions about the height of the hierarchy will be of pressing importance; but only ${\textrm {Zr}}$ provides a suitable framework for raising such questions. Concerning deductive weakness: any adequate foundational theory must be recursively axiomatizable since, as Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 45] put it, only recursively axiomatizable theories can leave no doubt regarding whether a putative proof is a proof, so that ‘the highest possible degree of exactness is obtained’; but only ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is recursively axiomatized.

2.4 Gödel on ‘superfluous restrictions’ in type theory

We just quoted Gödel on mathematical foundations. Having made the quoted remarks, Gödel went on to make a more famous claim:

the system of axioms for the theory of aggregates, as presented by Zermelo, Fraenkel, and von Neumann…is nothing else but a natural generalization of the theory of types, or rather, what becomes of the theory of types if certain superfluous restrictions are removed.Footnote 17

He continued by outlining the ‘superfluous restrictions’ thus:Footnote 18

  1. (i) $a \in b$ ’ is meaningful iff the type of ‘b’ is exactly one greater than that of ‘a’;

  2. (ii) each class (of any type) can contain classes of exactly one type; and

  3. (iii) only finite types are allowed.

Whilst explicitly disavowing exegetical aims, Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 273–274, 278] motivate $\textrm {CTT}$ by suggesting that $\textrm {CTT}$ arises from ${\textrm {STT}}$ simply by lifting these ‘superfluous restrictions’.

Certainly $\textrm {CTT}$ lifts restrictions (i)–(iii). But ${\textrm {Zr}}$ also lifts these restrictions, and in a different way. Moreover, it is this latter way which we find in Gödel’s Reference Gödel and Feferman[18] lecture. On each of points (1)–(3) from Section 2.2, Gödel sides against the use of anything like $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ .

Concerning (1). Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 47] is clear that the theory which arises by removing ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s ‘superfluous restrictions’ will supply its own ‘types’.Footnote 19

Concerning (2). Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 49] complains that, in ${\textrm {STT}}$ , we have to formulate ‘the logical axioms for each type separately’, and he states that the theory which removes ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s ‘superfluous restrictions’ will avoid this complaint. Such a theory will therefore employ an untyped variable, which can range over all entities.

Concerning (3). As already noted, Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 45 and 48] insists that an adequate formalization of the foundations of mathematics must be recursively axiomatizable, and explicitly remarks that such theories are necessarily arithmetically incomplete.

Gödel, then, seems never to have envisaged theories like $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ or ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ .Footnote 20 Rather, Gödel’s suggestion was that removing ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s ‘superfluous restrictions’ led to ${\textrm {ZFU}}$ , by the simple stipulation that the ‘type’ of x is $\alpha $ iff $x \in V_{\alpha +1} \setminus V_\alpha $ , with these segments of the set hierarchy defined directly within ${\textrm {ZFU}}$ in the (now) familiar fashion.Footnote 21 That is, Gödel simply identified a set’s ‘type’ with (what we now call) its rank, and advocated the use of recursively axiomatized theories whose untyped variables range over all the sets (of all ranks).

3 The (in)significance of the Sets-from-Types Theorem

We have noted the important mathematical differences between ${\textrm {Zr}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ . We will now show how these differences undermine the philosophical significance of the Sets-from-Types Theorem. In broad brush strokes: Linnebo and Rayo think that the Sets-from-Types Theorem sheds important new light on set theory; we disagree, since $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ and ${\textrm {Zr}}$ and importantly distinct.

3.1 Elsa’s worries

To reconstruct Linnebo and Rayo’s [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 289–294, Reference Linnebo and Rayo24, p. 178] intended use of the Sets-from-Types Theorem, we will introduce a character, Elsa. Elsa wants to use ${\textrm {Zr}}$ to talk about the hierarchy of sets, but she has some ontological worries. Following post-Quinean orthodoxy, Elsa draws a sharp distinction between a theory’s ontology and its ideology. In general, Elsa thinks that if a theory is coherent, then that is enough to guarantee the good standing of its ideology: roughly, Elsa thinks that a theory’s ideology merely provides you with a way of talking about objects, and there is no standard beyond coherence by which to judge ways of talking. Now, Elsa is certain that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is coherent, and so she has no reservations about its ideology. But, ${\textrm {Zr}}$ also postulates a rich ontology of sets, and Elsa insists that the mere coherence of a theory is not enough to guarantee the existence of its ontological commitments. So, Elsa worries: What guarantees that there are enough sets?

Linnebo and Rayo have a sequence of recommendations for Elsa. First, they will introduce Elsa to the type hierarchy, in the form of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ , whose coherence can be assumed (at least, in this context). The question arises of how Elsa should think about ontology/ideology in the type-theoretic context. Quantification over type $0$ entities is just first-order quantification; so Elsa should think that theorizing at type $0$ introduces ontological commitments. However, Elsa can perhaps be encouraged to think that theorizing at higher types simply gives us sophisticated ways to talk about the objects at type $0$ , and so only introduces ideological commitments. If Elsa agrees to think in this way, then she will map her dichotomy between ontology and ideology onto the dichotomy between type $0$ and type $> 0$ .Footnote 22 Having done this, she will regard ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ as ontologically unproblematic: it posits just one object (i.e., one type $0$ entity). Granted, she may regard ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ as ideologically profligate, but she thinks that its coherence guarantees the good standing of its ideology. Consequently, Elsa should have no worries about using ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Now, via the Set-from-Types Theorem, Elsa can use ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ to obtain $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ . So, according to Linnebo and Rayo, Elsa will have no reason to worry about using $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ in place of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ .

Having come this far, Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 290] hope that Elsa might now be brought to share their view, that ‘the two hierarchies’—the ‘ideological’ hierarchy of $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ and the ‘ontological’ hierarchy of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ —‘constitute different perspectives on the same subject-matter.’ But we do not need to consider that further step. We think that Elsa should balk at the line of reasoning given in the previous paragraph.

3.2 Ontology relocated

The immediate problem is that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ are importantly different theories. One of the differences, mentioned in Section 2.3, is that Elsa can ask about the height of her set-hierarchy within the object-language of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , whereas she can only ask about the height of a type-hierarchy within a metalanguage. But, as we will now show, this basic issue—of object language versus metalanguage—completely undermines the dialectical force of Linnebo and Rayo’s line of reasoning.

Recall: Elsa wants to use ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , but worries: What guarantees that enough sets exist? Linnebo and Rayo recommend that Elsa invoke the Sets-from-Types Theorem. Specifically, they encourage Elsa to fix some limit $\kappa> \omega $ with $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ , then work in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ to obtain $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ .

Inevitably, though, this discussion of $\kappa $ and $\tau $ takes place within some metatheory which we use to describe ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . After all, as noted in Sections 2.22.3, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ ’s types are supplied externally. So, if Elsa is to follow Linnebo and Rayo’s recommendation, she will have to countenance a suitably large index, $\tau $ , in the metatheory, so that she can both describe ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and obtain $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ .

At this point, though, Elsa will simply want to ask: What guarantees that any suitable $\tau $ exists? Such an entity would have to stand at the head of a vast sequence of type-indices. Well then: What guarantees that enough type-indices exist? Her ontological worries about sets have not have been addressed; they have just become worries about the ontology postulated within the metatheory.

3.3 Ideological-bootstrapping

This elementary problem undermines Linnebo and Rayo’s way of dealing with Elsa. However, it is worth considering one possible line of response, via (what we call) ideological-bootstrapping. This idea is independently interesting, and it will buy Linnebo and Rayo some slack, but not enough slack to save their argumentative strategy.

To define ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ , we must be given the type-index $\tau $ . In the previous subsection, we imagined Elsa worrying about whether $\tau $ exists. But—so this line of reply runs—Elsa is mistakenly assuming here that $\tau $ must be a type $0$ entity. Instead, $\tau $ could be a higher-type entity, supplied by some ideologically-rich but ontologically-innocent theory, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\sigma }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . In turn, $\sigma $ might be some higher-type entity, supplied by some theory ${\textrm {CTT}^{\rho }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . And so on.Footnote 23

The hope is that, somehow, considering a sequence of such theories will sooth away Elsa’s ontological concerns. But, however exactly this line of response is meant to work, it will require that $\tau> \sigma > \rho > \ldots $ . After all, Elsa’s worries kick in as soon as the syntax of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ is laid down; so her worries clearly cannot be addressed by starting with some theory ${\textrm {CTT}^{\sigma }_{\textrm {p}}}$ with $\sigma \geq \tau $ .

This simple observation dictates the form that the attempted reply must take. We are being asked to imagine a sequence of theories, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _1}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , …, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _n}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , as follows:

  1. (a) $\tau _1$ is so small that Elsa has no serious qualms about its existence.

  2. (b) As we move along the sequence, the ideology strictly increases (i.e., $\tau _i < \tau _{i+1}$ ), but the earlier theory proves the existence of an entity which indexes the terms of the next theory (i.e., each ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _i}_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves the existence of something with order-type $\tau _{i+1}> \tau _i$ ).

  3. (c) ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _n}_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ , for some suitable $\kappa $ .

Call this response ideological-bootstrapping, since ideologically weaker theories are used to define ideologically richer theories at step (b).Footnote 24

(Note that we have assumed that the sequence of theories is finite. To explain why, suppose someone instead suggests this: If Elsa has accepted the existence of an $\omega $ -sequence of theories ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _1}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _2}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , …, then Elsa can bootstrap her way to their limit, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _\omega }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . This suggestion is spurious. If some ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _i}_{\textrm {p}}}$ is sufficient to introduce an entity with order-type $\tau _\omega $ , then we can simply take ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _\omega }_{\textrm {p}}}$ as the $i\mathord {+}1^{\textrm {th}}$ theory. The important case is when none of the theories ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau _i}_{\textrm {p}}}$ suffices to introduce anything with order-type $\tau _\omega $ . But in this case, Elsa will worry whether ‘taking the limit’ is ontologically innocent; for, by assumption, she has not found any ontologically innocent theory which supplies $\tau _\omega $ .)

Ideological-bootstrapping might work in specific circumstances. For example, suppose Elsa is comfortable with the existence of $\omega +\omega + 3$ , and so has no concerns with the specification of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega +\omega +3}_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Invoking the Sets-from-Types Theorem, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega +\omega +3}_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves ${\textrm {Zr}}^{(\omega +\omega )}$ . This allows Elsa to simulate the set-theoretic hierarchy up to $V_{\omega +\omega }$ . Living within $V_{\omega +\omega }$ , Elsa can find an uncountable A well-ordered by some relation $<$ .Footnote 25 Using this, Elsa can define a theory ${\textrm {CTT}^{A}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , whose type indices are the members of A as ordered by $<$ . Since A is uncountable, ${\textrm {CTT}^{A}_{\textrm {p}}}$ is straightforwardly richer than ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega + \omega + 3}_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Moreover, using ${\textrm {CTT}^{A}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , Elsa can simulate a much larger chunk of the set-theoretic hierarchy than $V_{\omega +\omega }$ ; living within that chunk of the hierarchy, she can find larger well-orders; these can be used to supply the indices for some further development of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}\ldots $ and so on. This seems like a case where ideological-bootstrapping might genuinely achieve something.

Nevertheless, there are hard limits on what ideological-bootstrapping can achieve. In the simplest case, suppose Elsa insists on starting with ${\textrm {CTT}^{n}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , for some finite n, because she is uncertain whether there are infinitely many entities. Since ${\textrm {CTT}^{n}_{\textrm {p}}}$ only yields (surrogates for) finite well-orders, no amount of ideological-boostrapping from this starting point will allow Elsa to obtain any infinite well-order. So, whenever Linnebo and Rayo try to describe any theory ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ such that $\tau $ is infinite, Elsa will worry whether the theory itself even exists.

The shape of this problem is quite general. Say that $\kappa $ is a hereditary-point iff $\kappa $ is an infinite cardinal and everything in $V_\kappa $ is strictly smaller than $\kappa $ (so $\omega $ is the first hereditary-point).Footnote 26 When $\kappa $ is a hereditary-point, it is in principle impossible to ideologically-bootstrap your way from below $\kappa $ to above $\kappa $ , since every entity below level $\kappa $ is strictly smaller than $\kappa $ itself.

This problem is especially pertinent, given two facts about hereditary-points and ${\textrm {ZF}}$ . First, ${\textrm {ZF}}$ proves that there are proper-class-many hereditary-points; but, since any hereditary-point after $\omega $ would be pretty enormous, it is not unreasonable to wonder whether any exist; and ideological-bootstrapping cannot quiet such qualms.Footnote 27 Second, the standard models of ${\textrm {ZF}}$ are the $V_\kappa $ such that $\kappa $ is strongly inaccessible; and every strongly inaccessible cardinal is a hereditary-point; so ideological-bootstrapping cannot possibly address any ontological worries that an Elsa-like character might have about the existence of any standard model of ${\textrm {ZF}}$ .

The argument of Section 3.2 therefore stands essentially unchanged. Linnebo and Rayo are mistaken to think that cumulative type theories can help us to overcome ontological worries, since the very existence of the (syntactically individuated) theories themselves requires a rich ontology in the metatheory.

4 CTT: superfluous type-restrictions

In Section 2.4, we discussed Gödel’s claim that ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions were ‘superfluous’. We should now make explicit something which we there left implicit: these type-restrictions are superfluous given Gödel’s aims. Specifically, Gödel wanted to establish a foundational, ‘formal system which avoids the logical paradoxes and retains all [of] mathematics’ [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 46]. Given those aims, $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are just as superfluous as ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s; it is best to follow Gödel, and work with something like ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , with its untyped variables.

All of this is compatible with the idea that, given alternative aims, ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s or $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions might not be superfluous, but deeply important. As we will show in this section, though, $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are inevitably ‘superfluous restrictions’, in the sense that any semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ also licenses the use of an untyped variable and allows the ‘types’ to be defined internally. (Cf. points (1) and (2) from Section 2.2.) So, in a slogan: $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are superfluous, on any semantics.

We will unpack the details in a moment. First, we should explain the phrase ‘a semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ ’. As we are using that phrase, a semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ is a general framework within which to provide models of $\textrm {CTT}$ , rather than a specific model of some ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ . (Compare the idea of ‘the possible worlds semantics for modal language’.) So, in providing a semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ , we fix the meaning of phrases like ‘a model of $\textrm {CTT}$ ’ and ‘an entity of type $\alpha $ ’; the latter will be the sort of entity which, according to the semantics, can be the value of a type $\alpha $ variable.

4.1 The abstract argument for introducing untyped variables

Our argument begins with an uncontentious point: the stringently-stated rules for $\textrm {CTT}$ tell us that $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ is well-formed iff $\beta> \alpha $ ; but these rules are needlessly stringent, on any given semantics.

To see this, fix some semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ , and let $\beta \leq \alpha $ . The formula $x^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^\beta $ is well-formed according to $\textrm {CTT}$ . So, for any model $\mathcal {M}$ and any type $\alpha $ entity $a^\alpha $ and type $\beta $ entity $b^\beta $ from $\mathcal {M}$ , either $\mathcal {M} \models a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ or $\mathcal {M} \models \lnot a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ . (Note: what exactly this comes to will depend on the details of the semantics; but we are proceeding abstractly for now and want to consider any semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ .) Now, as explained in Section 1.2, the formula $x^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^\beta $ perfectly simulates the formula $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ ; that is, it perfectly simulates the notion of applying a type $\beta $ entity to a type $\alpha $ entity. So we could have allowed $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ to count as well-formed, even though $\beta \ngtr \alpha $ . So, $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s stringently-stated type-restrictions are needlessly stringent.

To be clear, this is not an objection to $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions. We are really just repackaging a point we made in Section 1.2, and also made by Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 282–283], that we can liberalise $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s stringently-stated formation rules, and allow that $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ is well-formed for any type-indices $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . From a purely formal point of view, this changes almost nothing. So, in what follows, we will simply allow that $\textrm {CTT}$ counts every formula $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ as well-formed.

Significantly, though, $\textrm {CTT}$ still lacks untyped variables. But, for exactly the same reason, this is also needlessly stringent, on any given semantics.

To see this, fix some semantics for (liberally formulated) $\textrm {CTT}$ . Now $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ is well-formed for any $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . So, for any model $\mathcal {M}$ and any type $\alpha $ entity $a^\alpha $ and type $\beta $ entity $b^\beta $ from that model, either $\mathcal {M} \models b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ or $\mathcal {M} \models \lnot b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ . That is, any model assigns a truth value to the application of any entity to any entity, whatever their types might happen to be. So we could have allowed the untyped atomic formula, $y(x)$ , to count as well-formed: whatever specific values the variables take, the formula would just amount to applying some entity to some entity, which is exactly what the semantics allows.

The upshot is that any semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ also licenses the use of untyped variables. This time, though, we do have an objection to $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions. Whereas stringently-formulated $\textrm {CTT}$ can simulate any typed-formula $y^\beta (x^\alpha )$ , via $x^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^\beta $ , it lacks the technical resources to simulate the untyped-formula $y(x)$ . Untyped variables have to be added by hand. But, once we have added them, we will have moved from a typed to an untyped theory; if we choose to retain ‘typed’ variables, then they will just behave as restricted untyped variables.

Of course, if there had been no consistent way to introduce untyped variables, then $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions would have been far from superfluous. But, in this sort of a context, theories like ${\textrm {Zr}}$ provide us with a clear method for consistently introducing untyped variables.Footnote 28 Moreover, they also provide us with a paradigm for how to define the notion of ‘type’ (i.e., rank) within the theory. So $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are genuinely superfluous.Footnote 29

4.2 Illustration: the class semantics

The argument of the previous subsection is very abstract. To make it more concrete, in this subsection and the next, we will consider two specific semantics in detail: the class semantics, and the plural semantics. Just as our abstract argument predicts, both semantics clearly license the use of untyped variables.

(To avoid any unfortunate misunderstandings: we offer these semantics merely as illustrations. When we say that no semantics could justify the adoption of $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions, we are not making an inductive inference from these two examples; that conclusion was established by the abstract argument of Section 4.1.)

We start by considering the class semantics. To define a model for $\textrm {CTT}$ within this semantics, we first specify some suitable set of urelements, U. We then stipulate that the type $\alpha $ entities are the members of $U_{\alpha +1}$ , where we define:

$$ \begin{align*} U_1 & := U \cup \{\emptyset\} & U_{\alpha+1} & := \wp(U_\alpha) \cup U & U_\beta & := \bigcup_{\alpha<\beta} U_\alpha \mbox{ for limit } \beta. \end{align*} $$

Finally, we offer a general clause governing the semantics of atomic sentences:

  • $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ ’ is true iff the referent of ‘ $a^\alpha $ ’ is a member of the referent of ‘ $b^\beta $ ’.

Uncontroversially, $\textrm {CTT}$ is sound for the class semantics. A stringently-typed formula like ‘ $b^2(a^0)$ ’ will be true (in a model) iff the referent of ‘ $a^0$ ’ is a member of the referent of ‘ $b^2$ ’. A liberally-typed formula like ‘ $b^0(a^2)$ ’ will also be true (in a model) iff the referent of ‘ $a^2$ ’ is a member of the referent of ‘ $b^0$ ’; and this will inevitably be false, since the latter is guaranteed to be an urelement, i.e., an individual without members.

Our semantic clause for atomic sentences employed type restrictions. However, on the class semantics, the type-restrictions are straightforwardly superfluous. We can easily offer a similar semantic clause for untyped terms:

  • $b(a)$ ’ is true iff the referent of ‘a’ is a member of the referent of ‘b’.

Otherwise put: there is no barrier to introducing untyped variables, whose values can be any individual or class. Of course, given the old paradoxes, we will have to take care in introducing untyped variables. However, as we have already discussed, ${\textrm {Zr}}$ -like theories show us how to do this safely.

4.3 Illustration: the plural semantics

The class semantics concerns a class-hierarchy built from a basis of individuals. The plural semantics concerns a plural-hierarchy built from a similar basis.Footnote 30 In a little more detail, we use the phrase ‘plural $^*$ ’ as a catch-all for whatever we find at any level in the plural hierarchy, i.e., any object, any objects, any objectses, …, any objects(es) $^\alpha $ ….Footnote 31 We then offer this general clause governing the semantics for atomic sentences:

  • $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ ’ is true iff what ‘ $b^\beta $ ’ refers to includes what ‘ $a^\alpha $ ’ refers to.Footnote 32

So ‘ $b^2(a^0)$ ’ is true iff what ‘ $b^2$ ’ refers to includes what ‘ $a^0$ ’ refers to; and ‘ $b^0(a^2)$ ’ is true iff what ‘ $b^0$ ’ refers to includes what ‘ $a^2$ ’ refers to. But equally, the semantic clause applies perfectly well to untyped terms:

  • $b(a)$ ’ is true iff what ‘b’ refers to includes what ‘a’ refers to.

Again: there is no barrier to introducing untyped variables, whose values can be any plural $^*$ .

As before, care must be taken to preserve consistency. But we know how to take care: roughly stated, we just need to do for plurals $^*$ what ${\textrm {Zr}}$ does for classes/sets. In more detail, instead of setting up a plural $^*$ -hierarchy using type-restricted variables with externally supplied type-indices, we can reason about plurals $^*$ using an untyped variable, with the plurals $^*$ arranged into a cumulative hierarchy according to their rank (with ‘rank’ defined within the theory, using our untyped variable). And this work has been carried out carefully: Oliver and Smiley [Reference Oliver and Smiley28, chap. 15] and Florio and Linnebo [Reference Florio and Linnebo11, sec. 12.6] both present consistent plural logics featuring untyped variables. Indeed, Florio and Linnebo develop their untyped plural logic precisely by starting with the $\textrm {CTT}$ on the plural semantics, and then collapsing the types in the way that we have described.

5 ${\textrm {STT}}$ : type-restrictions justified

We have argued that $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are inevitably superfluous. They are unnecessary for the aim of providing a foundational theory for mathematics, and they cannot be justified semantically, since any semantics for $\textrm {CTT}$ will permit the introduction of an untyped variable.

In this section, we will show that ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions are not similarly superfluous. We can justify the adoption of ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions by invoking the Fregean semantics. Indeed, on this semantics, a formula is intelligible iff it is well-formed in ${\textrm {STT}}$ .

5.1 Against referentialism

In Sections 4.2 and 4.3, we used the class and plural semantics to illustrate our objection to $\textrm {CTT}$ . Both of these semantics are referentialist. By this we mean that both semantics treat every type of term as a type of referring term: every type of term performs the same semantic role—referring—and all that changes is what they refer to—individuals, classes/plurals $^*$ , or something else.Footnote 33

The class and plural semantics render $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions superfluous, precisely because they are referentialist. After all, if every type of term performs the same kind of semantic role as every other type of term, then every type of term can be meaningfully substituted for every other type of term. In that case, as we argued in Section 4.1, the semantics will also allows us to introduce an untyped variable. It follows, immediately, that any semantics which might justify ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions will have to be non-referentialist; in other words, it will have to assign different kinds of semantic role to different types of term.

Now, at one time, this might have seemed like an impossible demand. According to the old Quinean [Reference Prior30, pp. 66–68] orthodoxy, we can only quantify into the position of a referring term; so type theory—which allows us to bind variables of every type—must be given a referentialist semantics. Fortunately, times have changed, and philosophers are increasingly willing to accept quantification into other kinds of position.Footnote 34 In what follows, we will simply assume that the old Quinean orthodoxy is mistaken, and will present a particular non-referentialist semantics—the Fregean semantics—which justifies ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions.

5.2 Conceptual but referentialist semantics

The Fregean semantics is a variety of conceptual semantics. On a conceptual semantics, type theories are theories of predication:Footnote 35 $a^0$ ’ is a name which refers to an object; ‘ $b^1$ ’ is a first-level predicate which expresses a property of objects (a type 1 property);Footnote 36 $c^2$ ’ is a second-level predicate which expresses a property of properties of objects (a type 2 property); and so on.

This way of characterising conceptual semantics is schematic, and we get different versions of the semantics when we supply different accounts of what it means for a predicate to express a property. On one view of predication, predicates ‘express’ properties in the sense that they refer to properties, just as names refer to objects. To illustrate, take the following sentence:

  1. (1) Socrates pontificates

According to this view of predication, ‘pontificates’ refers to the property Pontification.Footnote 37 Clearly, combining this account of predication with the conceptual semantics yields another brand of referentialism. Every type of term is still referential; all that changes is whether it refers to an ordinary individual (like Socrates) or to something within a property-hierarchy (like Pontification). We then have the following semantic clause for atomic sentences:

  • $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ ’ is true iff the referent of ‘ $a^\alpha $ ’ instantiates the referent of ‘ $b^\beta $

This allows us to make sense of ‘ $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ ’, for any types $\alpha $ and $\beta $ . For example, ‘ $b^0(a^0)$ ’ is true iff the referent of ‘ $a^0$ ’ instantiates the referent of ‘ $b^0$ ’. Now, admittedly, this formula would correspond to something slightly peculiar in natural language. If ‘ $a^0$ ’ referred to Socrates, and ‘ $b^0$ ’ referred to Plato, then we might try to render ‘ $b^0(a^0)$ ’ as:

  1. (2) Socrates Plato

This is scarcely grammatical English. Still, for referentialists about predication, (2) is intelligible: it says that Socrates instantiates Plato. Indeed, precisely this point is made by Magidor Reference Magidor[27], who insists that (2) is perfectly meaningful and trivially false. We are not agreeing with Magidor here, but we do think that referentialists about predication should agree with her. Moreover, and as in Section 4.1, referentialists about predication will ultimately find type-restrictions superfluous; nothing will prevent them from introducing untyped variables and insisting that ‘ $b(a)$ ’ is true iff the referent of ‘a’ instantiates the referent of ‘b’.

5.3 Fregean semantics

There is, however, a non-referentialist version of the conceptual semantics: it is a Fregean semantics.

Unlike referentialists, Fregeans do not think that predicates refer to properties (not, at least, in anything like the sense that a name ‘refers’).Footnote 38 Rather, they think that the role of a predicate is to say something of an object; for example, ‘pontificates’ says of an object that it pontificates. This is the sense in which Fregeans think that predicates are ‘incomplete’, and they indicate this by writing their predicates with gaps. So rather than writing the predicate in (1) as ‘pontificates’, they write it as ‘x pontificates’, where ‘x’ marks a gap for a name to go. We can then say that sentence (1) is true iff ‘x pontificates’ says something true of the referent of ‘Socrates’, i.e., iff Socrates pontificates.Footnote 39

From this Fregean perspective, (2) is not just ungrammatical, but unintelligible. We arrive at it by taking (1) and replacing its predicate, ‘x pontificates’, with a referring name, ‘Plato’. Names and predicates are made to work together, but two names cannot work together in the same way. It is not within a name’s remit to say anything of an object; names just refer to objects. And that is why (2) is a meaningless string: neither name says anything of the referent of the other (let alone something true or false).

Now consider the following sentence:

  1. (3) Someone pontificates

This sentence is not made by combining a predicate with a name. Instead, it is made by combining two predicates, ‘x pontificates’ and ‘Someone Y’. Crucially, though, these are two different types of predicates: ‘x pontificates’ is a first-level predicate, meaning that ‘x’ marks a gap for a name; ‘Someone Y’ is a second-level predicate, meaning that ‘Y’ marks a gap for a first-level predicate. Just as first-level predicates play a different kind of semantic role from the names they can take as input, second-level predicates play a different kind of semantic role from the first-level predicates that they can take as input. We might describe this role thus: a second-level predicate says something of things said of objects. This means that (3) is true/false iff ‘Someone Y’ says something true/false of what ‘x pontificates’ says of objects. Specifically: ‘Someone Y’ says something true of what ‘x pontificates’ says of objects iff ‘x pontificates’ says something true of someone; and it says something false of what ‘x pontificates’ says of objects iff ‘x pontificates’ says something false of everyone.

Again, from this Fregean perspective, it is easy to see that we cannot meaningfully substitute a name for the first-level predicate in (3). Attempting to do this would yield:

  1. (4) Someone Plato

This string is not just ungrammatical, but meaningless. To be meaningful, the input to ‘Someone Y’ must be the kind of expression that says something of objects. But ‘Plato’ refers to an object, rather than saying anything of objects (let alone something true of someone or false of everyone). So, if we try to plug ‘Plato’ into the argument-place of ‘Someone Y’, we end up with garbage.Footnote 40

The crucial point is that, on the Fregean semantics, different types of term play different types of semantic role: ‘ $a^0$ ’ is a name which refers to an object; ‘ $b^1$ ’ is a first-level predicate which says something of objects; ‘ $c^2$ ’ is a second-level predicate which says something of things said of objects; and so on. And rather than having a single semantic clause which applies to all atomic sentences, we have different clauses for different types of predication:

  • $b^1(a^0)$ ’ is true iff ‘ $b^1$ ’ says something true of the referent of ‘ $a^0$

  • $c^2(b^1)$ ’ is true iff ‘ $c^2$ ’ says something true of what ‘ $b^1$ ’ says of objects

  • $\ldots $

These semantic clauses allow us to make sense of ‘ $b^n(a^m)$ ’ iff $n=m+1$ . This is how the Fregean semantics justifies ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions: a formula is intelligible on the Fregean semantics iff it is well-formed in ${\textrm {STT}}$ .

For the same reason, the Fregean semantics also prohibits the introduction of untyped variables. Untyped variables would need to be able to take any entity of any type as their values. But, on the Fregean semantics, there is no one sense in which different types of entity could be the ‘value’ of a variable; the sense in which an object is the value of a type 0 variable is incommensurable with the sense in which a type 1 property is the value of a type 1 variable.

To be clear, we are not trying to argue here that anyone should adopt the Fregean semantics.Footnote 41 Our point here is just that ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions, unlike $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s, are justified by at least one semantics.Footnote 42

5.4 ‘Cumulative types’ as ambiguous

We have just argued that the Fregean semantics prohibits the introduction of untyped variables. But what it cannot prohibit, of course, is the introduction of ambiguous variables, which sometimes behave as one type, and sometimes behave as another. And in fact, this provides the Fregeans with one way of starting to make sense of $\textrm {CTT}$ . Specifically, they can treat $a^0$ as an ambiguous term: in $b^1(a^0)$ , it behave as a name, and so refers to an object; in $c^2(a^0)$ , it behaves as a first-level predicate, and so says something of an object.

If that is how we are to read formulas like $c^2(a^0)$ , though, then they no longer represent any departure from ${\textrm {STT}}$ . Working in ${\textrm {STT}}$ , we can introduce an injective type-raising function, $\mathord {\uparrow }$ , from objects to type $1$ properties; so $a^0$ is an object, but $\mathord {\uparrow } a^0$ is a type $1$ property (We also lay down rules to ensure that $\mathord {\uparrow } a^0$ behaves as a suitable surrogate for ‘the $a^1$ such that $a^1 \mathrel {\equiv } a^0$ ’; for details, see §C.) To avoid ambiguity, we can then rewrite $c^2(a^0)$ as $c^2(\mathord {\uparrow } a^0)$ , which is now well-formed according to ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions.

This idea can be extended across all finite types. The result is ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ , which augments ${\textrm {STT}}$ with a theory of type-raising functions, like $\mathord {\uparrow }$ , whilst retaining ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions. We can then prove the following strong result: ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ and ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ are definitionally equivalent (where ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ is the fragment of $\textrm {CTT}$ which uses all and only finite type indices; for details, see Appendix C).

There is, however, an important limitation to this equivalence result. Since entities do not really cumulate in ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ , ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ cannot accommodate transfinite types, and so cannot recapture any transfinite uses of $\textrm {CTT}$ . This is significant, because Linnebo and Rayo’s main argument for $\textrm {CTT}$ invokes transfinite types (see Section 6). For this reason, Linnebo and Rayo must have intended $\textrm {CTT}$ to be taken at face-value, rather than as a disguised form of ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ . Unfortunately for them, though, nothing could justify $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions, taken at face-value; that was the lesson of Section 4.

6 The semantic argument

We have established an important difference between $\textrm {CTT}$ and ${\textrm {STT}}$ : nothing could justify $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions, but the Fregean semantics can justify ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions. In this section, we will respond to Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument for $\textrm {CTT}$ . This argument is designed to show that ${\textrm {STT}}$ is semantically unstable, and that restoring stability pushes us to $\textrm {CTT}$ . We will not present any new objections to $\textrm {CTT}$ in this section; our aim is simply to explain how an advocate of the Fregean semantics should reply to Linnebo and Rayo.

6.1 Naïve Optimism and Naïve Union

Linnebo and Rayo introduce us to two notions:

  • A $\beta $ -order language is a language which contains variables of all (and only) the types $\alpha < \beta $ .Footnote 43

  • A generalized semantic theory for a language is ‘a theory of all possible interpretations the language might take’ [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 275]. In particular, a generalized semantic theory for a $\beta $ -order language provides an interpretation which allows any type $\alpha $ entity to be the value of a variable $x^\alpha $ , for each $\alpha < \beta $ .Footnote 44

These notions are connected by two formal results Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, Appendix B]:

  • Blocker Theorem. No language can provide a generalized semantic theory for itself.

  • Enabler Theorem. For any $\beta $ , let $\beta ^* = \beta + 2$ if $\beta $ is a limit and $\beta ^* = \beta +1$ otherwise; then a $\beta ^*$ -order language can provide a generalized semantic theory for a $\beta $ -order language.

The Blocker Theorem holds by familiar, liar-like reasoning. Moreover, as Florio and Shapiro [Reference Florio and Shapiro12, pp. 162–163] note, it shows that these two principles are jointly inconsistent:

  • Naïve Optimism. Any language can be given a generalized semantic theory.

  • Naïve Union. For any languages, there is a union language, which combines all the expressions of those languages.

To see the problem: by Naïve Union, there is a language, $\mathscr {U}$ , which is the union of all languages; by Naïve Optimism, $\mathscr {U}$ can be given a generalized semantic theory in some language $\mathscr {G}$ ; by the Blocker Theorem, $\mathscr {G}$ is not a sub-language of $\mathscr {U}$ ; but this contradicts the fact that $\mathscr {U}$ is the union of all languages, including $\mathscr {G}$ .

6.2 Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument

Linnebo and Rayo avoid contradiction by restricting Naïve Union as follows:

  • Limited Union. For any limit $\lambda $ , if there is a $\beta $ -order language for every $\beta < \lambda $ , then there is also a $\lambda $ -order language.Footnote 45

Having restricted Naïve Union in this way, Linnebo and Rayo’s [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 275–281] Semantic Argument for $\textrm {CTT}$ now gets going. Here is a very brief summary. Suppose we start with an ordinary first-order language. By Naïve Optimism, this language has a generalized semantic theory. By the Blocker Theorem, this generalized semantic theory cannot be given in a first-order language; but, by the Enabler Theorem, it can be given in a second-order language. Naïve Optimism now requires that this second-order language has a generalized semantic theory; as before, the Blocker and Enabler theorems will lead us to provide this semantics in a third-order language. This process repeats, running through every finite order. At this point, Limited Union kicks in, giving us an $\omega $ -order language which combines all of the finite orders into a single language. To present a generalized semantic theory for this language, Naïve Optimism and the Blocker and Enabler Theorems push us up to an $\omega \mathord {+}2$ -order language. And there is now no stopping us: Naïve Optimism, Limited Union and the two theorems keep pushing us to countenance languages of higher and higher orders. Moreover, when we supply the semantics for variables of some limit type $\lambda $ , the only plausible option is to allow them to take all entities of all types $<\lambda $ as values. And this requires that at least some of our types be cumulative.

6.3 Rebutting the semantic argument

We agree with the following conditional: if we accept both Naïve Optimism and Limited Union, then there is good reason to embrace $\textrm {CTT}$ . Our response is to reject Naïve Optimism (and to insist on Naïve Union). However, we will show that our stance is more principled that Linnebo and Rayo’s.

Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 280] motivate Limited Union as follows: whenever you are ‘prepared to countenance languages of order $\beta $ for every $\beta < \lambda $ ’, you ‘should also countenance languages of order $\lambda $ ’, since ‘they would be made up entirely of vocabulary that had been previously deemed legitimate’. This line of reasoning is compelling. However, it clearly generalizes, to provide a motivation for Naïve Union. After all: whenever you are prepared to countenance some languages, you should also countenance their union, for that union would be made up entirely of vocabulary that had been previously deemed legitimate. In short: the only motivation Linnebo and Rayo offer for Limited Union is really a motivation for Naïve Union.

Of course, Naïve Union is inconsistent with Naïve Optimism. So, if there were a stellar argument in favour of Naïve Optimism, we could see the retreat from Naïve Union to Limited Union as a simple instance of the heuristic that, on encountering a contradiction, we should aim to get as close as we can to what we initially wanted, without falling into inconsistency.Footnote 46 Regrettably, though, Linnebo and Rayo provide no argument for Naïve Optimism. So, prima facie, an equally good instance of that heuristic would be to accept Naïve Union and instead restrict Naïve Optimism. This threatens to leave us with a deadlock, between those who want to restrict Naïve Union (and so embrace $\textrm {CTT}$ ), and those who want to restrict Naïve Optimism (and so might reject $\textrm {CTT}$ ).

Fortunately, the argument of Section 5 provides a principled way to break the deadlock: if we are working with a Fregean semantics for the types, then we should restrict Naïve Optimism. Specifically, we should replace Naïve Optimism with the following:

  • Finite Optimism. Any language of any finite order can be given a generalized semantic theory.

To be clear: the motivation for this restriction is not simply to avoid contradiction. (As far as restoring formal consistency goes, Finite Optimism is serious overkill.) Rather, Finite Optimism expresses the exact amount of optimism which is even coherent on the Fregean semantics. Since Fregean types cannot cumulate, we cannot make any sense of the idea of an $\omega \mathord {+}2$ -order language on the Fregean semantics. Finite Optimism and Naïve Union push us to countenance an $\omega $ -order language, like ${\textrm {STT}}$ itself, but we are pushed no further. Otherwise put: ${\textrm {STT}}$ is the principled limit on Fregean types.

7 Partially cumulative types

In this paper, we have critically discussed $\textrm {CTT}$ , which is the approach to cumulative types favoured by Linnebo and Rayo. In this final section, we will discuss an alternative approach to cumulative types, due to Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, sec. 5].

$\textrm {CTT}$ is cumulative in two senses: first, $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ is well-formed whenever $\beta> \alpha $ ; second, the values of $x^\beta $ include all of the values of $x^\alpha $ , whenever $\beta \geq \alpha $ . Florio and Jones’ cumulative type theory—call it ${\textrm {FJT}}$ —is cumulative only in the first of these senses. Indeed, for them, no type $\alpha $ entity is a type $\beta $ entity, when $\alpha \neq \beta $ . As we will see, this difference between $\textrm {CTT}$ and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is a double-edged sword: on the one hand, it provides Florio and Jones with the means to defend ${\textrm {FJT}}$ from the argument we offered against $\textrm {CTT}$ in Section 4; on the other hand, it leaves so little distance between ${\textrm {FJT}}$ and ${\textrm {STT}}$ , that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is best seen as a misleadingly formulated version of ${\textrm {STT}}$ .

7.1 ${\textrm {FJT}}$

Since entities do not cumulate up the types in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , its quantifier rules must be more restrictive than $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s (see Section 1.2). Indeed, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ has exactly the same quantifier rules as ${\textrm {STT}}$ (see Section 1.1). Consequently, in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , you cannot generalize about everything that has a type $2$ property by writing $\forall x^1(a^2(x^1) \rightarrow \phi (x^1))$ .Footnote 47 In ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , that formula generalizes over every type 1 property that has $a^2$ , but it says nothing about any objects that have it. To cover everything that might have $a^2$ , we must conjoin that formula with $\forall x^0(a^2(x^0) \rightarrow \phi (x^0))$ . Indeed, to generalize over everything that might have a type n property, we will need n conjuncts. This is illustrated by Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Linnebo11, p. 55] version of Comprehension:

  • ${FJT}$ -Comprehension. $\exists z^n\bigwedge _{i < n}\forall x^i (z^n(x^i) \leftrightarrow \phi _i(x^i))$ , for each $n> 0$ , whenever each $\phi _i(x^i)$ is well-formed and does not contain $z^n$ .

The various $\phi _i$ s need have nothing in common, so this is an instance of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension:

$$ \begin{align*}\exists z^2(\forall x^1(z^2(x^1) \leftrightarrow x^1=x^1)\land\forall x^0(z^2(x^0) \leftrightarrow x^0 \neq x^0)).\end{align*} $$

As Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, p. 61] observe, this entails $\forall x^0 \forall y^1\phantom {)} x^0 \mathrel {\not \equiv } y^1$ , where $\mathrel {\equiv }$ is defined as before. More generally, in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , if $n \neq m$ then $\forall x^n \forall y^m\phantom {(}x^n\mathrel {\not \equiv } y^m$ . So ${\textrm {FJT}}$ contradicts $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s Type-Raising principle (see Section 1.2).

7.2 ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is finitary

In formulating ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension, we have reverted to using natural numbers as type indices, rather than allowing that types might be transfinite (contrast the formulation of $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension in Section 1.2). We have done this for a simple reason: formulating ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension for a transfinite type, $\beta $ , would require infinitary conjunction:

$$ \begin{align*}\exists z^\beta \bigwedge_{\alpha < \beta} \forall x^\alpha (z^\beta (x^\alpha) \leftrightarrow \phi_\alpha(x^\alpha)).\end{align*} $$

But ${\textrm {FJT}}$ does not allow for infinitary conjunction. Consequently, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ cannot comprehend any transfinite types.Footnote 48

Much of our discussion of $\textrm {CTT}$ focussed on the Sets-from-Types Theorem (see Section 23). However, due to its finitary nature, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ cannot establish any similar result. Indeed, if we add surrogates for purity and extensionality to ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , the resulting theory is decidable.Footnote 49

7.3 Interpreting ${\textrm {FJT}}$ ’s types

Having discussed the Sets-from-Types Theorem, we then argued that $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions cannot be justified semantically (see Section 4). We began with Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, pp. 282–283] observation that, even if we stuck with the stringent formation rules for $\textrm {CTT}$ , we could always apply $b^\beta $ to $a^\alpha $ in $\textrm {CTT}$ with the formula $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ , which is defined as follows (where $\gamma = \max (\alpha , \beta )+1$ ):

$$ \begin{align*} a^\alpha \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^\beta & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} (\exists x^{\gamma} \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta) x^{\gamma}(a^\alpha). \end{align*} $$

We then argued that, since every type of entity can be applied to every type of entity in $\textrm {CTT}$ , there can be no barrier to introducing untyped variables.

This line of argument is not straightforwardly applicable to ${\textrm {FJT}}$ . Since entities do not cumulate up the types in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , $b^n$ is not identical to any entity of type $k \neq n$ . So, as Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, sec. 7] stress, it is doubtful whether $a^m \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^n$ , i.e., $(\exists x^{k} \mathrel {\equiv } b^n) x^{k}(a^m)$ with $k = \max (m,n)+1$ , provides us with a way of applying $b^n$ to $a^m$ in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ .

Nonetheless, we are still left with the question of how to justify the type-restrictions imposed by ${\textrm {FJT}}$ . Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, pp. 45–47] explicitly intend to provide ${\textrm {FJT}}$ with some version of the conceptual semantics, but it is unclear which version they could have in mind. The referentialist version that we discussed in Section 5.2 licenses the use of an untyped variable; the Fregean version that we discussed in Section 5.3 justifies ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions; so it seems that neither of these versions of the conceptual semantics could serve their purpose.

In fact, appearances are somewhat misleading here. It is true that, when ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is taken at face value, the Fregean semantics cannot justify its type-restrictions. However, it turns out that the Fregean semantics can make good sense of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , if its terms are interpreted as being systematically ambiguous, in the following way: in ‘ $c^2(b^1)$ ’, ‘ $c^2$ ’ expresses a type $2$ property, but in ‘ $c^2(a^0)$ ’, it expresses a type $1$ property. (Compare the interpretation of $\textrm {CTT}$ in ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ of Section 5.4.)Footnote 50

This ambiguity can easily be handled by augmenting ${\textrm {STT}}$ with a theory of type-lowering relations. We start by introducing a type-lowering relation, $\triangleright $ , from type $2$ to type $1$ . We then read ‘ $c^2(b^1)$ ’ verbatim, but treat ‘ $c^2(a^0)$ ’ as shorthand for ‘ $\forall x^1 (c^2\triangleright x^1\rightarrow x^1(a^0))$ ’. This latter formula is perfectly well-formed according to ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-constraints, and the idea can be extended across all types. The resulting theory is ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ . We can then prove that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ and ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ are definitionally equivalent. (For details and proof, see Appendix D.)

We think that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is best understood as a (somewhat misleading) formulation of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ . To begin with, there is no obvious reason to resist this interpretation of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ . Linnebo and Rayo had a clear technical reason for refusing to interpret $\textrm {CTT}$ via ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ : the major selling point of $\textrm {CTT}$ was meant to be its ability to accommodate transfinite types (see Section 6). But, as we saw in Section 7.2, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is just as limited to finite types as ${\textrm {STT}}$ . So ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , like ${\textrm {STT}}$ , cannot go beyond Finite Optimism.

Not only is there no reason for Florio and Jones to resist the interpretation of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ as ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ , there is good reason for them adopt it. Their Reference Florio and Jones[10] main aim is to argue that cumulative type theories can accommodate absolute generality. However, as we will now show, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ can accommodate absolute generality iff it is taken as a mere notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ .

7.4 ${\textrm {STT}}$ accommodates absolute generality

We start by explaining how ${\textrm {STT}}$ accommodates absolute generality.

In traditional set-theoretic semantics, domains are taken to be sets. In ${\textrm {STT}}$ , we can think of them as properties. For example, we can think of a domain of objects as a type 1 property, $d^1$ , and we can say that $x^0$ is in that domain iff $d^1(x^0)$ . As Williamson Reference Williamson[43] clearly explains, there is a real advantage to thinking of domains in this type-theoretic way. There is no set of all objects, and so if we think of domains as sets, unrestricted quantification over all objects is impossible. But ${\textrm {STT}}$ straightforwardly supplies a type $1$ property, $U^1$ , held by all objects, i.e.:Footnote 51

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x^0 U^1(x^0).\end{align*} $$

(Nothing special is signified by our use of a capitalized ‘U’ here; it simply aids readability.)

Whilst $U^1$ includes all the objects, one might worry that it is still restricted, since it includes no type $1$ properties. But, in the context of ${\textrm {STT}}$ , this worry is toothless; no sense can be made of this idea in ${\textrm {STT}}$ . To regard $U^1$ as restricted, we would have to be able to make sense of the idea of a more inclusive domain, which contains both objects and properties.Footnote 52 But that is incoherent in ${\textrm {STT}}$ . To say ‘d contains both objects and properties’ is to say $\exists x^0\exists y^1(d(x^0) \land d(y^1))$ , which is just ungrammatical in ${\textrm {STT}}$ . For $d(x^0)$ to be grammatical, d must be type $1$ ; for $d(y^1)$ to be grammatical, d must be type $2$ ; but every term has a unique type.

Suppose, then, we introduce suitably typed domains, $d^1$ and $d^2$ . In ${\textrm {STT}}$ , these domains are incommensurable, to use Williamson’s [Reference Williamson43, p. 458] phrase. This does not mean that $d^1$ and $d^2$ have different members; it means that we cannot even express the idea that they have the same (or different) members. We might put this by saying that, in ${\textrm {STT}}$ , we cannot articulate a univocal notion of Thing or Entity which applies to both objects and properties. (We can still talk about ‘type $0$ entities’, ‘type $1$ entities’, etc., but we cannot think of ‘entity’ as a recurring categorematic component in these constructions.) So, if a first-order quantifier quantifies over all objects, then it quantifies over absolutely every thing it makes sense to imagine that it might quantify over.

We can put the same point slightly differently by drawing on Florio and Jones’ [Reference Florio and Jones10, p. 49] explication of unrestrictedness: ‘an unrestricted domain is a domain such that true universal quantification over it precludes there from being absolutely any counterexamples whatsoever.’Footnote 53 This informal explication can be converted into a formal definition in ${\textrm {STT}}$ . To say that ‘everything melted’ is true over the domain things in the freezer is just to say that $\forall x(x \mbox{ is in the freezer }\rightarrow x \textrm { melted})$ . More generally, to say that $\forall x^{n-1} y^{n}(x^{n-1})$ is true over domain $d^{n}$ is just to say $\forall x^{n-1}(d^{n}(x^{n-1}) \rightarrow y^{n}(x^{n-1}))$ . To say that there are absolutely no counterexamples to this restricted generalization is to say that the generalization still holds good even when we lift the restriction, and return to $\forall x^{n-1} y^{n}(x^{n-1})$ . And finally, to say that there are absolutely no counterexamples to any true quantification over $d^{n}$ is just to generalize over all $y^{n}$ . Assembling this, we obtain, for all $n> 0$ :

  1. (1) $d^{n}$ is unrestricted $\mathrel {\textrm {iff}_{\textrm {df}}}$

    $$ \begin{align*}\forall y^{n}(\forall x^{n-1}(d^{n}(x^{n-1})\rightarrow y^{n}(x^{n-1}))\rightarrow \forall x^{n-1}y^{n}(x^{n-1})).\end{align*} $$

This definition is adequate because, in ${\textrm {STT}}$ , only generalizations of the form $\forall x^{n-1} y^{n}(x^{n-1})$ can be true over $d^{n}$ . And $U^1$ , as introduced at the start of this subsection, is unrestricted according to (1): since $\forall x^0U^1(x^0)$ , if $\forall x^0(U^1(x^0)\rightarrow y^1(x^0))$ , it immediately follows that $\forall x^0 y^1(x^0)$ . More generally, within ${\textrm {STT}}$ , it is obvious that $d^{n}$ is unrestricted iff $\forall x^{n-1} d^{n}(x^{n-1})$ .

7.5 Absolute generality in ${\textrm {FJT}}$

We have seen that ${\textrm {STT}}$ can accommodate absolute generality. So, if we read ${\textrm {FJT}}$ as a (misleadingly formulated) notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ , then ${\textrm {FJT}}$ can equally accommodate absolute generality. But, as we will now show, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ cannot accommodate absolute generality if it is taken at face-value.

To establish this, we will assume in what follows that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is to be taken at face-value, so that $d^2(y^1)$ and $d^2(x^0)$ apply the very same type $2$ property to $y^1$ and $x^0$ . (That assumption will remain in force until we explicitly lift it in Section 7.7.) So understood, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ allows type $2$ properties to serve as domains containing both objects and type 1 properties. In fact, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ delivers a domain, $U^2$ , which contains all type $1$ properties and all objects, i.e., such that:Footnote 54

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x^1U^2(x^1) \land \forall x^0U^2(x^0)\end{align*} $$

But now first-order quantification becomes a form of restricted quantification: in a clear sense, $U^1$ is a restriction of $U^2$ , since $U^2$ contains everything in $U^1$ , and more besides.Footnote 55

The point here is that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ does treat objects and type $1$ properties as a species of a single genus. Indeed, for each $n>0$ , we can think of Thing $^{n}$ as the property $U^{n}$ such that $\bigwedge _{m < n} \forall x^mU^{n}(x^m)$ . So in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , it makes sense, and is true, to say that first-order quantifiers quantify over some things but not others.Footnote 56

Again, we can make the same point in terms of Florio and Jones’ idea that $d^n$ is unrestricted iff there are absolutely no counterexamples to any universal generalization which is true over $d^n$ . Applied to ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , this does not quite yield a simple definition of unrestrictedness,Footnote 57 but it does yield a schematic necessary condition for unrestrictedness: if $d^{n}$ is unrestricted, and $y^{m}$ is true of everything in $d^{n}$ that it can be meaningfully applied to, then $y^m$ is true of absolutely everything it can be meaningfully applied to. Formalizing this intuitive idea, we obtain the following, for all $m,n> 0$ :

  1. (2) $d^{n}$ is unrestricted $\rightarrow $ $\qquad\qquad\phantom{sssssss}\forall y^{m}(\bigwedge _{i < \min (m, n)}\forall x^{i}(d^{n}(x^{i})\rightarrow y^{m}(x^{i}))\rightarrow \bigwedge _{i < m}\forall x^{i} y^{m}(x^{i})).$

This makes $U^1$ restricted, since ${\textrm {FJT}}$ yields an $H^2$ which applies to every object but to no type $1$ property, i.e., such that:Footnote 58

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x^1\lnot H^2(x^1) \land \forall x^0H^2(x^0).\end{align*} $$

Clearly $\forall x^0(U^1(x^{0}) \rightarrow H^2(x^0))$ , but $\lnot \forall x^1 H^2(x^1)$ ; so $U^1$ is restricted by (2).Footnote 59 A similar argument shows that every domain of every type is restricted in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ .Footnote 60 (And the same style of argument shows that no domain is unrestricted in $\textrm {CTT}$ .)Footnote 61

7.6 Florio and Jones on (R=U)

Our argument that every domain is restricted in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ was based on Florio and Jones’ own explication of unrestrictedness. But they thought that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ could accommodate absolute generality. In this subsection, we will lay out their reasoning, and explain why it was mistaken.

Alongside their explication of unrestrictedness, Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, p. 51] introduce a further notion: a domain is Russellian for a generalization $\forall v Fv$ iff it coincides with the range of significance of the predicate F, i.e., the range of things that F can be meaningfully applied to. They then propose [Reference Florio and Jones10, pp. 51–53]:

  • (R=U) A domain is Russellian iff it is unrestricted.

Here is the idea behind (R=U): a counterexample to $\forall v Fv$ would be something of which F is false; but F does not say anything (whether true or false) of the things which fall outside of its range of significance; so if $\forall v Fv$ is true over d, and d is Russellian for $\forall v Fv$ , then there cannot be any counterexamples to $\forall v Fv$ ; so d is unrestricted for $\forall v Fv$ .

Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, pp. 57–58] attempt to use (R=U) as follows. The domain $U^1$ is Russellian for the generalization $\forall x^0 a^1(x^0)$ : after all, type 1 terms express type 1 properties, and type 1 properties apply meaningfully only to objects.Footnote 62 So if we read $\forall x^0 a^1(x^0)$ as a quantification over $U^1$ , then by (R=U) it is unrestricted. Whilst $U^1$ is a strict sub-domain of $U^2$ , none of the extra entities in $U^2$ fall within $a^1$ ’s range of significance.

Our basic problem with (R=U) is quite simple: there is a fundamental mismatch between the R and the U. Unrestrictedness is normally understood in absolute terms: either a domain is absolutely unrestricted, or it is not. By contrast, Florio and Jones’ notion of Russellianness is a relative matter: a domain is not just Russellian full stop; it is only ever Russellian for a generalization $\forall v Fv$ . This basic problem can be overcome in ${\textrm {STT}}$ , but not in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ .

In ${\textrm {STT}}$ , a property $d^{n}$ can (meaningfully) be a domain for, and only for, generalizations of the form $\forall x^{n-1} y^{n}(x^{n-1})$ . After all, if we attempt to relativize the generalization $\forall y^{m}(x^i)$ to $d^{n}$ , obtaining $\forall x^i(d^{n}(x^i) \rightarrow y^{m}(x^i))$ , then the result is grammatical in ${\textrm {STT}}$ iff $n = m = i+1$ . Consequently, the relativity involved in Russellianness can be safely ignored: it would not even make sense to say that $d^{n}$ is Russellian for $\forall x^{m-1} y^{m}(x^{m-1})$ when $n\neq m$ . Indeed, since the range of significance of any type n property in ${\textrm {STT}}$ is always exactly the type $n\mathord {-}1$ entities, we can say that $d^{n}$ is Russellian $\mathrel {\textrm {iff}_{\textrm {df}}} \forall x^{n-1} d^{n}(x^{n-1})$ . Using (1) from Section 7.4, we can then prove (R=U) for ${\textrm {STT}}$ .

In ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , by contrast, a property $d^n$ can (meaningfully) be a domain for generalizations $\forall x^i y^m(x^i)$ with $n \neq m$ , so we cannot simply ignore the relativity in Russellianess. Let us, then, try to accommodate it. Officially, a domain is supposed to be Russellian for a generalization. However, since the range of significance of any type m property in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is always exactly the type $k < m$ entities, all that really matters is the type of the predicate used in the generalization. This leads to an explicitly relativized notion of Russellianness as follows:

  1. (3) $d^{n}$ is ${m}$ -Russellian $\mathrel {\textrm {iff}_{\textrm {df}}}$ all and only the type $k < m$ entities have $d^{n}$

    i.e., ${\bigl (\bigwedge _{k < m}\kern-1pt\forall y^k \bigvee _{i < n} (\exists x^i \kern-2pt\mathrel {\equiv }\kern-2pt y^k)d^{n}(x^i)\kern-1pt\bigr ) \kern1pt{\land}\kern1pt \bigl (\bigwedge _{i < n}\kern-1.5pt\forall x^{i}(d^{n}(x^{i}) \kern0.5pt{\rightarrow} \bigvee _{k < m}\kern-1pt\exists y^{k} x^{i} \kern-2pt\mathrel {\equiv }\kern-2pt y^{k}\kern-1pt)\kern-1pt\bigr )\kern-1pt.}$

The first conjunct captures the idea that every type $k < m$ entity has $d^{n}$ ; it says that every type $k < m$ entity is an entity in $d^{n}$ . The second conjunct captures the idea that only the type $k < m$ entities have $d^{n}$ ; it says that every (type $i < n$ ) entity in $d^{n}$ is a type $k < m$ entity.Footnote 63 This definition allows us (meaningfully) to ask whether $d^{n}$ is m-Russellian, for any n and m. Furthermore, if $n < m$ , then $d^{n}$ is not m-Russellian. In particular, $U^1$ is not $2$ -Russellian. However, $U^1$ is $1$ -Russellian. So, in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , Russellianness is significantly relativized.

To make sense of (R=U) in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ , then, Florio and Jones must relativize the notion of unrestrictedness, so that it matches the relativity in Russellianness. Tacitly, they do exactly this, describing domains as unrestricted for certain generalizations [Reference Florio and Jones10, e.g., pp. 52–53]. Florio and Jones do not define this relative sense of ‘unrestricted’, but we can easily provide a definition on their behalf. To say that $d^{n}$ is unrestricted with regard to type m is, presumably, to say this: if $y^{m}$ is true of everything in $d^{n}$ that it can be meaningfully applied to, then it is true of absolutely everything it can be meaningfully applied to. Formalizing this, we obtain the following, for all $m,n>0$ :

  1. (4) $d^{n}$ is $m\textrm {-unrestricted} \mathrel {\textrm {iff}_{\textrm {df}}}$

  2. $\qquad\qquad\forall y^{m}(\bigwedge _{i < \min (m, n)}\forall x^{i}(d^{n}(x^{i})\rightarrow y^{m}(x^{i}))\rightarrow \bigwedge _{i < m}\forall x^{i} y^{m}(x^{i})).$

Indeed, this just turns (2), which is a schematic necessary condition on unrelativized unrestrictedness, into a definition of relativized m-unrestrictedness.

We can now understand (R=U) thus: a domain is m-Russellian iff it is m-unrestricted. But so understood, (R=U) is false: $U^2$ is $1$ -unrestricted but not $1$ -Russellian, with $U^2$ as given in Section 7.5. Moreover, we do not need any principle like (R=U) to determine whether a given domain is m-unrestricted; we can just use definition (4). For example, it is clear from (4) that $U^1$ is $1$ -unrestricted but $2$ -restricted. More generally, $d^{n}$ is m-unrestricted iff both $n \geq m$ and $\bigwedge _{i < m}\forall x^i d^{n}(x^i)$ .

The only remaining question is whether the salient notion of unrestrictedness in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is the absolute notion governed by (2), or the relative notion defined by (4). We think it is completely clear that the relevant notion is the absolute one. After all, the debate here is about absolute generality. It would be false advertising to enter that debate, promising to vindicate unrestricted quantification, and then only deliver relatively unrestricted quantification. To emphasise this point, return to the example of $U^1$ : evidently, $U^1$ is $1$ -unrestricted but $2$ -restricted, as defined by (4). Precisely because $U^1$ is $2$ -restricted, though, there is a clear sense in which $U^1$ is restricted simpliciter. In particular, with $H^2$ as given at the end of Section 7.5, everything which is $U^1$ is $H^2$ , i.e., $\forall x^0(U^1(x^0) \rightarrow H^2(x^0))$ , but some entities are not $H^2$ , in that $\exists x^1 \lnot H^2(x^1)$ .

Indeed, this is exactly where Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, p. 57] go wrong. They recognise that you can find a type $1$ entity not in $U^1$ , but say: ‘it does not entail that F is meaningfully predicable of that entity’, where $\forall x^0 F (x^0)$ is the generalization under consideration. However, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ has precisely that entailment when F’s type is $> 1$ , as in the case of $F = H^2$ .

7.7 ${\textrm {FJT}}$ : the case for ambiguity

It might be helpful to end our discussion of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ by summarizing our case for reading it as a mere notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ .

First. We see no reason not to read ${\textrm {FJT}}$ in this way. Linnedo and Rayo could not read ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ as a notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ , because they wanted to extend ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ into the transfinite. But ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is as finitary as ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ .

Second. If we take ${\textrm {FJT}}$ at face-value, then it is unclear how we should interpret it. Florio and Jones explicitly intended to give ${\textrm {FJT}}$ a conceptual semantics, but we know of no version of that semantics which could justify ${\textrm {FJT}}$ ’s type-restrictions, taken at face-value.

Third. If we take ${\textrm {FJT}}$ at face-value, then it cannot accommodate absolute generality. However, if we read ${\textrm {FJT}}$ as a notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ , then it can supply absolutely unrestricted domains.

8 Conclusion

In this paper, we have argued for four main claims:

  1. (a) $\textrm {CTT}$ cannot be used to close the gap between an ideological hierarchy of types and an ontological hierarchy of sets (Section 2 and 3).

  2. (b) $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-restrictions are superfluous, on any semantics (Section 4).

  3. (c) ${\textrm {STT}}$ ’s type-restrictions can be justified by a Fregean semantics, which also provides us with a way to resist Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument in favour of $\textrm {CTT}$ (Sections 5 and 6).

  4. (d) ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is best understood as a misleading formulation of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ (Section 7).

We start with (a). The Sets-from-Types Theorem allows us to simulate ${\textrm {Zr}}$ within $\textrm {CTT}$ . But deep mathematical differences remain between ${\textrm {Zr}}$ and and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ , rendering $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ unsuitable as a framework for mathematical foundations. Furthermore, the Sets-from-Types Theorem cannot allay any ontological worries we might have about set theory: $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s type-indices are supplied externally, and so the Sets-from-Types Theorem merely shunts our ontological worries into the metalanguage.

Next is (b). $\textrm {CTT}$ is a remarkably relaxed type theory: it allows us to apply every type of entity to every type of entity. But it still retains the constraint that all of its variables are typed and, in $\textrm {CTT}$ , that type-restriction is superfluous. Once every type of entity can be applied to every type of entity, there can be no barrier to introducing untyped variables.

We come now to (c). The strict type-restrictions imposed by ${\textrm {STT}}$ can be justified by the Fregean semantics. On this semantics, different types of term play fundamentally different types of semantic role, so that they cannot be meaningfully intersubstituted. Moreover, this semantics yields a principled reason to reject Naïve Optimism, a crucial premise in Linnebo and Rayo’s Semantic Argument.

We end with (d). Florio and Jones’ ${\textrm {FJT}}$ was meant to be a partially cumulative type theory, but we argue it is best understood as a notational variant of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ : taking ${\textrm {FJT}}$ at face-value leaves it unable to accommodate absolute generality; whereas ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ —which is definitionally equivalent to ${\textrm {FJT}}$ —provides absolutely unrestricted domains of quantification.

A Elementary facts about CTT

The remainder of this paper comprises technical appendices, covering the formal results mentioned in the main text. We will start with some elementary observations about $\textrm {CTT}$ . As mentioned in Section 1.2, for each ordinal $\tau $ , we have a theory ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ .Footnote 64 Recall that we have explicitly defined $\mathrel {\equiv }$ and $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ , for any types $\alpha $ and $\beta $ and where $\gamma = \max (\alpha , \beta )+1$ :

$$ \begin{align*} a^\alpha \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} \forall x^{\gamma}(x^{\gamma}(a^\alpha) \leftrightarrow x^\gamma(b^\beta))\\ a^\alpha \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^\beta & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} (\exists x^{\gamma} \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta)x^{\gamma}(a^\alpha). \end{align*} $$

In what follows, we will frequently invoke the following simple facts about $\mathrel {\equiv }$ and $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ ; crudely, they allow us to move seamlessly between different type-levels:

Lemma 1. If $\alpha \leq \beta $ and $\beta + 1 < \tau $ , then ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ proves: $\forall a^\alpha \exists b^\beta \phantom {)}a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $

Proof. By ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{\beta +1}_{\beta +1}}$ , we have $\forall x^{\beta +1}(x^{\beta +1}(a^\alpha ) \leftrightarrow x^{\beta +1}(a^\alpha ))$ , i.e., $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } a^\alpha $ ; so $\forall a^\alpha \exists b^\beta \ a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ by ${\exists {\textrm {I}}^{\beta }_{\alpha }}$ followed by ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{\alpha }_{\alpha }}$ .□

Lemma 2. For any $\phi $ , and any $\alpha , \beta , \gamma $ with $\max (\alpha , \beta , \gamma ) + 2 < \tau $ , ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ proves:

  1. (1) if $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ and $\phi (a^\alpha )$ , then $\phi (b^\beta )$ , when this is well-formed

  2. (2) if $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta \mathrel {\equiv } c^\gamma $ , then $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } c^\gamma $

  3. (3) if $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ and $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } c^\gamma $ , then $b^\beta \mathrel {\varepsilon } c^\gamma $

  4. (4) if $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ and $c^\gamma \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^\alpha $ , then $c^\gamma \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $

Proof. (1) Suppose $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ and $\phi (a^\alpha )$ . Let $\delta = \max (\alpha , \beta )$ ; by $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension there is some $c^{\delta +1}$ such that $\forall x^{\delta }(c^{\delta +1}(x^{\delta }) \leftrightarrow \phi (x^{\delta }))$ . Since $\phi (a^\alpha )$ , by ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{\delta }_{\alpha }}$ we have that $c^{\delta +1}(a^\alpha )$ . Since $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ , i.e., $\forall z^{\delta +1}(z^{\delta +1}(a^\alpha ) \leftrightarrow z^{\delta +1}(b^\beta ))$ , by ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{\delta +1}_{\delta +1}}$ we have that $c^{\delta +1}(b^\beta )$ . Now $\phi (b^\beta )$ by ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{\delta }_{\beta }}$ .

(2)–(4) We leave these to the reader. They are not completely immediate consequences of (1), since the definitions of $\mathrel {\equiv }$ and $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ are typically ambiguous.□

Lemma 3. If $\max (\alpha , \beta ) + 2 < \tau $ , then ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ proves: $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{\beta +1} \leftrightarrow (\exists x^\beta \mathrel {\equiv } a^\alpha ) b^{\beta +1}(x^\beta )$

Proof. By Type-Founded and Lemmas 1 and 2.□

It is worth emphasising that Type-Founded and Type-Basis are independent from $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s other axioms. To show this, we begin by building an ill-founded set-theoretic structure, $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $\textbf {a} = \{\emptyset , \textbf {a}\}$ ; now define:

$$ \begin{align*} A_1 &:= \textbf{a} & A_{n+1} &:= \wp(A_n) & A & := \bigcup_{n < \omega} A_n. \end{align*} $$

So $A_2 = \{\emptyset , \{\emptyset \}, \{\textbf {a}\}, \textbf {a}\}$ . Let $\mathcal {A}$ be the structure whose domain is A and which interprets $\in $ verbatim; evidently, $\mathcal {A}$ is ill-founded. Using a slight tweak of the class semantics of Section 4.2, we now create a model, $\mathcal {M}$ , of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ without Type-Founded. We start by defining a ranking function $\rho : A \longrightarrow \mathbb {N}$ on $\mathcal {A}$ as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} \rho(\emptyset) &= 0 & \rho(\textbf{a}) &= 1 & \rho(c) = n \mbox{ iff } c \in A_{n} \setminus A_{n-1.} \end{align*} $$

So $\rho (\{\emptyset \}) = 2$ . Now we stipulate that $\mathcal {M}$ ’s type n entities are all those $c \in A$ such that $\rho (c) \leq n$ , and applications are stipulated to hold as follows, for all $m < n$ and all $b, c \in A$ :

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{M} \models c^n(b^m) \mbox{ iff } b \in c. \end{align*} $$

It is easy to confirm that $\mathcal {M}$ models ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ without Type-Founded. But, by construction, $c^m \mathrel {\equiv } c^n$ whenever $\min (m, n) \geq \rho (c)$ . So $\textbf {a}^2(\textbf {a}^1)$ with $\textbf {a}^2 \mathrel {\equiv } \textbf {a}^1$ , and hence $\textbf {a}^1 \mathrel {\varepsilon } \textbf {a}^1$ . So $\mathcal {M}$ violates Type-Founded. Admittedly, Type-Basis holds in $\mathcal {M}$ , but we can violate it with a similar construction: start with a Quine atom $\textbf {b} = \{\textbf {b}\}$ ; let $B_0 = \textbf {b}$ and $B_{n+1} = \wp (B_n)$ ; define $\rho (c) = n$ iff $c \in B_n \setminus B_{n-1}$ ; and note that $\textbf {b}^0 \mathrel {\varepsilon } \textbf {b}^0$ .

B Obtaining ${\textrm {Zr}}$ in ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$

In Section 2, we stated the Sets-from-Types Theorem. In this appendix, we prove that result. We also introduce the interpreting theory, ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , and the interpreted theory, ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , and discuss how ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ deals with Replacement.

B.1 The theory ${\textrm {Zr}}$

The set theory which we simulate is ${\textrm {Zr}}$ . We can think of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ as arising by adding to ${\textrm {Z}}$ the principle that the sets are arranged in well-ordered levels; ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is therefore strictly stronger than ${\textrm {Z}}$ and strictly weaker than ${\textrm {ZF}}$ .Footnote 65 We follow Button’s Reference Button[5] formulation of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , starting with a core of definitions:

Definition 4. Say that h is a history, written Hist $(h)$ , iff $(\forall a \in h)\forall x(x \in a \leftrightarrow (\exists c \in h)x \subseteq c \in a)$ . Say that s is a level, written Lev $(s)$ , iff $\exists h({{{Hist}}}(h) \land \forall x(x \in s \leftrightarrow \exists c(x \subseteq c \in h)))$ .Footnote 66

Using these definitions, we can consider some axioms:

  • Extensionality $\forall a \forall b (\forall x(x \in a \leftrightarrow x \in b) \rightarrow a =b)$

  • Separation $\forall a \exists b \forall x(x \in b \leftrightarrow (\phi (x) \land x \in a))$ , for every $\phi $ not containing b

  • Stratification $\forall a (\exists s \supseteq a){\textit{Lev}}(s)$

  • Endless $\forall a \exists b\ a \in b$

  • Infinity $\exists a(\exists x\ x \in a \land (\forall x \in a)\exists y(x \in y \in a))$

The theory ${\textrm {LT}}$ has, as axioms, Extensionality, all instances of Separation, and Stratification, which serves as a principle of foundation. The theory ${\textrm {Zr}}$ adds Endless and Infinity to ${\textrm {LT}}$ . In what follows, these next two results will be extremely useful:Footnote 67

Lemma 5. Extensionality + Separation proves: if ${\textit{Lev}}(s)$ , then $s = \{x : \exists r({\textit{Lev}}(r) \land x \subseteq r \in s)\}$ .

Theorem 6. Extensionality + Separation proves: the levels are well-ordered by $\in $ , i.e.:

  1. (1) $\exists s({\textit{Lev}}(s) \land \phi (s)) \rightarrow \exists s({\textit{Lev}}(s) \land \phi (s) \land \lnot (\exists r \in s)({\textit{Lev}}(r) \land \phi (r)))$

  2. (2) $\forall s\forall t(({\textit{Lev}}(s) \land {\textit{Lev}}(t)) \rightarrow (s \in t \lor s = t \lor t \in s))$

This last result allows us to define the rank of a, written $\textrm {rank}(a)$ , within ${\textrm {LT}}$ , in terms of the $\in $ -least level with a as a subset.

B.2 The theory ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$

The theory ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ extends $\textrm {CTT}$ with two new principles.Footnote 68 First, we add a version of ‘extensionality’, for all $\alpha \leq \beta $ :

  • Type-Ext. $\forall a^{\alpha +1} \forall b^{\beta +1}([\forall x^\alpha (a^{\alpha +1}(x^\alpha ) \rightarrow b^{\beta +1}(x^\alpha )) \land {}$

    $\quad\forall x^\beta (b^{\beta +1}(x^\beta ) \rightarrow (\exists y^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } x^\beta )a^{\alpha +1}(y^\alpha ))] \rightarrow a^{\alpha +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^{\beta +1}).$

Second, to achieve ‘purity’, we add an axiom stating that there is exactly one object:

  • Type-Purity. $\forall x^0\forall y^0\ x^0 = y^0$

Note that, modulo $\textrm {CTT}$ ’s other axioms, Type-Founded follows from Type-Ext and Type-Purity.

To begin our simulation of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ within ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , we will show that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves ${\textrm {Extensionality}^{(\kappa )}}$ and ${\textrm {Separation}^{(\kappa )}}$ .

Lemma 7. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {\textrm {Extensionality}^{(\kappa )}}$ , whenever $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

Proof. Suppose $\kappa $ is a limit (the proof is easier when $\kappa $ is a successor). Without loss of generality, fix $\alpha \leq \beta < \kappa $ and suppose $\forall x^\kappa (x^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^\alpha \leftrightarrow x^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta )$ .

Using Lemma 1, find $a^{\alpha +1} \mathrel {\equiv } a^\alpha $ and $b^{\beta +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ . Suppose $a^{\alpha +1}(x^\alpha )$ . So $x^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha +1}$ by Lemma 3; by Lemma 1 there is $x^\kappa \mathrel {\equiv } x^\alpha $ , and $x^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha }$ by Lemma 2; so $x^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ , and now $b^{\beta +1}(x^\alpha )$ by Lemmas 2 and 3. Similar reasoning shows: if $b^{\beta +1}(x^\beta )$ then $(\exists y^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } x^\beta )a^{\alpha +1}(y^\alpha )$ . By Type-Ext, $a^{\alpha +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^{\beta +1}$ ; hence $a^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ by Lemma 2. Generalizing, for any $\alpha , \beta < \kappa $ :

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x^\kappa(x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\alpha \leftrightarrow x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^\beta) \rightarrow a^\alpha \mathrel{\equiv} b^\beta . \end{align*} $$

Now ${\textrm {Extensionality}^{(\kappa )}}$ holds, using Limit $^\kappa $ twice.□

Lemma 8. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {\textrm {Separation}^{(\kappa )}}$ , whenever $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

Proof. Suppose $\kappa $ is a limit (the proof is easier when $\kappa $ is a successor). Fix $\alpha < \kappa $ and $\phi $ such that $\phi (x^\kappa )$ is well-formed. Fix $a^\alpha $ and find $a^{\alpha +1} \mathrel {\equiv } a^\alpha $ by Lemma 1. Using $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension, fix $b^{\alpha +1}$ such that:

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x^\alpha(b^{\alpha+1}(x^\alpha) \leftrightarrow (\forall x^\kappa \mathrel{\equiv} x^\alpha)(\phi(x^\kappa) \land x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^{\alpha+1})).\end{align*} $$

Suppose $z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{\alpha +1}$ ; by Lemma 3 there is $z^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } z^\kappa $ such that $b^{\alpha +1}(z^\alpha )$ ; so using the biconditional, $\phi (z^\kappa ) \land z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha +1}$ . Conversely, suppose $\phi (z^\kappa ) \land z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha +1}$ ; by Type-Founded there is $z^\alpha \mathrel {\equiv } z^\kappa $ , and $(\forall x^\kappa \mathrel {\equiv } z^\alpha )(\phi (x^\kappa ) \land x^{\kappa } \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha +1})$ by Lemma 2; so $b^{\alpha +1}(z^\alpha )$ , and $z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{\alpha +1}$ by Lemma 3. Summarizing: $z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{\alpha +1} \leftrightarrow (\phi (z^\kappa ) \land z^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\alpha +1})$ . By Lemma 1 there is $b^\kappa \mathrel {\equiv } b^{\alpha +1}$ . Generalizing and using Lemma 2, for any $\alpha < \kappa $ :

$$ \begin{align*}\forall a^\alpha \exists b^\kappa \forall z^\kappa(z^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} b^\kappa \leftrightarrow (\phi(z^\kappa) \land z^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\alpha)).\end{align*} $$

Now ${\textrm {Separation}^{(\kappa )}}$ follows by the Limit $^\kappa $ -rule.□

Consequently, ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves Lemma ${\textrm {5}}^{(\kappa )}$ and Theorem ${\textrm {6}^{(\kappa )}}$ . The latter result states that the ${\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}$ s are well-ordered by $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ . Here, ‘ ${\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}$ ’ is the obvious translation of the definition of ‘ ${\textit{Lev}}$ ’; we also call these levels $^{(\kappa )}$ . In what follows, we also write things like $x^\kappa \subseteq ^{(\kappa )} y^\kappa $ for $(\forall v^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } x^\kappa )v^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^\kappa $ .

Our next goal is to show that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ simulates our set-theoretic principle of foundation, i.e., Stratification. We first need a small subsidiary lemma, which says (roughly) that any subset of a low-typed entity is itself low-typed:

Lemma 9. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash \forall a^\alpha (\forall b^\kappa \subseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\alpha )\exists x^\alpha \ b^\kappa \mathrel {\equiv } x^\alpha $ , whenever $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

Proof. Suppose $\alpha $ and $\kappa $ are limits (the proof is easier otherwise). Let $\beta < \kappa $ , and fix $b^\beta \subseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\alpha $ ; it suffices to show that $\exists x^\alpha \ b^\beta \mathrel {\equiv } x^\alpha $ , since we can then use Limit $^\kappa $ to establish the result.

If $\beta \leq \alpha $ , Lemma 1 immediately tells us that $\exists x^\alpha \ b^\beta \mathrel {\equiv } x^\alpha $ . Suppose instead that $\beta> \alpha $ . Fix $\gamma < \alpha $ , and suppose there is some $a^{\gamma +1} \mathrel {\equiv } a^\alpha $ . Using Lemma 1, let $b^{\beta +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ . By $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension, there is $c^{\gamma +1}$ such that:

$$ \begin{align*}\forall v^\gamma(c^{\gamma+1}(v^\gamma) \leftrightarrow b^{\beta+1}(v^\gamma)).\end{align*} $$

Using Lemmas 13: if $b^{\beta +1}(v^\beta )$ , then $v^\beta \mathrel {\varepsilon } a^{\gamma +1}$ since $b^\beta \subseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^{\gamma +1}$ , so that there is $y^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } v^\beta $ ; now $b^{\beta +1}(y^\gamma )$ , so that $c^{\gamma +1}(y^\gamma )$ . Generalizing, $\forall v^\beta (b^{\beta +1}(v^\beta ) \rightarrow (\exists y^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } v^\beta )c^{\gamma +1}(y^\gamma ))$ . By Type-Ext, $c^{\gamma +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^{\beta +1} \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta $ . Summarizing all this, we have established the following conditional, for each $\gamma < \alpha $ :

$$ \begin{align*}\exists x^{\gamma+1}\ a^\alpha \mathrel{\equiv} x^{\gamma+1} \rightarrow \exists x^{\gamma+1}\ b^\beta \mathrel{\equiv} x^{\gamma+1}.\end{align*} $$

Now, for reductio, suppose that $\forall x^\alpha \ b^\beta \mathrel {\not \equiv } x^\alpha $ . Then $\forall x^{\gamma +1}\ b^\beta \mathrel {\not \equiv } x^{\gamma +1}$ for all $\gamma < \alpha $ . So, by the relevant conditional, $\forall x^{\gamma +1}\ a^\alpha \mathrel {\not \equiv } x^{\gamma +1}$ . By the Limit $^\alpha $ -rule, $\forall x^\alpha \ a^\alpha \mathrel {\not \equiv } x^\alpha $ , a contradiction. Discharging the reductio, $\exists x^\alpha \ b^\beta \mathrel {\equiv } x^\alpha $ , as required.□

Lemma 10. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {\textrm {Stratification}^{(\kappa )}}$ , whenever $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

Proof. We will show that, for each $\beta \leq \kappa $ , ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ proves $\forall a^\beta (\exists s^\beta \supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\beta ){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^\beta )$ . This is an induction on $\beta $ in the metatheory, where our induction hypothesis is that for each $\alpha < \beta $ we have established $\forall a^\alpha (\exists s^\alpha \supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\alpha ){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^\alpha )$

Induction case when $\beta = 0$ . By Type-Founded, . So ${{\textit{Hist}}}^\kappa (a^0)$ and ${\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(a^0)$ , vacuously. So $\forall a^0(\exists s^0 \supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^0){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^0)$ .

Induction case when $\beta $ is a limit. Applying Lemmas 12 to our induction hypothesis, we have $\forall a^\alpha (\exists s^\beta \supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\alpha ){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^\beta )$ . Now $\forall a^\beta (\exists s^\beta \supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\beta ){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^\beta )$ , by the Limit $^\beta $ -rule.

Induction case when $\beta = \alpha + 1$ . Using $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension twice, find $h^{\beta }$ and $s^{\beta }$ such that

(1) $$ \begin{align} \forall x^\alpha&(h^{\beta}(x^\alpha) \leftrightarrow {\textit{Lev}}^{\kappa}(x^\alpha)) \end{align} $$
(2) $$ \begin{align} \forall x^\alpha&\phantom{(}s^{\beta}(x^\alpha). \end{align} $$

Combining these with the induction hypothesis, we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x^\alpha (s^{\beta}(x^\alpha) & \leftrightarrow (\exists c^\alpha \supseteq^{(\kappa)} x^\alpha)h^{\beta}(c^\alpha)). \end{align*} $$

Hence, by Lemmas 13 and 9:

(3) $$ \begin{align} \forall x^\kappa &(x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} s^{\beta} \leftrightarrow \exists c^\kappa(x^\kappa \subseteq^{(\kappa)} c^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} h^{\beta})). \end{align} $$

Next, applying ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{\kappa }_{\alpha }}$ and ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{\alpha }_{\alpha }}$ to Lemma ${\textrm {5}^{(\kappa )}}$ gives:

$$ \begin{align*} \forall a^\alpha&({\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa)}(a^\alpha) \rightarrow \forall x^\kappa(x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\alpha \leftrightarrow \exists c^\kappa({\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa)}(c^\kappa) \land x^\kappa \subseteq^{(\kappa)} c^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\alpha))). \end{align*} $$

So, by (1) and Lemmas 13:

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall a^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} h^{\beta})\forall x^\kappa(x^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\kappa \leftrightarrow (\exists c^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} h^{\beta})x^\kappa \subseteq^{(\kappa)} c^\kappa \mathrel{\varepsilon} a^\kappa), \end{align*} $$

i.e., $h^\beta $ is a history $^{(\kappa )}$ . So $s^\beta $ is a level $^{(\kappa )}$ , by (3). Moreover, for any $a^{\beta }$ , we have $a^\beta \subseteq ^{(\kappa )} s^\beta $ by (2) and Lemmas 13. So $\forall a^{\beta }(\exists s^{\beta }\supseteq ^{(\kappa )} a^\alpha ){\textit{Lev}}^{(\kappa )}(s^{\beta })$ .□

We have now established ${\textrm {LT}^{(\kappa )}}$ . To obtain ${\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}}$ , we need just two straightforward results, which we leave to the reader (they hold using $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension, Lemmas 13, and the Limit-rule).

Lemma 11. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {{\textrm {Endless}^{(\kappa )}}}$ , whenever $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ and $\kappa $ is a limit.

Lemma 12. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {{\textrm {Infinity}^{(\kappa )}}}$ , whenever $\kappa> \omega $ and $\kappa + 2 < \tau .$

Assembling Lemmas 712, we have the Sets-from-Types Theorem:

Theorem 13. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}} \vdash {\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}}$ for any limit $\kappa> \omega $ with $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ .

B.3 Replacement, and semantic considerations

We mentioned that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ sits strictly between ${\textrm {Z}}$ and ${\textrm {ZF}}$ . Specifically, ${\textrm {Zr}}$ does not include Replacement. To settle the status of Replacement with regard to ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ ,Footnote 69 we will move from proof theory to semantics, linking models of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ with models of ${\textrm {LT}}$ . (Recall that ${\textrm {LT}}$ is the subtheory of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ whose axioms are Extensionality, Separation and Stratification.)

In considering models of ${\textrm {LT}}$ , we restrict our attention to transitive models.Footnote 70 Recall that a structure $\mathcal {A}$ in the signature of set theory is transitive iff both $(\forall x \in A)x\subseteq A$ , and $(\forall a \in A)(\forall b \in A)(a \in b \leftrightarrow a \in ^{\mathcal {A}} b)$ . So membership and subsethood are absolute for transitive models. Also recall that being a (von Neumann) ordinal is absolute for transitive models,Footnote 71 and so is the notion of a set’s (ordinal) rank. (Recall from Appendix B.1 that we can define a set’s rank within ${\textrm {LT}}$ , and hence within ${\textrm {Zr}}$ .) Where $\mathcal {A}$ is a transitive model of ${{\textrm {LT}}}$ , let ${\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}$ be the least ordinal not in A itself.

Whilst we consider only transitive models of ${\textrm {LT}}$ , we will entertain non-standard models. A transitive model $\mathcal {A} \models {{\textrm {LT}}}$ is standard iff for any $\alpha < {{\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}}$ , every subset of $\{x \in A : {\textrm {rank}}(x) \leq \alpha \}$ is itself in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Given any model $\mathcal {M} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ with $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ , we can easily turn it into a transitive set-theoretic model, ${\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}$ , as follows: let ${\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}$ ’s domain comprise all the type $\kappa $ entities from $\mathcal {M}$ ; and let ${{\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}} \models a \in b$ iff $\mathcal {M} \models a \mathrel {\varepsilon } b$ .

Lemma 14. When $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ : if $\mathcal {M} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ , then ${\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}$ is isomorphic to a unique transitive model of ${\textrm {LT}}$ .

Proof. By Lemmas 710, ${{\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}} \models {{\textrm {LT}}}$ . The type indices are well-ordered. By the Limit-rule, Type-Founded, Type-Purity and Lemma 7, ${\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}$ ’s membership relation is extensional and well-founded. Now use Mostowski’s Collapsing Lemma.□

We can also move in the opposite direction, from transitive models of ${\textrm {LT}}$ to models of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ . In effect, we follow the class-semantics of Section 4.2, but tweaked to ban urelements and to allow for non-standard models of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , where a model of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ is standard iff for any entities of any type $\alpha $ (other than the greatest) in the model, some type $\alpha \mathord {+}1$ property in the model applies exactly to those entities.Footnote 72 Still, the basic plan is simple: start with a transitive model of ${\textrm {LT}}$ ; treat entities of different rank as being of different types; and read membership as ‘application’.

Unfortunately, there is a small wrinkle in implementing this plan, thanks to an irritating mismatch between the types of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ and a set’s rank. To illustrate: ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ ’s Limit-rule means that every type $\omega $ entity is of some finite type, but the ordinal $\omega $ has rank $\omega $ . To deal with this wrinkle, we define a function which (in effect) tells us how to map from ranks to types:

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha^* &= \begin{cases} \alpha&\mbox{if } \alpha < \omega\\ \alpha+1&\mbox{if } \alpha \geq \omega. \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

We can now implement our plan. Where $\mathcal {A}$ is a transitive model of ${\textrm {LT}}$ , define ${\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}$ as follows. Its denizens are just the members of A, and if ${{\textrm {rank}}}(x) = \alpha $ then x is treated as a type $\beta $ entity for all $\alpha ^* \leq \beta < {{\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}}^*$ . Then, we stipulate that ${{\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}} \models y^{\alpha }(x^{\alpha })$ iff $\mathcal {A} \models x \in y$ .

Lemma 15. Let $\mathcal {A} \models {{\textrm {LT}}}$ be transitive. Then ${{\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{{{\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}}^{*}}_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Moreover, $\mathcal {A}$ is standard iff ${\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}$ is standard.

Proof sketch. The quantifier-rules and Limit-rules are obviously sound. When $\mathrel {\equiv }$ and $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ are well-defined ${\textrm {CTT}^{{\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})^{*}}}}$ -expressions,Footnote 73 distinct entities $a^{\alpha }$ and $b^\beta $ are distinguished by $\{a^\alpha \}^{\alpha +1}$ , so $\mathrel {\equiv }^{{{\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}}}$ is identity and $\mathrel {\varepsilon }^{{{\textbf {C}\mathcal {A}}}}$ is membership. Type-Base and Type-Purity now hold, as $\mathcal {A}$ has exactly one rank- $0$ object, and it is empty. Type-Ext follows from Extensionality and simple reasoning about ranks. For $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension, fix $\phi $ and $\alpha $ with $\alpha +1 < {{\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}}^*$ ; we will show that:

$$ \begin{align*}{{\textbf{C}\mathcal{A}}} \models \exists z^{\alpha+1} \forall x^\alpha(z^{\alpha+1}(x^\alpha) \leftrightarrow \phi(x^\alpha)).\end{align*} $$

Let $\beta ^* = {\alpha +1}$ ; note that $\beta \in A$ , as $\mathcal {A}$ is transitive. Fix $s \in A$ such that $\mathcal {A}$ thinks that s is the $\in $ -least level with $\beta $ as a subset. By Separation on s in $\mathcal {A}$ , there is some $c \in A$ of rank $\leq \beta $ which serves as a witnessing value for $z^{\alpha +1}$ when regarded as an entity of type $\alpha +1$ . Finally, the remark about standardness is immediate from the construction.□

We now have the means to move between transitive models of ${\textrm {LT}}$ and models of ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Recalling that ${\textrm {LT}}$ is strictly weaker than ${\textrm {ZF}}$ , we can now settle the status of Replacement, in ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ , by using some well-known facts concerning models of ${\textrm {ZF}}$ :

Theorem 16. Fix $\kappa> \omega $ such that $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ :

  1. (1) If $\kappa $ is strongly inaccessible, every model of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ satisfies ${{\textrm {ZF}}^{(\kappa )}}$ .

  2. (2) If $\kappa $ is not strongly inaccessible, there are models of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ which violate ${{\textrm {ZF}}^{(\kappa )}}$ , and any model of ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ which satisfies ${{\textrm {ZF}}^{(\kappa )}}$ is non-standard.

Proof. (1) Let $\kappa $ be strongly inaccessible with $\mathcal {M} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . Using Theorem 13 and Lemma 14, obtain a transitive model $\mathcal {A} \cong {\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}} \models {\textrm {Zr}}$ . To show that $\mathcal {M} \models {{\textrm {ZF}}^{(\kappa )}}$ , it suffices to show that $\mathcal {A} \models \textrm {Replacement}$ . So: fix $a \in A$ and suppose $\mathcal {A} \models (\forall x \in a)\exists !y \phi (x,y)$ . Working outside $\mathcal {A}$ , let

$$ \begin{align*}\beta = \textrm{sup}\{{{\textrm{rank}}}(c) : \mathcal{A} \models (\exists x \in a)\phi(x,c)\}.\end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {A}$ is transitive and $\kappa $ is strongly inaccessible, $\beta \in A$ . So also $\{c : \mathcal {A} \models (\exists x \in a)\phi (x,c)\} \in A$ , by Separation in $\mathcal {A}$ on what $\mathcal {A}$ thinks is a level with $\beta $ as a subset.

(2) Here are two general facts about the $V_\alpha $ hierarchy:

$$ \begin{align*} V_\kappa \models {{\mbox{ZF }}}&\mbox{ iff } \kappa \mbox{ is strongly inaccessible}\\ V_{\kappa}\models {{\mbox{LT }}}&\mbox{ iff } \kappa> 0. \end{align*} $$

So suppose $\kappa> \omega $ is not strongly inaccessible. Fix $\sigma $ such that $\sigma ^* \geq \tau $ . Now, $V_\sigma $ is a transitive model of ${\textrm {LT}}$ and Ord ${{({V_\sigma })}} = \sigma $ . Using Lemma 15, obtain ${{\textbf {C}V_{\sigma }}} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ . By construction, ${\textbf {L}^{\kappa }{\textbf {C}V_{\sigma }}} = V_{\kappa }$ . Since $V_{\kappa } \nvDash \textrm {Replacement}$ , also ${{\textbf {C}V_{\sigma }}} \nvDash {{\textrm {Replacement}^{(\kappa )}}}$ .

For the second clause: suppose $\mathcal {M} \models {\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ and $\mathcal {M} \models {{\textrm {ZF}}^{(\kappa )}}$ , with $\kappa $ not strongly inaccessible. Use Lemma 14 to obtain a unique transitive model $\mathcal {A} \cong {{\textbf {L}^{\kappa }\mathcal {M}}}$ . Since $\mathcal {A} \models {\textrm {ZF}}$ but ${\textit{Ord}({\mathcal {A}})}$ is not strongly inaccessible, $\mathcal {A}$ is non-standard.□

C Definitional equivalence for ${{\textrm {CTT}}^{\omega }}$

In Section 5.4, we stated that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ is definitionally equivalent to ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ . In this appendix, we define ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ , and prove the equivalence.

${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ augments ${\textrm {STT}}$ with a new function symbol, $\mathord {\uparrow }$ , for each n, which takes a type n entity as input and outputs a type $n\mathord {+}1$ entity.Footnote 74 So, for example, $b^2(\mathord {\uparrow } a^0)$ and $c^5(\mathord {\uparrow }\mathord {\uparrow } b^2)$ are well-formed. ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ retains ${\textrm {STT}}$ -Comprehension; this holds for formulas containing $\mathord {\uparrow }$ . ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ then has axioms ensuring that $\mathord {\uparrow }$ is injective, preserves property-possession, and delivers well-foundedness:

  • Up-Inject. $\forall x^n \forall y^n(\mathord {\uparrow } x^n = \mathord {\uparrow } y^n \rightarrow x^n = y^n)$

  • Up-Possess. $\forall x^n \forall y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow } y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow } x^n) \leftrightarrow y^{n+1}(x^n))$

  • Up-Founded. $\forall x^{n+1}\forall y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow } y^{n+1}(x^{n+1}) \rightarrow \exists z^n\ x^{n+1} = \mathord {\uparrow } z^n)$

  • Up-Base. $\forall x^0\forall y^0 \lnot \mathord {\uparrow } y^0(x^0)$

For readability, where $m> n$ , we write $\mathord {\uparrow }_{m}a^n$ for the result of applying $m - n$ instances of $\mathord {\uparrow }$ to $a^n$ , yielding a type m entity; so $\mathord {\uparrow }_{4} a^0$ abbreviates $\mathord {\uparrow }\mathord {\uparrow }\mathord {\uparrow }\mathord {\uparrow } a^0$ , and $c^5(\mathord {\uparrow }_{4}b^2)$ abbreviates $c^5(\mathord {\uparrow }\mathord {\uparrow } b^2)$ . Simple induction, which we leave to the reader, shows that ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ proves generalizations of our new axioms; specifically, for each $m> n$ :

  • $\forall x^n \forall y^n(\mathord {\uparrow }_{m} x^n = \mathord {\uparrow }_{m} y^n \rightarrow x^n = y^n)$

  • $\forall x^n \forall y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow }_{m+1} y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow }_{m} x^n) \leftrightarrow y^{n+1}(x^n))$

  • $\forall x^{m}\forall y^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow }_{m+1}y^{n+1}(x^{m}) \rightarrow \exists z^n\ x^{m} = \mathord {\uparrow }_{m}z^n)$

  • $\forall x^n\forall y^0 \lnot \mathord {\uparrow }_{n+1} y^0(x^n)$ .

To prove that ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ and ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ are definitionally equivalent (Theorem 23), we first define an interpretation, I, from ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ to ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ . This preserves the interpretation of all logical symbols, including $=$ ; its only non-trivial action is as follows:Footnote 75

$$ \begin{align*} [y^n(x^m)]^I &:= y^n(\mathord{\uparrow}_{n-1} x^m). \end{align*} $$

Observe that if $n = m + 1$ , then $[y^n(x^m)]^I$ is just $y^n(x^m)$ . Here is a very simple fact about the relationship between $\mathord {\uparrow }$ and the interpretations of $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ and $\mathrel {\equiv }$ , which holds just by unpacking some definitions (the proof is left to the reader):

Lemma 17. Where $i = \max (m, n)$ , ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ proves:

  1. (1) $[x^m \mathrel {\equiv } y^n]^I \leftrightarrow \mathord {\uparrow }_{i} x^m = \mathord {\uparrow }_{i}y^n$

  2. (2) $[x^m \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^n]^I \leftrightarrow \mathord {\uparrow }_{i+1}y^n(\mathord {\uparrow }_{i}x^m)$

We now have one substantial result:

Lemma 18. The I-interpretations of ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{n}_{m}}$ and ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{n}_{m}}$ are admissible in ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$

Proof. We start with ${\forall {\textrm {E}}^{n}_{m}}$ . Suppose that both $\phi (x^n)$ and $\phi (a^m)$ are well-formed in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ . Working in ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ , suppose $\forall x^n\phi ^I(x^n)$ . If $m = n$ , then $\phi ^I(a^m)$ follows by ordinary $\forall $ E in ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ . So consider the case when $m < n$ . The variable $x^n$ cannot occur in any identity-claim, e.g. $x^n = c^n$ , since $a^m = c^n$ is ill-formed in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ ; so $\phi $ must have this kind of shape (illustratively):

$$ \begin{align*}\psi(x^n(v^i), \ldots, y^{k}(x^n), \ldots)\end{align*} $$

with $i < m < n < k$ ; note that $i < m$ , since $\phi (a^m)$ is well-formed in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ . Now $\phi ^I$ is:

$$ \begin{align*}\psi(x^n(\mathord{\uparrow}_{n-1}v^{i}), \ldots, y^k(\mathord{\uparrow}_{k-1}x^n), \ldots).\end{align*} $$

Using ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}'$ s rule $\forall \textrm {E}^n$ , we can infer $\phi ^I(\mathord {\uparrow }_{n} a^m)$ , i.e.:

$$ \begin{align*}\psi(\mathord{\uparrow}_{n} a^m(\mathord{\uparrow}_{n-1}v^{i}), \ldots, y^k(\mathord{\uparrow}_{k-1}\mathord{\uparrow}_{n} a^m), \ldots).\end{align*} $$

Simplifying, and using generalized Up-Possess, we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*}\psi(a^m(\mathord{\uparrow}_{m-1}v^{i}), \ldots, y^k(\mathord{\uparrow}_{k-1} a^m), \ldots),\end{align*} $$

which is precisely $\phi ^I(a^m)$ , as required.

The admissibility of ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{n}_{m}}$ under interpretation follows straightforwardly. Given $\phi ^I(b^n)$ , with $b^n$ suitably arbitrary: infer $\forall x^n\phi ^I(x^n)$ using ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ ’s rule $\forall \textrm {I}^n$ ; with $a^m$ suitably arbitrary, infer $\phi ^I(a^m)$ using ${\forall {\textrm {I}}^{n}_{m}}$ under interpretation; finally, infer $\forall x^m\phi ^I(x^m)$ using ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ ’s rule $\forall \textrm {I}^m$ .□

It is now easy to prove that I is an interpretation:

Lemma 19. $I : {\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }} \longrightarrow {{\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}}$ is an interpretation.

Proof. We simply check all inference rules and axioms. Lemma 18 deals with the quantifier-rules, and no Limit-rules apply since we are considering ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ .

${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ -Comprehension. If $\phi (x^n)$ is an ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ -formula, then $\phi ^I(x^n)$ is an ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ -formula; now use ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ -Comprehension.

Type-Founded. Suppose $[a^m \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^{n+1}]^I$ i.e. $\mathord {\uparrow }_{i+1}b^{n+1}(\mathord {\uparrow }_{i}a^m)$ with $i = \max (m, n+1)$ by Lemma 17.2. By generalized Up-Founded, there is $z^{n}$ such that $\mathord {\uparrow }_{i}a^m = \mathord {\uparrow }_{i} z^n$ , i.e., $[a^m \mathrel {\equiv } z^n]^I$ by Lemma 17.1.

Type-Base. By generalized Up-Base, $\lnot \mathord {\uparrow }_{n+1} y^0(x^n)$ ; so by Lemma 17.2.□

We now switch to working in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ . It will help if we allow ourselves the use of a definite description operator, , within ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ . (This is harmless since, by standard Russellian techniques, this can always be eliminated from any formula.)Footnote 76 Now, by Type-Raising in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ , for any type n and each $x^n$ there is a unique $x^{n+1}$ such that $x^n \mathrel {\equiv } x^{n+1}$ ; we will denote this in ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ using $\mathord {\Uparrow } x^n$ , i.e., . As before, we write ${\mathord {\Uparrow }_{n}} a^m$ for the result of applying $n-m$ instances of $\mathord {\Uparrow }$ to $a^m$ , yielding a type n entity. We now define an interpretation, J, from ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ to ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ , with these actions:Footnote 77

$$ \begin{align*} [y^{n+1}(x^n)]^J &:= y^{n+1}(x^n)\\ [\mathord{\uparrow} x^n]^J &:= \mathord{\Uparrow} x^n. \end{align*} $$

Lemma 20. $J : {{\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}} \longrightarrow {\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ is an interpretation.

Proof. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ -Comprehension immediately licenses ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ -Comprehension. For Up-Inject, suppose $\mathord {\Uparrow } x^n = \mathord {\Uparrow } y^n$ , i.e., ; so $x^n \mathrel {\equiv } y^n$ by Lemma 2, and hence $x^n = y^n$ . Similarly, Up-Possess holds by Lemma 2. And Up-Founded and Up-Base hold via Type-Founded and Type-Base.□

It only remains to show that I and J together yield a definitional equivalence.

Lemma 21. ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ proves this scheme: $[[y^n(x^m)]^I]^J \leftrightarrow y^n(x^m)$ .

Proof. Note that $[[y^n(x^m)]^I]^J\, \textrm {iff}\ [y^n(\mathord {\uparrow }_{n-1}x^m)]^J\, \textrm {iff}\ y^n({\mathord {\Uparrow }_{n-1}} x^m)\ \textrm {iff}\ y^n(x^m)$ , using Lemma 2 for the final biconditional.□

Lemma 22. ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ proves these schemes: $[[y^{n+1}(x^n)]^J]^I \leftrightarrow y^{n+1}(x^n)$ and $[[\mathord {\uparrow } x^n]^J]^I = \mathord {\uparrow } x^n$ .

Proof. The first scheme is trivial. For the second:

Assembling Lemmas 1922, we obtain:

Theorem 23. ${\textrm {STT}_{\uparrow }}$ and ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ are definitionally equivalent

D Definitional equivalence for ${\textrm {FJT}}$

In Section 7, we stated that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is definitionally equivalent to ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ . In this appendix, we define ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ and prove the equivalence.

The guiding idea is to simulate ${\textrm {FJT}}$ by using a version of ${\textrm {STT}}$ with this sort of behaviour: for all types $1 < m < n$ , each type n entity $a^n$ projects downwards to some type m entity $\mathord {\downarrow _m}a^n$ ; we can then simulate an application $a^n(x^{m-1})$ by instead considering $\mathord {\downarrow _m}a^n(x^{m-1})$ . However, there is a small snag: we are treating $\mathord {\downarrow _m}$ as functional; but, if we assume no version of extensionality, then we will have no way to decide whether $a^2$ should project downwards to $b^1$ or $c^1$ , if $b^1$ and $c^1$ are coextensional. The snag can be avoided by using a relational (rather than function) version of downward-projection. What follows spells this out rigorously.

We define ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ by augmenting ${\textrm {STT}}$ as follows. For each $n> 0$ , we have a relational constant, $\triangleright $ , expressing the downward-projecting relation from a type $n\mathord {+}1$ entity to a type n entity. So we write e.g. $e^4 \triangleright d^3$ or $b^1 \triangleright a^0$ ;Footnote 78 when convenient, we may write $d^3 \triangleleft e^4$ or $a^0 \triangleleft b^1$ instead. We introduce some useful abbreviations:

$$ \begin{align*} a^n \approx b^n & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} \forall x^{n-1}(a^n(x^{n-1}) \leftrightarrow b^n(x^{n-1})), \textrm{when}\ n>0\\ a^n \mathrel{\blacktriangledown} b^n & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} \forall x^{n-1}(a^n \triangleright x^{n-1} \leftrightarrow b^n \triangleright x^{n-1}), \textrm{when}\ n >1\\ a^1 \mathrel{\blacktriangledown} b^1 & \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} a^1 = a^1. \end{align*} $$

So $a^n \approx b^n$ tells us that $a^n$ and $b^n$ are coextensive, and $a^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } b^n$ tells us that $a^n$ and $b^n$ project downwards to exactly the same entities. The special stipulation for $a^1 \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } b^1$ is needed as ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ has no relational constant $\triangleright $ expressing a relation from a type $1$ entity to a type $0$ entity, and so will hold vacuously. We concatenate chains of conjunctions; so we may write e.g., $a^2 \triangleleft d^3 \triangleright b^2 \approx c^2$ in place of $(d^3 \triangleright a^2 \land d^3 \triangleright b^2 \land b^2 \approx c^2)$ . ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ retains the ${\textrm {STT}}$ -Comprehension scheme for type $1$ entities, i.e., $\exists z^1 \forall x^0(z^1(x^0) \leftrightarrow \phi (x^0))$ ; but for each $n> 1$ , it has an augmented scheme:Footnote 79

  • ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ -Comprehension. $\forall y^n (\exists z^{n+1} \triangleright y^n) \forall x^n(z^{n+1}(x^n)\leftrightarrow \phi (x^n))$ , for any formula $\phi (x^n)$ not containing $z^{n+1}$ .

For each $n> 0$ , ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ also has these axioms:

  • Down $_\exists $ . $\forall z^{n+1}\exists x^n\phantom {)}z^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$

  • Down $_{{Sim}}$ . $\forall z^{n+1}\forall x^{n}\forall y^n(x^n \triangleleft z^{n+1} \triangleright y^n \rightarrow x^n \approx y^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } x^{n})$

  • Down $_{{Max}}$ . $\forall z^{n+1}\forall x^{n}\forall y^{n}(z^{n+1} \triangleright x^n \approx y^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } x^{n} \rightarrow z^{n+1} \triangleright y^{n})$

So Down $_\exists $ says that all entities of types $\geq 2$ project downwards; Down $_{\textrm {Sim}}$ says that if $z^{n+1}$ projects to two entities $x^n$ and $y^n$ , then $x^n$ and $y^n$ apply and project to exactly the same entities; and Down $_{\textrm {Max}}$ says that if $z^{n+1}$ projects to some entity $x^n$ , then $z^{n+1}$ also projects to any $y^n$ which applies and projects to exactly the same entities as $x^n$ . These axioms ensure that $\triangleright $ -chains are always equivalent, in a strong sense which is brought out by these next two lemmas:

Lemma 24. ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ proves this scheme (with $n> 0$ ). If $a^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$ and $b^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$ for some $x^n$ , then $a^{n+1} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } b^{n+1}$ .

Proof. Suppose $a^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$ and $b^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$ . If $a^{n+1} \triangleright y^n$ , then $x^n \approx y^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } x^n$ by Down $_{\textrm {Sim}}$ , so $b^{n+1} \triangleright y^n$ by Down $_{\textrm {Max}}$ ; similarly if $b^{n+1} \triangleright y^n$ then $a^{n+1} \triangleright y^n$ .□

Lemma 25. ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ proves this scheme (with $n> 0$ ). Given any $\triangleright $ -chains:

$$ \begin{align*} a^{n+1} \triangleright {}&a^{n} \triangleright a^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright a^{1}\\ &b^{n} \triangleright b^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright b^{1}. \end{align*} $$

  1. (1) If $a^{n+1} \triangleright b^{n}$ , then $\bigwedge _{1 \leq i \leq n} a^{i} \approx b^{i} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } a^{i}$ .

  2. (2) If there is m such that $1 \leq m \leq n$ and $b^m \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } a^m$ and $\bigwedge _{m \leq i \leq n} a^{i} \approx b^{i}$ , then $\bigwedge _{m \leq i \leq n} b^{i} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } a^{i}$ and $a^{n+1} \triangleright b^{n}$ .

Proof. (1) From Down $_{\textrm {Sim}}$ , by induction.

(2) By assumption, $a^{m+1} \triangleright a^m \approx b^m \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } a^m$ , so $a^{m+1} \triangleright b^m$ by Down $_{\textrm {Max}}$ ; so $b^{m+1} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } a^{m+1}$ by Lemma 24. This establishes a base case; the rest follows by induction. Now $a^{n+1} \triangleright b^{n}$ by Down $_{\textrm {Max}}$ .□

We will use these results to prove that ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ are definitionally equivalent (Theorem 31). We first define an interpretation, I, to take us from ${\textrm {FJT}}$ to ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ :Footnote 80

$$ \begin{align*} [y^n(x^m)]^I &:= \forall y^{n-1}\forall y^{n-2}\cdots \forall y^{m+1}(y^n \triangleright y^{n-1} \triangleright y^{n-2} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright y^{m+1} \rightarrow y^{m+1}(x^m)). \end{align*} $$

Note that if $m + 1 = n$ , then $[y^n(x^m)]^I$ is just $y^n(x^m)$ .

Lemma 26. $I : {{\textrm {FJT}}} \longrightarrow {{\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}}$ is an interpretation

Proof. For all $0 \leq i < n$ , let $\phi _i$ be ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -formulas not containing $z^n$ or $z^j$ or $y^j$ for any $0 \leq j < n$ . (No generality is lost here, as we can relabel variables as necessary.) By multiple successive applications of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ -Comprehension, there are $z^1 \triangleleft z^2 \triangleleft \cdots \triangleleft z^n$ such that $\forall x^i(z^{i+1}(x^i) \leftrightarrow \phi _i^I(x^i))$ , for each $0 \leq i < n$ . By Lemma 25.1, for each $0 \leq i < n$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x^i(\forall y^{n-1}\cdots \forall y^{i+1}(z^{n} \triangleright y^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright y^{i+1} \rightarrow y^{i+1}(x^i)) &\leftrightarrow \phi_i^I(x^i))\\ \textrm{i.e.,}\ \forall x^i([z^{n}(x^i)]^I &\leftrightarrow \phi_i^I(x^i)). \end{align*} $$

Conjoining these biconditionals and applying $\exists $ I, we obtain $[\exists z^{n}\bigwedge _{i < n}\forall x^i(z^n(x^i) \leftrightarrow \phi _i(x^i))]^I$ , i.e., an arbitrary instance of $[{\textrm {FJT}}\text{-}\textrm {Comprehension}]^I$ .□

We now switch to working in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ . We introduce another abbreviation, for a bounded version of coextensiveness, whenever $k \leq \min (m,n)$ :

$$ \begin{align*} a^m \approxeq_{k} b^n \mathrel{\textrm{iff}_{\textrm{df}}} \bigwedge_{i < k} \forall x^i(a^m(x^i) \leftrightarrow b^n(x^i)). \end{align*} $$

Note the bound is $i < k$ . We now define an interpretation, J, from ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ to ${\textrm {FJT}}$ :Footnote 81

$$ \begin{align*} [y^{n+1}(x^n)]^J &:= y^{n+1}(x^n)\\ [y^{n+1} \triangleright x^n]^J &:= y^{n+1} \approxeq_{n} x^{n}. \end{align*} $$

Lemma 27. ${\textrm {FJT}}$ proves the following schemes, where well-formed:

  1. (1) If $a^{m} \approxeq _{k} c^l$ and $b^{n} \approxeq _{k} c^l$ , then $a^m \approxeq _{k} b^n$ .

  2. (2) $a^m \approxeq _{k} b^n$ iff $\forall x^k(a^{m} \approxeq _{k} x^k \leftrightarrow b^{n} \approxeq _{k} x^k)$ .

  3. (3) $a^n \approxeq _{n-1} b^n$ iff $[a^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } b^n]^J$ , noting here that we must have $n> 1$ .

Proof. (1) Trivial.

(2) Left-to-right. Suppose $a^{m} \approxeq _{k} b^{n}$ ; if $a^{m} \approxeq _{k} c^k$ , then $b^{n} \approxeq _{k} c^k$ by (1), and conversely. Right-to-left. Suppose $\forall x^k(a^{m} \approxeq _{k} x^k \leftrightarrow b^{n} \approxeq _{k} v^k)$ ; by ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension, there is some $c^k \approxeq _{k} a^{m}$ ; so $b^{n} \approxeq _{k} c^k$ , and now $a^{n} \approxeq _{k} b^{n}$ by (1).

(3) Using (2), since $[a^{n} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } b^{n}]^J$ is $\forall x^{n-1}(a^{n} \approxeq _{n-1} x^{n-1} \leftrightarrow b^{n} \approxeq _{n} x^{n-1})$ .□

Lemma 28. $J : {{\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}} \longrightarrow {{\textrm {FJT}}}$ is an interpretation.

Proof. For Down $_\exists $ . Fix $z^{n+1}$ ; by ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension there is some $x^n \approxeq _{n} z^{n+1}$ , i.e., $[z^{n+1} \triangleright x^{n}]^J$ .

For Down $_{{Sim}}$ . Suppose $[x^n \triangleleft z^{n+1} \triangleright y^n]^J$ , i.e., $x^n \approxeq _{n} z^{n+1} \approxeq _{n} x^n$ ; so $x^n \approxeq _{n} y^n$ by Lemma 27.1. In particular, $x^n \approx y^n$ , so $[x^n \approx y^n]^J$ . Moreover, if $n> 1$ then $x^n \approxeq _{n-1} y^n$ , so that $[x^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } y^n]^J$ by Lemma 27.3; if $n = 1$ then $[x^n \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } y^n]^J$ vacuously.

For Down $_{{Max}}$ . Suppose $[z^{n+1} \triangleright x^{n} \approx y^{n} \mathrel {\blacktriangledown } x^n]^J$ , i.e., $z^{n+1} \approxeq _{n} x^n \approx y^{n} \approxeq _{n-1} x^{n}$ , using Lemma 27.3. So $y^{n} \approxeq _{n} x^{n}$ , and hence $z^{n+1} \approxeq _{n} y^{n}$ by Lemma 27.1, i.e., $[z^{n+1} \triangleright y^{n}]^J$ .

For ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ -Comprehension. Let $\phi $ be any ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ -formula not containing $z^{n+1}$ (but which may contain $y^n$ ). Fix $y^n$ ; by ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension, there is $z^{n+1}$ such that:

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x^n(z^{n+1}(x^n) \leftrightarrow \phi^J(x^n)) &\land \bigwedge_{i < n}\forall x^i(z^{n+1}(x^i) \leftrightarrow y^n(v^i))\\ \textrm{i.e.,}\ \forall x^n(z^{n+1}(x^n) \leftrightarrow \phi^J(x^n)) &\land z^{n+1} \approxeq_{n} y^n\\ \textrm{i.e.,}\ [\forall x^n(z^{n+1}(x^n) \leftrightarrow \phi(x^n))^J &\land z^{n+1} \triangleright y^n]^J \end{align*} $$

So we have arbitrary instances of $[{{\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}}\textrm {-Comprehension}]^J$ .□

It only remains to show that I and J characterise a definitional equivalence.

Lemma 29. ${\textrm {FJT}}$ proves this scheme: $[[y^n(x^m)]^I]^J \leftrightarrow y^n(x^m)$ .

Proof. Note that the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $[[y^n(x^m)]^I]^J$

  2. (2) $[\forall y^{n-1}\cdots \forall y^{m+1}(y^n \triangleright y^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright y^{m+1} \rightarrow y^{m+1}(x^m))]^J$

  3. (3) $\forall y^{n-1}\cdots \forall y^{m+1}(y^n \approxeq _{n-1} y^{n-1} \approxeq _{n-2} \cdots \approxeq _{m+1} y^{m+1} \rightarrow y^{m+1}(x^m))$

  4. (4) $y^n(x^m)$

The last equivalence uses Lemma 27.1, and repeated instances of ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension to provide a chain $y^n \approxeq _{n-1} a^{n-1} \approxeq _{n-2} \cdots \approxeq _{m+1} a^{m+1}$ .□

Lemma 30. ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ proves these schemes: $[[y^{n+1}(x^n)]^J]^I \leftrightarrow y^{n+1}(x^n)$ and $[[y^{n+1} \triangleright x^n]^J]^I \leftrightarrow y^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$ .

Proof. The first scheme is trivial. For the second, note that the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $[[y^{n+1} \triangleright x^n]^J]^I$

  2. (2) $[\bigwedge _{i < n}\forall v^i(y^{n+1}(v^i) \leftrightarrow x^n(v^i))]^I$

  3. (3) $\bigwedge _{i < n}\forall v^i(\forall y^n \forall y^{n-1}\cdots \forall y^{i+1}(y^{n+1} \triangleright y^{n} \triangleright y^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright y^{i+1} \rightarrow y^{i+1}(v^i)) \leftrightarrow {}$ $\forall x^{n-1} \cdots \forall x^{i+1}(x^n \triangleright x^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright x^{i+1} \rightarrow x^{i+1}(v^i)))$

  4. (4) $y^{n+1} \triangleright x^n$

For the last equivalence, first note that repeated use of Down $_\exists $ gives us chains:

$$ \begin{align*} y^{n+1} \triangleright{} &a^n \triangleright a^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright a^{1}\\[-4pt] &x^{n} \triangleright b^{n-1} \triangleright \cdots \triangleright b^{1} \end{align*} $$

Using Lemma 25.1 twice, (3) is equivalent to:

  • ( $3^{\prime }$ ) $a^n \approx x^n \land a^{n-1} \approx b^{n-1} \land \cdots \land a^1 \approx b^1$

Now Lemma 25.1 yields (4) $\Rightarrow $ (3 $'$ ), and Lemma 25.2 gives (3 $'$ ) $\Rightarrow $ (4).□

Assembling Lemmas 2630, we obtain:

Theorem 31. ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ are definitionally equivalent

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Neil Barton, Salvatore Florio, Peter Fritz, Luca Incurvati, Stephan Krämer, Øystein Linnebo, Nicholas Jones, Agustín Rayo, Thomas Schindler, Lukas Skiba, and an anonymous referee for Review of Symbolic Logic.

Footnotes

1 Cf. Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 294, Reference Linnebo and Rayo24, pp. 178–179] on ‘definite’ collections of languages and alternative ‘labels’. For readability, we use standard ordinal notation in this paper, but this is easily eliminable; e.g., ‘ $\alpha +1$ ’ can be parsed as ‘the next index after $\alpha $ ’, and ‘ $\omega $ ’ as ‘the first limit index’.

2 These are the obvious natural-deduction versions of Degen and Johannsen’s [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, p. 149] sequent-calculus rules. Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 288] are not specific on the rules they adopt, but [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, 282n20] appeal to a result from Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, p. 150] which uses these rules.

3 Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, p. 149] and Linnebo and Rayo Reference Linnebo and Rayo[23] offer a variant formulation, using $\lambda $ -abstraction.

4 Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, 153] and Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 288].

5 Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, p. 149] draw no distinction between $=$ and $\mathrel {\equiv }$ .

6 For a proof, see Lemma 2 of Appendix A.

7 Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 288] take Type-Raising as an axiom scheme; we prove it in Lemma 1 of Appendix A.

8 Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, p. 151] and Linnebo and Rayo Reference Linnebo and Rayo[23]. Notation: $(\exists x^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta )\phi $ abbreviates $\exists x^\gamma (x^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta \land \phi )$ ; similarly, $(\forall x^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta )\phi $ abbreviates $\forall x^\gamma (x^\gamma \mathrel {\equiv } b^\beta \rightarrow \phi )$ ; and similarly for other two-place infix predicates.

9 In Appendix A, we prove that Type-Founded and Type-Base are independent from the axioms given so far. Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 289] provide a version of Type-Base, but no version of Type-Founded (though they clearly want some such principle; see [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 283n.22]). Degen and Johannsen Reference Degen and Johannsen[7] tackle this slightly differently; see the start of Appendix B. With these principles, we can establish that: if $\alpha < \beta $ then $a^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\beta $ iff $b^\beta (a^\alpha )$ ; if $\alpha \geq \beta $ and $\alpha $ is minimal for $a^\alpha $ and $\beta $ is minimal for $b^\beta $ , then . (Here, we say that $\gamma $ is minimal for $c^\gamma $ iff $\forall x^\delta \ c^\gamma \mathrel {\not \equiv } x^\delta $ for all $\delta < \gamma $ .)

10 This extends Degen and Johannsen’s [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, sec. 4.1] results concerning ${\textrm {Z}}$ . Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23 cover only ${\textrm {Z}}$ without Foundation. The bound $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ is needed as $a^\kappa \mathrel {\varepsilon } b^\kappa $ abbreviates $\exists x^{\kappa +1}(\forall z^{\kappa +2}(z^{\kappa +2}(x^{\kappa +1})\leftrightarrow z^{\kappa +2}(b^{\kappa })) \land x^{\kappa +1}(a^\kappa ))$ .

11 Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 284, 289] mention differences (1) and (2) themselves, but they do not mention (3).

12 Indeed, it is definable within ${\textrm {LT}}$ ; see Appendix B.

13 Assuming $\kappa> \omega $ and $\kappa + 2 < \tau $ . Sketch. Using the Sets-from-Types Theorem, use ${\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }_{\textrm {p}}}$ to develop ${\textrm {Zr}^{(\omega +\omega )}}$ . In ${\textrm {Zr}^{(\omega +\omega )}}$ , define $\mathbb {N}$ as the set of finite von Neumann ordinals, and define $+$ and $\times $ as usual. Suppose we can show $\phi (n)$ for each n; then since the type of each n is n, for each $n < \omega $ we can show $\forall x^n(x^n \mathrel {\varepsilon } \mathbb {N} \rightarrow \phi (x^n))$ ; now use Limit $^\omega $ .

14 See footnote 10.

15 Illustration. Let $\textrm {Con}_{{{\textrm {Zr}}}}$ be a suitable consistency sentence for ${\textrm {Zr}}$ . This is independent from ${\textrm {Zr}}$ , by the second incompleteness theorem; but $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ proves $\textrm {Con}_{{{\textrm {Zr}}}}^{(\kappa )}$ , since it is arithmetically complete. The same example shows that ${\textrm {Zr}}$ does not interpret $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ .

16 Pace Degen and Johannsen’s Reference Degen and Johannsen[7] sentiment that ${\textrm {CTT}_{\textrm {p}}}$ might serve ‘as a foundation for set theory’. Note that differences (1)–(2) also underpin the philosophical discussion of Section 3.

17 Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, pp. 45–46].

18 Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, pp. 46–47]; for discussion, see Feferman [Reference Feferman and Feferman9, p. 37] and Tait [Reference Tait39, p. 88].

19 Tait [Reference Tait39, p. 92] emphasises this point, and Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 289 n.28] concede it.

20 Can we consider (or might Gödel have considered) the move from ${\textrm {STT}}$ to ${\textrm {Zr}}$ as involving two steps: first, Linnebo and Rayo’s step from ${\textrm {STT}}$ to some ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ and $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ ; second the addition of an untyped variable to $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ , yielding ${\textrm {Zr}}$ ? (Thanks to an anonymous referee for posing this question.) This may be a useful heuristic, but it is slightly technically infelicituous, since the result of adding an untyped variable to $\textrm {Zr}^{(\kappa )}$ will be arithmetically complete (cf. footnote 29).

21 Cf. Scott [Reference Scott and Jech36, p. 208]: ‘the best way to regard Zermelo’s theory is as a simplification and extension of Russell’s [ ${\textrm {STT}}$ ]…. The simplification was to make the types cumulative.’ Note that we are talking about ${\textrm {ZFU}}$ rather than ZrU. This is inevitable, since ZrU was not formulated until long after Gödel’s lecture. However, Gödel supplied an additional argument in favour of Replacement; see footnote 24.

22 Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 270] claim that this is how the higher-types are widely regarded by philosophers. For the record, we think that anyone who uses type theory (cumulative or non-cumulative) should reject the idea that there is a useful ontology/ideology dichotomy to be drawn along this faultline. When Quine Reference Quine[31] drew his distinction between ontology and ideology, he drew it for first-order logic. In that setting, the distinction is clear enough: we are ontologically committed to the things we quantify over; ideological commitments are expressed by symbols in positions that cannot be quantified into. But in a type-theoretic setting, we can quantify into predicate-position. So distinctions of logical order no longer align with the quantifiable/unquantifiable distinction. See also Trueman [Reference Trueman40, chap. 7] and Williamson [Reference Williamson44, pp. 260–261].

23 Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo24, p. 179] suggest something a little similar, though in terms of the plurally-interpreted hierarchy (see Section 4.3) and in response to a slightly different concern.

24 Gödel [Reference Gödel and Feferman18, p. 47] suggests something similar: given ‘the system $S_\alpha $ you can… take an ordinal $\beta $ greater than $\alpha $ which can be defined in terms of the system $S_\alpha $ , and by means of it state the axioms for the system $\beta $ including all types less than $\beta $ , and so on.’ However, Gödel is not trying to defend anything like the argument of Section 3.2. As such—and unlike in the context of ideological-bootstrapping—Gödel need not confine himself to finite sequences of theories. For discussion of Gödel, see Feferman [Reference Feferman8, pp. 37–38 fn. f], Incurvati [Reference Incurvati19, pp. 90–93]. Koellner [Reference Koellner20, pp. 21–24], and Tait [Reference Tait39, pp. 89–93].

25 Note that A is not a von Neumann ordinal, i.e., A is not well-ordered by $\in $ . Still, the existence of some such A and $<$ follows (without Choice) from Hartog’s Lemma; see Incurvati [Reference Incurvati19, p. 92] and Potter [Reference Potter29, p. 185].

26 Formally, $\kappa $ is a hereditary-point iff $\kappa $ is an infinite cardinal and any of these equivalent conditions hold (we leave the reader to prove the equivalences): (1) $(\forall x \in V_\kappa )|x| < \kappa $ ; (2) $H_\kappa = V_\kappa $ , where $H_\kappa = \{x : |{\textrm {trcl}}(x)| < \kappa \}$ ; (3) either $\kappa = \omega $ or $\kappa $ is a $\beth $ -fixed point, i.e., $\beth _\kappa = \kappa $ ; (4) $|V_\kappa | = \kappa $ . Characterisation (1) formalizes the definition in the text and (2) gives the idea its name.

27 Boolos [Reference Boolos3, p. 258] had qualms about the existence of the first $\aleph $ -fixed point; calling it $\kappa $ , he wrote that $\kappa $ is ‘so big… that it calls into question the truth of any theory, one of whose assertions is the claim that there are at least $\kappa $ objects’. The first hereditary-point after $\omega $ is at least as large as Boolos’s $\kappa $ ; it is a $\beth $ -fixed point, as in (3) of footnote 26, and hence an $\aleph $ -fixed point.

28 We do not need all of ${\textrm {Zr}}$ ; we can make do with the subtheory ${\textrm {LT}}$ . For details, see Appendix B and Button [Reference Button5].

29 Pedantic Objection. Perhaps ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ ’s externally supplied types are not wholly superfluous, since they allow us to formulate the intrinsically infinitary Limit-rules which gives ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ a kind of strength which a recursive theory like ${\textrm {Zr}}$ cannot simulate (see (3) from Section 2.2). Pedantic Reply. Those who want to lean on ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ ’s infinitary features can incorporate them within a ${\textrm {Zr}}$ -like setting. We will illustrate how using ${\textrm {Zr}}$ itself. For each index $\alpha < \tau $ , introduce a new constant, $c_\alpha $ ; add to ${\textrm {Zr}}$ each sentence ‘ $c_\alpha $ is a von Neumann ordinal’; add the sentence ‘ $c_\alpha \in c_\beta $ ’ iff $\alpha < \beta $ ; for each limit $\lambda < \tau $ , add the infinitary rule: from $\phi (c_\alpha )$ for all $\alpha < \lambda $ , infer $(\forall x \in c_\lambda )\phi (x)$ .

30 Rayo Reference Rayo, Rayo and Uzquiano[33] develops this plural interpretation.

31 Our word ‘plural $^*$ ’ is a ‘pseudo-singular device’, in the sense of Oliver and Smiley [Reference Oliver and Smiley28, chap. 15]; in natural language, it infelicitously behaves like a singular term. Florio and Linnebo [Reference Florio and Linnebo11, sec. 11.8] use ‘higher plurality’ here.

32 The inclusion is vertical in the sense of Oliver and Smiley [Reference Oliver and Smiley28, chap. 15]. Vertical inclusion only ever holds between plurals $^*$ of different levels, and is analogous to set-membership. Vertical inclusion is to be contrasted with horizontal inclusion, which is analogous to subsethood: b horizontally includes a iff b vertically includes everything that a vertically includes.

33 We are speaking as if variables refer. This is one way to gloss a Tarskian referentialist approach to semantics: the value of a variable (on a Tarskian valuation) can be thought of as the variable’s referent (on the valuation). In certain contexts, describing variables as referring is misleading (see Button and Walsh [Reference Button and Walsh6, chap. 1]), but we do not think it will do any harm here. If we wanted, we could say that a semantics is referentialist iff it treats every type of constant as a referring term, and then use a Robinsonian or hybrid approach to handle variables (again, see Button and Walsh [Reference Button and Walsh6, chap. 1]).

34 See Boolos [Reference Boolos3, Prior [Reference Quine31, chap. 3], Rayo and Yablo [Reference Rayo and Yablo34], Trueman [Reference Trueman40], Williamson [Reference Williamson43, pp. 458–460, Reference Williamson44, chap. 5], and Wright [Reference Wright46].

35 This point is emphasised throughout Florio and Jones Reference Florio and Jones[10].

36 We have taken the label ‘conceptual semantics’ from Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 272], who use ‘concept’ instead of ‘property’. Of course, Linnebo and Rayo are following Frege here. However, this use of ‘concept’ is potentially misleading; we prefer ‘property’, which avoids any psychological overtones.

37 This was arguably the standard way of thinking about predication before Frege introduced his alternative (see below), and plenty of philosophers after Frege have advocated versions of it too: see Bealer [Reference Bealer1, chap. 4], Gaskin [Reference Gaskin16, Reference Gaskin17], Strawson [Reference Strawson37, Reference Strawson38], and Wiggins [Reference Wiggins42].

38 For discussion of the very different sense in which predicates could be said to refer, see Trueman [Reference Trueman40, chaps. 4–6].

39 This account of predication is what we take to be suggested by Frege’s (e.g., [Reference Frege and Beaney13, Reference Frege and Beaney14, Reference Frege15, sec. 31]) discussions of predication; however, we do not want to commit to any exegetical claims here. It is worth noting that the gap between our Fregeans and the referentialists about predication need not be as large as it initially appears. Even if referentialists think of words like ‘pontificates’ as referring terms, on a par with names like ‘Socrates’, concatenation behaves like a Fregean predicate: ‘ $\textsf {x}\textsf {y}$ ’ says of a pair of objects that the former instantiates the latter. This point is originally due to Frege [Reference Frege and Beaney14, pp. 192–193], and is further developed by Trueman [Reference Trueman40, secs. 3.4 and 8.4].

40 Whitehead and Russell [Reference Whitehead and Russell41, Introduction, chap. II, sec. 4] present a similar argument (in their distinctive terminology).

41 For an extended argument to that effect, see Trueman Reference Trueman[40].

42 We have considered two conceptual semantics: referentialist and Fregean. Wright Reference Wright, Hale and Wright[45], MacBride Reference MacBride[25], Liebesman Reference Liebesman[22], and Rieppel Reference Rieppel[35] offer a third approach, which attempts to provide a middle-way between referentialism and Fregeanism. They agree with referentialists that ‘x pontificates’ denotes Pontification, but they agree with Fregeans that ‘x pontificates’ says of objects that they teach. Given the latter point, they agree that first-level predicates play a different kind of semantic role from names; so they agree with Fregeans that ‘ $c^2(a^0)$ ’ is unintelligible. However, unlike Fregeans, they cannot embrace ${\textrm {STT}}$ : according to the middle-way, every type $1$ property is also a type $0$ object, but ${\textrm {STT}}$ -Comprehension straightforwardly entails that there are strictly more type $1$ properties than objects. Moreover, one of us, Trueman [Reference Trueman40, chaps. 4 and 8], has also argued at length that this middle-way is philosophically incoherent.

43 It can also contain type $\alpha \mathord {+}1$ constants, for any $\alpha < \beta $ .

44 This is very slightly different from what Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 300] actually say: they consider interpretations of constants (see footnote 43). The particular requirement on generalized semantic theories is an application of the principle that for each $\alpha $ , it is possible to quantify unrestrictedly over all entities of type $\alpha $ . (Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 274] only state this principle for type $0$ , but their argument requires that the principle apply to all types; Florio and Linnebo [Reference Florio and Linnebo11, sec. 11.5] explicitly commit themselves to the fully general principle.) We discuss the broader concept of absolute generality in Section 7.

45 Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 276]. Note that they also [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 294], [Reference Linnebo and Rayo24, p. 176] consider a second, slightly differently restricted principle: For any ‘definite totality’ of languages, there is a union language. For our purposes, there is no significant difference between these formulations. Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo24, 179–180] treat ‘definite totality’ as an unanalysed notion. However, the function of this notion is as follows: given any ‘definite totality’ of languages, we can comprehend a limit-index, $\lambda $ , which acts as an upper bound of the orders on the languages among that ‘definite totality’. (This notion of an ‘upper bound’ makes sense, since every $\textrm {CTT}$ -like language has well-ordered indices.) So, once we recall that we have only insisted that our type-indices be well-ordered, not that they be ordinals, the two principles come to the same thing.

46 Cf. Maddy [Reference Maddy26, p. 485, 492ff.] on the rules of thumb ‘one step back from disaster’ and ‘maximize’; and cf. Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 274, esp. fn. 8] on the rule of thumb: ‘Because we can.’

47 Throughout this section, we assume a conceptual semantics, and so speak of type $n> 0$ entities as properties. Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, pp. 45–47] offer ${\textrm {FJT}}$ as a theory of predication, and we also think that ${\textrm {STT}}$ is best understood as a theory of predication.

48 At least: Florio and Jones nowhere discuss infinitary conjunction, and only ever use natural numbers as type indices.

49 The surrogate for extensionality is the scheme, for all $n> 0$ : $\forall x^{n}\forall y^{n}(\bigwedge _{i < n}\forall z^i(x^{n}(z^i) \leftrightarrow y^{n}(z^i)) \rightarrow x^{n} = y^{n})$ ); the surrogate for purity is Type-Purity (see Appendix B.2). To see that the resulting theory is decidable, note two facts: (i) all its variables are explicitly typed and (ii) for each n, it proves that there are exactly $h(n)$ type n entities, where $h(0) = 1$ and $h(n+1) = 2^{h(0) + \cdots + h(n)}$ ; it follows that every quantifier provably has a fixed finite range.

50 Eagle-eyed readers will notice a slight difference between this and Section 5.4. When dealing with $\textrm {CTT}$ , we read $c^2(a^0)$ as $c^2(\mathord {\uparrow } a^0)$ , since $\textrm {CTT}$ licenses Type-Raising, which projects entities upwards through the levels of the type hierarchy. By contrast, ${\textrm {FJT}}$ contradicts Type-Raising; and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension effectively projects entities downwards.

51 Via $\exists z^1 \forall x^0(z^1(x^0)\leftrightarrow x^0=x^0)$ , which is an instance of ${\textrm {STT}}$ -Comprehension and $\textrm {CTT}$ - and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension.

52 We are not saying that there would have to be a more inclusive domain, only that it would have to make sense to say that there is. If $\phi $ make sense, then so must $\lnot \phi $ .

53 This explication has an obvious shortcoming: it employs unrestricted quantification itself, in talking about ‘absolutely any counterexamples’. However, this shortcoming is shared by every account of unrestricted quantification. Moreover, anyone who already understands unrestricted quantification should agree with Florio and Jones’ explication.

54 Via the ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension instance: $\exists z^2(\forall x^1(z^2(x^1) \leftrightarrow x^1=x^1)\land \forall x^0(z^2(x^0) \leftrightarrow x^0 = x^0))$ .

55 Formally: $\forall x^0(U^1(x^0)\rightarrow U^2(x^0))$ , but $\exists y^1(U^2(y^1)\land \forall x^0(U^1(x^0) \rightarrow x^0 \mathrel {\not \equiv } y^1))$ .

56 Krämer Reference Krämer[21] presents a very similar argument, but directed against $\textrm {CTT}$ rather than ${\textrm {FJT}}$ .

57 This is because we can ask whether $d^n$ is m-unrestricted for any $m> 0$ ; see (4) in Section 7.6.

58 Via the ${\textrm {FJT}}$ -Comprehension Instance: $\exists z^2(\forall x^0(z^2(x^0)\leftrightarrow x^0 = x^0) \land \forall x^1(z^2(x^1)\leftrightarrow x^1\neq x^1))$ .

59 This informal argument crucially assumes that ${\textrm {FJT}}$ is taken at face value. Take the idea that ‘ $y^2$ is true of everything in $d^1$ that it can meaningfully be applied to’ can be glossed in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ as $\forall x^0(d^1(x^0) \rightarrow y^2(x^0))$ . Under interpretation into ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ , this formula becomes $\forall x^0(d^1(x^0) \rightarrow \forall z^1(y^2 \triangleright z^1 \rightarrow z^1(x^0)))$ . This no longer says anything about whether $y^2$ itself is true of everything in $d^1$ .

60 Assuming that the type hierarchy does not have a terminal level.

61 When $\textrm {CTT}$ is taken at face value, and again assuming that the type hierarchy does not have a terminal level. In detail: first, we observe that if $d^{\beta +1}$ is unrestricted, then $\forall y^{\gamma +1}(\forall x^\alpha (d^{\beta +1}(x^{\alpha })\rightarrow y^{\gamma +1}(x^{\alpha }))\rightarrow \forall x^{\gamma }y^{\gamma +1}(x^{\gamma }))$ , for all $\alpha \leq \min (\beta , \gamma )$ . Via $\textrm {CTT}$ -Comprehension, we obtain an $H^{\beta +2}$ such that $\forall x^{\beta +1}(H^{\beta +2}(x^{\beta +1})\leftrightarrow \exists x^\beta \phantom {(}x^{\beta +1} \mathrel {\equiv } x^{\beta })$ . Then any $d^{\beta +1}$ is restricted, since $\forall x^\beta (d^{\beta +1}(x^\beta ) \rightarrow H^{\beta +2}(x^\beta ))$ but $\lnot \forall x^{\beta +1} H^{\beta +2}(x^{\beta +1})$ .

62 This explains why Florio and Jones abandoned Linnebo and Rayo’s $\textrm {CTT}$ , in favour of a theory which invalidates Type-Raising: in $\textrm {CTT}$ , every type of entity can be applied to every type of entity (using $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ if necessary), and so the range of significance of $a^1$ includes all entities of all types.

63 Florio and Jones [Reference Florio and Jones10, p. 56fn.15] have some doubts about whether $\mathrel {\equiv }$ expresses cross-type identity in ${\textrm {FJT}}$ . If these doubts are justified, then our formal definition of m-Russellian will have to be revised as follows:

  • ( $3_*$ ) $d^{n}$ is ${m}$ -Russellian $_* \mathrel {\textrm {iff}_{\textrm {df}}} \bigl (\bigwedge _{k<m}\forall y^kd^n(y^k)\bigr ) \land \bigl (\bigwedge _{m\leq k < n}\forall y^k\lnot d^n(y^k)\bigr )$ .

If $n < m$ , then ‘ $d^n$ is m-Russellian $_*$ ’ is ill-formed rather than false. Nevertheless, our key points about Russellianness still go through. First, Russellianness $_*$ is significantly relativized, since $H^2$ is $1$ -Russellian $_*$ but not $2$ -Russellian $_*$ , with $H^2$ as given at the end of Section 7.5. Second, (R=U) is false, since $U^2$ is $1$ -unrestricted but not $1$ -Russellian $_*$ , with $U^2$ as given in Section 7.5.

64 Throughout the appendices, we will assume that all type-indices are ordinals; nothing turns on this, but it makes the technicalities more familiar.

65 ${\textrm {Zr}}$ is equivalent to Potter’s Reference Potter[29] theory Z; this is strictly stronger than Zermelo’s ${\textrm {Z}}$ .

66 Notation: we let ‘ $x \subseteq c \in h$ ’ abbreviate ‘ $(x \subseteq c \land c \in h)$ ’; similarly for other infix predicates.

67 See Button [Reference Button5, sec. 3] for proofs.

68 Compare these with Degen and Johannsen [Reference Degen and Johannsen7, 149 Ext, 153 Nullity].

69 This addresses Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 289 n.28].

70 All the set-theoretic facts needed in this ensuing discussion of transitive models can be found in Button and Walsh [Reference Button and Walsh6, chap. 8]. Notation: We use calligraphic fonts for structures, and italics for their underlying domains; so A is the domain of $\mathcal {A}$ . The definition of a transitive model is given in the model theory; so we use ‘ $\in $ ’, here, in the model theory, and use ‘ $\in ^{\mathcal {A}}$ ’ for $\mathcal {A}$ ’s interpretation of $\in $ ’.

71 Whenever we speak of ordinals in this subsection, we mean von Neumann ordinals.

72 See Linnebo and Rayo [Reference Linnebo and Rayo23, p. 279n.13].

73 Recall from footnote 10 that $x^\alpha \mathrel {\varepsilon } y^\beta $ is a ${{\textrm {CTT}^{\tau }}}$ -formula iff $\max (\alpha , \beta ) + 2 < \tau $ .

74 As with the signs $=$ , $\mathrel {\equiv }$ or $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ , we are using the same symbol (in a typically ambiguous way) for each type level.

75 So: $[x^n = y^n]^I := x^n = y^n$ ; $[\phi \land \psi ]^I := (\phi ^I \land \psi ^I)$ ; $[\lnot \phi ]^I := \lnot \phi ^I$ ; and $[\forall x^n\phi ]^I := \forall x^n \phi ^I$ .

76 So we are relying on the fact that ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ augmented with this device is definitionally equivalent to ${\textrm {CTT}^{\omega }}$ . Clearly, it is. Still, for details of how to handle function symbols more austerely, see e.g., Button and Walsh [Reference Button and Walsh6, sec. 5.5, esp. fn.23].

77 And: $[x^n = y^n]^J := x^n = y^n$ ; $[\phi \land \psi ]^J := (\phi ^J \land \psi ^J)$ ; $[\lnot \phi ]^J := \lnot \phi ^J$ ; and $[\forall x^n\phi ]^J := \forall x^n \phi ^J$ .

78 As with the signs $=$ , $\mathrel {\equiv }$ or $\mathrel {\varepsilon }$ , we are using the same symbol (in a typically ambiguous way) for each type level.

79 It follows that some models of (plain vanilla) ${\textrm {STT}}$ cannot be turned into models of ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ just by assigning some meaning to ‘ $\triangleright $ ’. Example: it is consistent with ${\textrm {STT}}$ that there are exactly four type $2$ entities; whereas ${\textrm {STT}_{\triangleright }}$ (and ${\textrm {FJT}}$ ) prove that there are at least eight type $2$ entities.

80 We choose variables to avoid clashes; I’s other actions are trivial.

81 We choose variables to avoid clashes in $[y^{n+1} \triangleright x^{n}]^J$ ; J’s other actions are trivial.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Bealer, G. (1982). Quality and Concept. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M., editor (1997). The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1985). Nominalist platonism. The Philosophical Review, 94, 327–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, G. (2000). Must we believe in set theory? In Sher, G., and Tieszen, R., editors. Between Logic and Intuition: Essays in Honor of Charles Parsons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 257–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Button, T. (forthcoming). Level theory, part 1: Axiomatizing the bare idea of a cumulative hierarchy of sets. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.Google Scholar
Button, T., & Walsh, S. (2018). Philosophy and Model Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Degen, W., & Johannsen, J. (2000). Cumulative higher-order logic as a foundation for set theory. Mathematical Logic Quarterly, 46(2), 147170.3.0.CO;2-2>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S., editor (1995a). Kurt Gödel: Collected Works, Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S., editor (1995b). Note to Gödel (1933). In Feferman, S., editor. Kurt Gödel: Collected Works, Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Florio, S., & Jones, N. K. (2021). Unrestricted quantification and the structure of type theory. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 102, 4464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Florio, S., & Linnebo, Ø. (2021). The Many and the One: A Philosophical Study of Plural Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Florio, S., & Shapiro, S. (2014). Set theory, type theory, and absolute generality. Mind, 123(489), 157174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frege, G. (1891). Function and concept. In Beaney, M., editor (1997). The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 130148.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1892). On concept and object. In Beaney, M., editor (1997). The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 181193.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1893). Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Vol. I. Jena: Pohle.Google Scholar
Gaskin, R. (1995). Bradley’s regress, the copula and the unity of the proposition. The Philosophical Quarterly, 45, 161180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaskin, R. (2008). The Unity of the Proposition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gödel, K. (1933). The present situation in the foundations of mathematics. In Feferman, S., editor (1995a). Kurt Gödel: Collected Works, Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 4553.Google Scholar
Incurvati, L. (2020). Conceptions of Set and the Foundations of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koellner, Peter (2003). The Search for New Axioms. Ph.D. Thesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
Krämer, S. (2017). Everything, and then some. Mind, 126(502), 499528.Google Scholar
Liebesman, D. (2015). Predication as ascription. Mind, 124, 517569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linnebo, Ø., & Rayo, A. (2012). Hierarchies ontological and ideological. Mind, 121(482), 269308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linnebo, Ø., & Rayo, A. (2014). Reply to Florio and Shapiro. Mind, 123(489), 175181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (2011). Impure reference: A way around the concept horse paradox. Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 297312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maddy, P. (1988). Believing the axioms. I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 53(2), 481511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magidor, O. (2009). The last dogma of type confusions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 109, 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oliver, A., & Smiley, T. (2016). Plural Logic (second edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potter, M. (2004). Set Theory and its Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. (1971). Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. v. O. (1970). Philosophy of Logic. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Quine, W. v. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2, 1115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A. (2006). Beyond plurals. In Rayo, A., and Uzquiano, G., editors. Absolute Generality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 220254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rayo, A., & Yablo, S. (2001). Nominalism through de-nominalization. Noûs, 35, 7492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rieppel, M. (2016). Being something: Properties and predicative quantification. Mind, 125(499), 643689.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, D. (1974). Axiomatizing set theory. In Jech, T., editor. Axiomatic Set Theory II. Proceedings of the Symposium in Pure Mathematics of the American Mathematical Society, July–August 1967. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society, pp. 207214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. (1974). Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar. London: Methuen & Co. Google Scholar
Strawson, P. (1987). Concepts and properties or predication and copulation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 37, 402406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, W. W. (2001). Gödel’s unpublished papers on the foundations of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 9, 87126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trueman, R. (2021). Properties and Propositions: The Metaphysics of Higher-Order Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Whitehead, A., & Russell, B. (1910). Principia Mathematica (first edition), Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. (1984). The sense and reference of predicates: A running repair of Frege’s doctrine and a plea for the copula. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34(136), 311328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2003). Everything. Philosophical Perspectives, 17(1), 415465.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (2013). Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. (1998). Why Frege does not deserve his grain of salt. In Hale, B., and Wright, C., editors. The Reason’s Proper Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7290.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (2007). On quantifying into predicate position: Steps towards a new(tralist) perspective. In Potter, M., editor. Mathematical Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 150174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar