Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T08:32:05.395Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Environmentally Induced Displacement: When (Ecological) Vulnerability Turns into Resilience (and Asylum)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 March 2024

Francesca Ippolito*
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of International Law, University of Cagliari, Italy, Jean Monnet Chair in European Climate of Change (REACT)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article aims to reflect on ‘ecological vulnerability’ – which makes evident the relationship, flows and interactions between the human being/body and the environment/non-human world – as applied in the context of environmentally induced migration. In particular, the dual role of the law vis-à-vis environmentally displaced migrants as a generator and exacerbator of their vulnerability as well as potential antidote, valuable for attaining protection, will be highlighted. Namely, on one hand, the analysis will show how a lack of conceptualisation of the notion to understand the spatial and temporal patterns of climate change-related migration, as well as its consequences for societal well-being, contributes to generate and exacerbate the vulnerability of that category of migrants. On the other hand, the critical understanding of vulnerability, as developed in some recent legal reasoning of international and national jurisdictions, will be proposed as a key element for ensuring the resilience of both environmental migrants and the law itself, for both virtuously expanding traditional asylum norms and flexibilising access to international protection for those migrants.

Type
Special Issue Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

Recent literature (Turner, Reference Turner2006; Fineman, Reference Fineman2008; Fineman and Grear, Reference Fineman and Grear2013; Goodin, Reference Goodin1985; Kittay, Reference Kittay1999; Beckett, Reference Beckett2006), in the realms of philosophy, legal theory and ethics, particularly feminist legal theory (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014; Fineman, Reference Fineman2015; Grear, Reference Grear2010), approaches vulnerability as a means to revolutionise the architecture of law, which is constructed around the ideal of a rational subject excised from both embodiment and socio-cultural context (Grear, Reference Grear, Jones, Grear, Fenton and Stevenson2011). The ‘vulnerable subject’ is advanced instead as a more realistic alternative (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008), stressing vulnerability and the ontological experience of all human beings as part of the personal, economic, social, and cultural circumstances in which individuals find themselves at different points in their lives, and as a fundamental feature of humanity (Turner, Reference Turner2006).

Such a shared ‘ontological insecurity’, characterised as a constant exposure to potential harm (whether intentional or accidental), may arise from: (i) ‘our corporeality, our neediness, our dependence on others, and our affective and social natures’ (inherent vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014); (ii) situational and context-specific conditions including personal, social, economic and environmental conditions, so being a product of genetic, social and environmental factors actually present or latent (situational vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers, and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014; Fineman, Reference Fineman2008; Peroni and Timmer, Reference Peroni and Timmer2013; Neal, Reference Neal2012); (iii) the exacerbation or compounding of existing types of vulnerability, including ‘morally dysfunctional interpersonal and social relationships characterised by disrespect, prejudice or abuse, or by socio-political situations characterised by oppression, domination, repression, injustice, persecution or political violence’ (pathogenic vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014); or (iv) contingencies that follow a choice (discretionary vulnerability) (Lotz, Reference Lotz2016). Such different and complex kinds of vulnerability may be superposed and experienced simultaneously (compounded vulnerability) (Luna, Reference Luna2009). As applied to the context migration, migrant vulnerability (Bronfenbrenner, Reference Bronfenbrenner1979) – or ‘migratory vulnerability’ (Baumgärtel, Reference Baumgärtel2020; Baumgärtel and Ganty, in this issue) – is normally associated with multiple factors. Some relate to individuals and their family circumstances. In other cases, vulnerability is associated with community factors, including availability of quality educational opportunities, health care and social services; equal access to resources; livelihood and income-generating opportunities; the natural environment and social norms and behaviours. Finally, structural factors of migrant vulnerability are the political, economic, social, and environmental conditions and institutions at national, regional and international levels. Footnote 1 The law also plays a key role (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue).

Most recently, however, building on Fineman’ conceptualisation, a theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’ has also been elaborated (Harris, Reference Harris2014) to make evident the relationship and interactions between the human being/body and the environment/non-human world. Through the concept of ‘ecological vulnerability’ it is recognised that humans are vulnerable not only because they age, become ill and die, ‘but because their survival depends on complex macro- and micro-ecologies – all of which are, in turn, vulnerable to harm’. As Harris (Reference Harris2014) underlines, adopting the language of ‘ecological vulnerability’ implies the necessity – well-explained by Bennet – of having to ‘admit that humans have crawled or secreted themselves into every corner of the environment; admit that the environment is actually inside human bodies and minds, and then proceed politically, technologically, scientifically, in everyday life, with careful forbearance’ (Bennet, Reference Bennet2010). According to Harris, ‘ecological vulnerability’ recognises that human lives are part of complex ecosystems that operate on various levels of scale, from the local to the global. She acknowledges that ‘in the age of the Anthropocene, when human activity is rapidly causing large-scale, not fully predictable, and potentially irreversible changes to our inner and outer environments’, the fully ‘responsive State’ (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008) should recognise that soil degradation, water scarcity, warming oceans, and depleted fishing stocks structure our options and create opportunities just as market and family relations do. In the age of the Anthropocene, it can no longer be argued that these environmental processes and events are outside the circle of justice. ‘Human behaviour’ and ‘the natural world’ are now locked in an ever-tightening feedback loop. Climate change represents the most dramatic example of this indivisibility of humans and ‘the environment’ (Pachauri etal., 2014; Grant, Kotze and Morrow, Reference Grant, Kotze and Morrow2013) being evident in the close interrelationship between greenhouse gas emissions, large-scale ecosystem and trans-human system disruptions, and human life and health. Thus, the applicability of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ notion to environmentally induced migration can serve to reframe the reach of law, including the scope of non-refoulement, that is, to assess the situation in the country of destination in the event of forcible expulsion of ‘climate refugees’. Accordingly, what this article proposes is that the non-refoulement principle – the main protection of those in need of international protection – should be re-interpreted in the sense that the risk of exposure to inhuman treatment to be assessed in the country of destination should encompass not only the individual situation (regarding threats of persecution or ill treatment) but also the overall conditions in the country, considering especially the level of an adequate standard of living in line with basic human rights. This – the recognition in law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) of ‘ecological vulnerability’ as a relevant factor in the non-refoulement assessment – could generate a (virtuous) expansion of traditional asylum norms and the flexibilization of access to international protection for that particular category of migrants (European Commission, 2022) in line with the evolving standards of international law.

2 Law as generator and exacerbator of environmental migrants’ vulnerability and the resilience of human rights

Since the expression ‘climate/or environmental refugees’ was first used in 1985 by El-Hinnawi and subsequently recurred in literature and political/institutional documents (e.g. European Parliament, 2011), it has served to bring to the fore the existence of three cumulative elements that characterise the plight of this category of persons: (i) the departure from the usual location; (ii) the existence of a climatic breach (due to natural or human causes, slow onset or not) that impacts and threatens human life and (iii) serious perturbances to living conditions. Despite the literal tenor of the expression (climate/or environmental refugees), however, the international refugee law framework, enshrined in the 1951 Convention Relative to the Status of Refugees Footnote 2 and its 1967 Protocol, Footnote 3 does not represent the normative source of their protection. In fact, the element of persecution that characterises the current definition of a ‘refugee’, based on ‘race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social group or political opinion’ (Goodwin-Gill and McAdam, Reference Goodwin-Gill and McAdam2007), is absent in the case of climate or environmentally induced migrations. Although adverse environmental and climate impacts could characterise any related harm as sufficiently severe (Foster, Reference Foster2009); environmental and climate change consequences are indiscriminate, and thus not tied to individuals’ backgrounds or beliefs (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011). There is nonetheless scope for some exceptions, where exposure to climate impacts or environmental degradation in themselves amount to persecution: if government policies target particular groups reliant on agriculture for survival or use starvation or famine as a political tool (Schmeidl, Reference Schmeidl, Zolberg and Benda2001), or contribute to environmental destruction, Footnote 4 or even desertification (Cooper, Reference Cooper1998; Kozoll, Reference Kozoll2004). This flows from developments in international human rights law that have informed the meaning of persecution and harm within the international refugee law regime (Foster, Reference Foster2009; McAdam, Reference McAdam2009) allowing for persecution to take the form of socio-economic deprivation (Foster, Reference Foster2009).

Moreover, as climate change is a gradual process, it is possible that some individuals will voluntarily leave the affected area before it becomes uninhabitable so that the characterisation of any ensuing harm as akin to persecution becomes too remote. This relates to a third issue, namely that it is extremely difficult to disentangle the specific cause of displacement from other connected factors, due to the incremental impacts of climate change on the broader political and socio-economic context (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011). Arelated matter concerns the problematic notion of climate change as violating human rights per se. Furthermore, while Article 1(A)(2) of the 1951 Convention requires the refugee to be ‘unable or owing to such fear … unwilling to vail himself from the protection of that country’, the country of origin may still be willing to protect its displaced inhabitants; the problem lying instead in its (in)capacity to do so.

But the limits of the notion of ‘environmental/climate refugees’ do not end in its inability to include environmental and climate refugees within the frame of international refugee law. Such a notion is not a shared one at either the international or the European level. In fact, a definition according to which climate-induced migration occurs every time a person cannot stay in their home due to a habitual climatic event is too vague and broad to come within the remit of international refugee law (Myers and Kent, Reference Myers and Kent1995). An agreement instead exists about the crossing of an international border and the vulnerability of such migrants, which bears strict similarities with the vulnerabilities of those who are unable to access safe, affordable and regular migration pathways (UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, 2018). The need for a coercive element to exist to qualify for international protection (Keane, Reference Keane2004) is not without criticism either. Thus, it can hardly be determined whether a migrant anticipating a rise in sea level or a drought is allowed (under international law) to organise his/her departure and even choose his/her receiving state (Gonin and Lassailly-Jacob, Reference Gonin and Lassailly-Jacob2002). Anyhow, at least the idea that the coercion that makes people leave, at the basis of climate/environmentally induced migration, shall be linked to an irresistible (sudden or gradual) environmental disaster/event that inexorably impacts the living conditions of those concerned should be retained.Footnote 5 The lack of consensus on how to define climate refugees makes it extremely difficult to develop an international instrument to protect them – whether in the form of an ad hoc Convention or an Additional Protocol to the 1951 Refugee Convention (Bierman and Boas, Reference Biermann and Boas2007; Hulme, Reference Hulme2008; Traore Chazalnoel and Ionescoor, Reference Traore Chazalnoele, Ionesco, Behrman and Kent2018) or to the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011), or as a reformulation of Article 1(A) of the 1951 Refugee Convention, to encompass within the refugee definition also those at risk to their personal psycho-physical integrity due to the effects of environmental degradation. This puts environmentally displaced persons outside the law’s protection (in quite a literal sense), with the consequence that the law’s exclusion ends up exacerbating vulnerabilities (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) and manifests itself as ill-suited to address their plight (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011).

Law, nonetheless, offers some respite in the specific regional context represented by the Organisation of African Unity (OAU) Convention (1974) and the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights (1986), which provide an extended refugee definition, encompassing those displaced due to ‘events seriously disturbing public order’ (Atapattu, Reference Atapattu2010) that could be read as accommodating climate disasters. People may therefore be eligible as refugees when displaced by climate change or an environmental disaster and fall under the protection of these regional instruments.

At the international level, the work of the International Law and Sea Level Rise Committee, which operates within the International Law Association (ILA) and of the International Law Commission’s working-group on Sea-level rise (ILA, 2022; Marchegiani, Reference Marchegiani2022; European Commission, 2016), is promising. The same applies to international human rights law, which offers some possibilities to bounce back from the challenges of climate/environmentally induced migration, giving expression to the different capacities of: (i) coping (Keck and Sakdapolrak, Reference Keck and Sakdapolrak2013) or maintaining, (ii) adapting and/or (iii) transforming (Methmann and Oels, Reference Methmann and Oels2015) the environmental vulnerability-exacerbating effects of climate change. The applicability of international human rights law persists in the context of forced migration, in particular, the positive duties attached to the obligation of non-refoulement. Footnote 6 Extreme situations of socioeconomic destitution, particularly in relation to vulnerable individuals, in fact, may amount to inhuman or degrading treatment and hence trigger the application of the principle of non-refoulement under human rights law. Footnote 7 Anon-refoulement effect has been applied also to non-absolute rights, Footnote 8 where there was a risk of a ‘flagrant violation’ Footnote 9 of attendant guarantees. Arisk of ‘irreparable harm’ in the receiving state, Footnote 10 a ‘reasonable risk of [a] violation of their fundamental rights’, Footnote 11 or a risk for the individual of suffering ‘serious forms of discrimination’ or gender-based violence have been considered sufficient to halt deportations. Footnote 12 Against this background, it is worth exploring whether human rights law has the potential of offering additional protection (through the concept of ‘ecological vulnerability’) in order to extend the protective application of the principle of non-refoulement to displaced persons who have crossed an international border due to environmental degradation or climate change. Adding to the reflections in this Special Issue, the next section thus turns to examine the potential of ‘ecological vulnerability’, when recognised in and through law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) to expand the non-refoulement obligation to cover and offer protection to environmental migrants.

3 The potential of vulnerability to expand the non-refoulement obligation to environmental migrants

Non-refoulement operates on the basis of the ‘returnability test’, thus on the ‘permissibility, feasibility (factual possibility) and reasonableness of return’ (Kälin, Reference Kälin and McAdam2010) in the light of the individual situation of the applicant in the event of expulsion. Therefore, state authorities should provide an adequate and individualised assessment of the risk of a threat to the applicant’s right to life or his/her right to not be subjected to inhuman or degrading treatment in the country of envisaged return. In such an assessment, vulnerability theories have played a role in the reasoning of human rights courts and UN monitoring bodies, expanding the protection by, for instance, lowering the threshold of risk (Ippolito, Reference Ippolito2020). On this basis, what this section will determine, when non-returnability is analysed in relation to climate induced displacement, is whether, through the protection par ricochet of the right to life, the application of vulnerability, and especially of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory on the dependence of mankind on the environment and various ecosystems as recalled in the previous section, should entail an expansion of the positive obligations attached to the principle of non-refoulement vis-a-vis environmentally displaced migrants.

The decision by the UN Human Rights Committee in the case of Ioane Teitiota v. New Zealand Footnote 13 – assessed positively by some (Behlert, Reference Behlert2020; McAdam, Reference McAdam2020; Schuetze, Reference Shuetze2020) or more critically by others (Behrmane and Kent, Reference Behrmane and Kent2020; Cullen Reference Cullen2020; Imbert, Reference Imbert2020; Le Moli, Reference Le Moli2020; Rive, Reference Rive2020; Scott, Reference Scott2019) – illustrates some of such a protective potential of a vulnerability-inspired reading of non-refoulement. The case concerned a family from the Republic of Kiribati, a Pacific Island-nation projected to be completely submerged by water by 2050, who applied in New Zealand for refugee status based on ‘changes to their environment in Kiribati caused by sea-level-rise associated with climate change’ that threatened their lives and wellbeing – having arrived there in 2007 and stayed well after their permits expired in 2010. All the national levels of jurisdiction dismissed the request for refugee status on the grounds that the Kiribati citizens did not ‘objectively face a real risk of being persecuted if returned to Kiribati’ (at 4) and that there was insufficient evidence to show that Mr Teitiota and his family faced a ‘real chance of suffering serious physical harm from violence’, or that he would be unable to find land accommodation to grow food and obtain potable water. Furthermore, there was no evidence that the environmental conditions in Tarawa were ‘so perilous that Teitiota’s life [and that of his family] would be jeopardised’ (ibid.). When the case reached the UN Human Rights Committee, arguing that New Zealand had violated Mr Teitiota’s right to life under Article 6 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), that argument was dismissed.

However, building on the consideration that the protection of the right to life implies positive obligations, including those arising from international environmental law (acknowledged first in the Portillo Càceres case),Footnote 14 the Committee interpreted the normative content of the right in an evolutionary way, comprehensive of the positive duty to protect not only against imminent risks to life but also against ‘reasonably foreseeable threats and life-threatening situations that can result in loss of life’, Footnote 15 even if they do not result in actual (and immediate) loss of life. Footnote 16 The Committee further recalled that environmental degradation and climate change constitute some of the most pressing and serious threats to the ability of present and future generations to effectively enjoy the right to life. Footnote 17 Interpreting the right to life as the right to enjoy a life with dignity, together with the acknowledgment of the existence of a close correlation between the obligations placed on states under international environmental law and the protection of the right to life enshrined in Article 6 ICCPR, Footnote 18 brought the Human Rights Committee to recognise that, without robust national and international efforts, the effects of climate change in receiving states may expose individuals to a violation of their rights under Articles 6 and/or 7 of the Covenant, thereby triggering their non-refoulement obligations. Furthermore, given the risk of an entire country becoming submerged under water and its potentially extreme consequences, the conditions of life in such a country may become incompatible with the right to a life with dignity before the risk materialises. Footnote 19 However, the risk of serious harm to life must be personal and cannot result simply from the general conditions of the receiving country, except in extreme cases. Therefore, Mr. Teitiota, not complaining of a strictly personal risk and with the Committee not taking into account a ‘cumulative assessment’ of all the relevant factors (McAdam, Reference McAdam2020) to assess the risk holistically, would have needed to provide proof of the uninhabitability of Kiribati to avoid expulsion.

The application of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory could have helped in refocusing the assessment in the light of the specific vulnerabilities of the applicant in relation also to the overall conditions in the country, in particular considering the level of an adequate standard of living, whose components include access to adequate food, clothing, housing and the continuous improvement of living conditions, as well as the right not to be deprived of livelihood means – all elements that are extremely affected by both environmental degradation and climate change. In particular, the theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’ could have been used to demonstrate that intermediate degrees of exposure to climate-induced harms may trigger non-refoulement protection. The theory would have served to jointly consider extreme conditions, making life unliveable, alongside the unbearable effects of environmental degradation, before the risk is realised (at 9.11) but being nonetheless imminent (at 9.12). Footnote 20

Namely, ‘ecological vulnerability’ may lower the evidence threshold necessary to prove the risk, giving rise to a ‘wider and more tailored net than the generic non-refoulement obligations’ (Pobjoy, Reference Pobjoy2017), as well as a broader and more flexible definition of harm (Sommario, Reference Sommario2021). ‘Ecological vulnerability’ draws from an intersectional evaluation of all the relevant risk factors as they interact together. If generalised, an ecological vulnerability-inspired evaluation would transform the assessment of, for instance, age-related vulnerabilities in a revolutionary way. In this regard, the Committee on the Rights of the Child (CRC Committee) has developed the notion of ‘other irreparable harm’ as ‘also includ[ing] harm to the survival, development, or health (physical or mental) of the child’, Footnote 21 which in the Committee’s jurisprudence requires the right to survival and development as implemented through the combined enforcement of the rights to health, adequate nutrition, an adequate standard of living, and a healthy and safe environment. Footnote 22 This, interpreted in light of the best interests of the child, is gaining momentum and becoming an effective strategy in the fight against climate change (Ippolito, Reference Ippolito2020, Reference Ippolito2022, Reference Ippolito2023; Liguori, 2022).

A similar approach might also turn to be applicable before the Human Rights Committee in future cases. Article 24(1) ICCPR entitles every child to special measures designed to protect its life in addition to the general measures required under Article 6 ICCPR for the protection of the lives of all individuals. Accordingly, when taking special measures of protection, states should be guided by the best interests of the child and the need to ensure the survival and development of all children and their well-being. This should apply also with specific regard to those positive obligations of a ‘special character’, which deal ‘with the conditions of the causes of the violation’ of Article 2 and 6 ICCPR. Footnote 23

The Human Rights Committee has partially embraced this understanding in its most recent case law, specifically in a case concerning aboriginal Australians with ancestral ties to the land and territorial sea in Torres Islands, Footnote 24 on consideration that their way of life and culture were being seriously threatened by the prospect of becoming displaced (together with the disappearance of certain species in the sea that are basic foodstuff the complainants depend on). In this case, the vulnerability of the applicants as indigenous people played a role in the configuration of their status as ‘victims’ under the Covenant, which was contested by the defendant state because it related to a form of future harm which had yet to materialise in any existing or foreseeable violation of, or threat to, their rights due to climate impacts. Using a precautionary approach to the interpretation of the notion of ‘imminence’ of the harm concerned (Anderson, Foster, Lambert and McAdam, Reference Anderson, Foster, Lambert and McAdam2019), the Committee did not reason in the sense that the risk must materialise within a short time (using a temporal frame). Instead, it considered those risks that directly (in a causal sense) threaten the persons involved, Footnote 25 linking the ‘alleged serious adverse impacts that have already occurred and are ongoing’ with the foreseeable consequent impairment of rights under the Covenant.

Thus, vulnerability played a role in the determination of the responsibility of Australia, as the destination country, for failing to adopt timely and adequate adaptation measures to protect the collective ability of people to maintain their traditional way of life, to transmit to their children and future generations their culture and traditions, and make use of ancestral land and sea resources. This amounted to a violation of the positive obligation to protect the right to enjoy their minority culture Footnote 26 and should be considered in the individual assessment of the applicant risk situation, as complemented by the overall conditions in the country, considering the level of (for example) an adequate standard of living.

In light of the statement contained in para 9.12 of the Teitiota decision, according to which ‘the assistance of the international community, to take affirmative measures to protect and, where necessary, relocate its population’, this reasoning might also pave the way to a possible application of the positive obligation of non-refoulement, binding the returning/expelling state to a form of subsidiary responsibility to protect third-country nationals (Schefer and Cottier, Reference Schefer and Cottier2015) in those cases where the countries of return are not able to protect them (Maneggia, Reference Maneggia2022). This would considerably extend the non-refoulement protection available to environmentally displaced migrants.

4 Vulnerability as a tool for an expansive reading of complementary protection regimes under EU law able to encompass environmentally-induced migration

Another way in which ‘ecological vulnerability’ might expand human rights protection is via favouring an extensive interpretation of complementary protection regimes, such as humanitarian forms of national protection and the ‘subsidiary protection’ offered by the Qualification Directive in the European Union to persons who do not qualify as refugees but are ‘otherwise’ in need of ‘international protection’. Footnote 27 According to Article 2(e) of the Directive, in fact, a person who is eligible for subsidiary protection is:

‘any third country national or stateless person who does not qualify as a refugee, but in respect of whom there are substantial grounds for believing that the person concerned, if returned to his or her country of origin or, in the case of a stateless person, to his or her country of former habitual residence, would face a real risk of being subjected to serious harm, would face a real risk of suffering the serious harm defined in Article 15, Article 17(1) and (2) not being applicable to that person, and that person being unable or, in view of that risk, unwilling to avail himself or herself of the protection of that country’.

Article 15 further defines ‘serious harm’ as:

  1. (a) the death penalty or execution, or

  2. (b) torture or inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment of an applicant in his or her country of origin, or

  3. (c) serious and individual threat to the life or person of a civilian by reason of indiscriminate violence or in case of internal or international armed conflict.

This list of different types of ‘serious harm’ does not explicitly include harm caused by global environmental problems. However, serious environmental problems may have similar effects to inhuman treatment as those set out in Article 15(b) of the Directive.

According to the case law of the European Court of Justice (CJEU), to qualify for subsidiary protection it is necessary to show that a threat of ‘serious harm’ is ‘individual’, either by reasons of ‘specific risk’ factors to do with a person’s particular characteristics or circumstances or by the ‘general risk’ factors arising out of an exceptional situation of a very high level of violence in the country of origin. Footnote 28 The Court appears to be following a ‘sliding scale’ approach (see further, Moreno-Lax and Garlick, Reference Moreno-Lax, Garlick, Peers, Moreno-Lax, Garlick and Guild2015), balancing individual threat and indiscriminate violence as two extremes of the same continuum, applying a notion of ‘general risk’ similar to the one developed in the case law of the ECtHR relating to Article 3 ECHR. Footnote 29 However, it seems to only apply this reasoning to situations related to Article 15(c) of the Qualification Directive, despite the fact that Article 15(b) of the Directive is based upon the jurisprudence of the ECtHR on Article 3 ECHR. In this connection, the Court has noted, in the case M’Bodj, Footnote 30 precisely that Article 15(b):

‘must be interpreted as meaning that serious harm … does not cover a situation in which inhuman or degrading treatment … to which an applicant suffering from a serious illness may be subjected if returned to his country of origin, is the result of the fact that appropriate treatment is not available in that country, unless such an applicant is intentionally deprived of health care’ (para. 41).

It seems therefore clear that the relevant ‘serious harm’ must necessarily derive from the conduct of an actor, rather than simply result from general shortcomings in the health system of the country of origin (para. 35). Applied to climate change-related effects, the logical consequence seems to be that, under Article 15(b) of the Qualification Directive, ‘serious harm’ cannot stem from a general situation obtaining from climate-change effects. However, the wording of Article 6 of the Qualification Directive does not preclude the application of subsidiary protection to cases of illness where the risks are situational rather than coming from an identifiable actor, as the list provided in this provision is merely indicative. Moreover, the wording and risk assessment criteria used by the Directive in Article 15(b) are borrowed from Strasbourg’s jurisprudence on Article 3 ECHR and, as noted, the main significance of Article 15(b) is precisely found in it ‘affording a status, rather than simply rendering non-removable, persons in these circumstances’ (Costello, Reference Costello2015). Therefore, a different reading of Article 15(b) could be imagined, inclusive of the risks facing environmentally induced migrants. The recent jurisprudence of the CJEU in Hamed seems to go towards this direction. Footnote 31 In Hamed, the CJEU insisted on the concept of the violation of human dignity linked to Article 4 of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights on the prohibition of ill-treatment as requiring a particularly high threshold of seriousness. It, however, acknowledged that such seriousness encompasses cases where state authorities’ acts or omissions create a situation of extreme material deprivation that would prevent the claimant from meeting their most basic needs and that would impair their physical or mental health or place them in a state of degradation incompatible with human dignity. This should not exclude cases where the serious humanitarian emergency is also caused or exacerbated by climate change and is connected with the vicious circle of poverty, conflict, violence, and the high level of insecurity in which the civilian population may find itself.

National case law concerning requests for asylum or entry visas in connection with phenomena related to climate change, environmental degradation, or natural or man-made disasters, already offers inspiring prospects. The case of Italy, to which the next section turns, identifies specific solutions, including the possibility of issuing a residence permit for disasters and of recognising special protection for those who, as a result of repatriation, would find themselves in a condition of vulnerability, including as a consequence of environmental or climate change.

5 The protective potential of vulnerability-based reasoning in national humanitarian jurisprudence

The case of Italy is particularly illustrative of a proactive vulnerability-inspired reading of the principle of non-refoulement applied to environmentally induced migration, Footnote 32 demonstrating the protective potential of the concept as and when mediated through law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue). Initially, the possibility of issuing a residence permit for ‘serious reasons of a humanitarian nature or arising from constitutional or international obligations of the Italian State’ Footnote 33 facilitated such a proactive outcome. Such a permit could be released by the Questore upon request or, in cases of rejection of the application for international protection, by the Territorial Commissions where the applicant did not qualify for refugee status or subsidiary protection proper, but still was confronted in the state of origin with ‘serious reasons’ of a humanitarian nature. In the absence of specifications regarding the requirements necessary for the issuance of such permits, the institutions have lent themselves to a broad interpretation regarding those persons who have suffered, or would be at risk of suffering upon removal, an ‘effective deprivation of human rights’. The risk assessment is conducted considering the applicant’s personal conditions in light of the prevailing situation in the country of origin. Indeed, the reference to their individual vulnerability on account also of slow-onset events has allowed Territorial Commissions Footnote 34 – and also Courts Footnote 35 – to extend these permits with respect to serious natural disasters, Footnote 36 droughts, Footnote 37 famine Footnote 38 and floods, Footnote 39 so enlarging the spectrum of situations of non-returnability in case of undignified and unsafe conditions in the country of return. Footnote 40

In the reasoning of the superior jurisdictions, it has been the situational vulnerability of applicants that has been central to extend the recognition of humanitarian non-refoulement in cases where situations that include adverse climatic conditions Footnote 41 may expose the applicant, upon removal, to the risk of a standard of living that does not respect core fundamental rights (including situations of drought, famine, or of unsustainable poverty). Footnote 42 That was the case, for instance, in the most recent jurisprudence of the Italian Court of Cassation, Footnote 43 following the appeal of a man from the Niger Delta against a decision by the Tribunal of Ancona rejecting international protection. The Court recognized the applicability of humanitarian protection (Passarini, Reference Passarini2022; Perrini, Reference Perrini2021) when the situation in the country of origin does not allow for a ‘minimum essential guarantee’ for the individual’s right to life. In particular, the recognition of humanitarian protection on the basis of Article 5(6) of the Testo Unico (TU) on immigration Footnote 44 was significantly anchored to an international obligation, with explicit references to the Teitiota case. The need for the expelling state to assess the individual risk of inhuman or degrading treatment in the country of expulsion alongside the general risk of undignified leaving conditions due to environmental degradation, climate change or unsustainable development in the area, was acknowledged. Footnote 45 Moreover, the Court reduced the burden of proof on asylum seekers in need of humanitarian protection on account of the effects of climate change, so that the more severe the situation of environmental degradation existing in the country of origin, the lesser the need to prove individual vulnerability; and this, especially, if environmental degradation derives from human action or inaction that excludes entire parts of the population from access to essential natural resources, such as cultivable land and drinkable water. In the case at hand, according to the Court, there was no doubt that the appellant was exposed to a situation of serious environmental degradation insofar as no policies were provided in the country of origin to fight against pollution and mitigate climate change. Footnote 46 To the contrary, it retained that the disastrous climatic situation of the country of origin was determined by the conduct of government authorities regarding industrial shrimp farming, the occupation of the territory with expanses of aquaculture tanks and an active policy of deforestation Footnote 47 that exposed the individual to the risk of seeing his fundamental rights to life and dignified existence annihilated, or in any case reduced below the threshold of their essential and inescapable core. Footnote 48 Following the Court of Cassation, an analogous reasoning has been applied by lower courts when confronted with environmental disasters stemming from intentional human misconduct or the over-exploitation of natural resources that endangers a claimant’s life or safety Footnote 49 .

Turning the attention to other European jurisdictions, it is possible to notice the same evolutive interpretation of non-refoulement and humanitarian protection in other countries as well (Scissa, Reference Scissa2021). For instance, the High Administrative Court of Baden-Württemberg, in 2020, annulled the repatriation decree issued to an Afghan national, partly because of the environmental and climatic conditions obtaining in the country of origin. Footnote 50 Like in the Italian jurisprudence, the situational vulnerability of the applicant was instrumental to a reinterpretation of the notion of inhumane and degrading treatment, considering not only the humanitarian situation in the country of origin, covering both the social and economic conditions there, but also the individual situation of the individual concerned. Footnote 51 Accordingly, the principle of non-refoulement has been considered applicable even when the terrible humanitarian conditions facing applicants are attributable to poverty or lack of state resources to deal with a natural phenomenon (Schloss, Reference Schloss2021).

A similar reasoning has been deployed by the Court of Appeal of Bordeaux, Footnote 52 which ruled that a temporary residence permit (carte de séjour temporaire) for medical treatment should be issued to an asylum seeker from Bangladesh because, due to the health and environmental conditions in his country, he would not have access to the essential health treatment he needed. The French Code on the Entry and Stay of Foreigners and the Right of Asylum provides for the possibility of issuing a temporary residence permit to a foreigner, habitually residing in France, who presents a state of health such that, if not treated, he would risk consequences of exceptional seriousness. In this sense, Article L. 313-11 provides that:

Sauf si sa présence constitue une menace pour l’ordre public, la carte de séjour temporaire portant la mention “vie privée et familiale” est délivrée de plein droit : … 11° Al’étranger résidant habituellement en France, si son état de santé nécessite une prise en charge médicale dont le défaut pourrait avoir pour lui des conséquences d’une exceptionnelle gravité et si, eu égard à l’offre de soins et aux caractéristiques du système de santé dans le pays dont il est originaire, il ne pourrait pas y bénéficier effectivement d’un traitement approprié’.

In the case at hand, the plaintiff suffered from a certified chronic respiratory condition, aggravated by a severe form of allergic asthma and sleep apnoea syndrome, which required the use of an electric ventilation device every night, as well as frequent maintenance and replacement of the mask, filters, and tubes. The Court of Appeal, once more, based on the vulnerability of the applicant and in the light of the general situation in his country of origin, ordered the issuance of the temporary residence permit. The reasoning stressed how in Bangladesh the rate of particulate matter pollutants is one of the highest in the world, so that, the mortality rate from respiratory diseases is 12.92 percent compared to 0.82 percent in France. Footnote 53 Those grounds served the Court to take account of the ‘very compelling humanitarian grounds’ standard, as articulated by the ECtHR in its case-law on ‘humanitarian non-refoulement’ of persons at risk of ill-treatment on health grounds, due to the lack of sufficient resources to deal with their condition in the receiving country. Footnote 54 Anchoring its reasoning in this ECtHR jurisprudence, Footnote 55 the Court formulated a positive obligation on the expelling state for the prevention of the further vulnerabilisation of the applicant. Such a positive obligation, insofar as the non-refoulement principle was at stake, implied that an individual assessment of the applicant’s condition in the receiving state had to include how his condition would evolve upon expulsion, Footnote 56 particularly in the light of the distinguishing features that make the lack of health services especially deleterious in the applicant’s regard, especially when combined with environmental degradation and underlying socio-economic vulnerabilities.

This reasoning, in the case at hand, led the applicant to obtain the extension of his residence permit for medical treatment given the severe environmental and health conditions prevailing in the country of origin. Footnote 57 Its extension to similar cases could even lead to new forms of asylum based on the cumulative impacts of climate change on people’s ability to enjoy their socio-economic rights when removal to ‘destitution’ amounts to inhuman or degrading treatment. Footnote 58

6 Concluding remarks: vulnerability to shore up an emerging law for the protection of environmental migrants?

Environmentally induced migration, together with the other drivers of migration, such as economic deprivation, social discrimination, and politically adverse conditions, acts as a push factor on human mobility (cf. Grundler, in this issue). However, environmental migrants remain undefined under international law and the lack of any conceptualisation of the notion of vulnerability, letalone an articulation of the theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’, in their regard makes it difficult to develop an international legal instrument to protect them, while at the same time leaving them unprotected under current (refugee) law. The law itself exacerbates the vulnerability facing environmental migrants (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue). Nonetheless, as the previous sections have shown, human rights law and, in particular, the principle of non-refoulement may offer some respite when interpreted through an intersectional, holistic lens that takes account of all the relevant circumstances of each individual case (Moreno-Lax, Reference Moreno-Lax2021).

In particular, the vulnerability (whether situational, contextual, or compounded) of environmental migrants could well become an empowering tool, if the notion of ‘ecological vulnerability’ would be legally employed by Courts and decision-makers around the world. The analysis above has shown how that notion may help in reconceptualizing non-refoulement obligations, generating a (virtuous) expansion of traditional asylum norms and the flexibilisation of access to international protection for environmentally and climate-induced migrants (European Commission, 2021). Namely, in the same vein that feminist studies have valorised the notion of ‘vulnerability’ to generate a more ‘responsive State’ (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008), discharging positive obligations of redistributive justice, when applied to the expulsion of environmental and climate-induced migrants, an ecological vulnerability-mediated interpretation of the law allows for an expansive (and principled) application of the non-refoulement obligation and the generation of additional humanitarian protection. The advent of the Anthropocene era requires a heightened awareness of the relationship between humans and the environments in which they live, which provides the grounds for said vulnerability to be considered pertinent and applicable in legal assessment. Emphasizing the ‘prognosis’ function of the ‘returnability test’, the application of an ‘ecological vulnerability’ lens should imply a refocusing of the assessment of individual situations in the destination country by expelling states to determine the ‘reasonableness of return’ (Kälin, Reference Kälin and McAdam2010). This should be conducted in the light of both the individual risk situation facing applicants and the general conditions obtaining in the country of origin, which should not amount to a breach of the right to a dignified life, including due to climate change and environmental degradation, interpreting the imminence of the risk not as the necessity that the risk materialises within a short period of time, but rather as comprising those risks that are directly threatening the persons involved in a material and causal sense.

Alternatively, or complementarily, the application of the same ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory could not only exclude or nuance the returnability of environmental migrants, but additionally serve to advance the case for their substantive protection. An ecological vulnerability-imbued reinterpretation of the law favours an extensive construal of the complementary protection regimes such as the ‘subsidiary protection’ offered under the EU Qualification Directive and similar national forms of humanitarian protection. Should some of the national practices explored in this article further expand, (ecological) vulnerability may become a helpful device to alleviate harm and produce new forms of asylum from the worst collateral effects of unsustainable development and climate change. In so doing, this expansion would help realising justice by contributing to achieving ‘just resilience’, which is essential for the equitable distribution of climate adaptation benefits (European Commission, 2021).

Acknowledgments

This article belongs to the Special Issue: Law, Migration and Vulnerability: From the Margins to the Centre, edited by Violeta Moreno-Lax and Niovi Vavoula, which is a deliverable of the Migration and Asylum Policy Systems (MAPS) Jean Monnet Network <https://www.mapsnetwork.eu/> funded by the Jean Monnet Programme (2018-2022) 599856-EPP-1-2018-1-IT-EPPJMO-NETWORK, Grant decision 2018-1606/001-001. Iam indebted to the editors and peer-reviewers for their generous feedback.

Competing Interests

None.

Footnotes

1 This is the model of migrants vulnerability developed by the International Organisation for Migrations (IOM). Available at: https://www.iom.int/sites/g/files/tmzbdl486/files/our_work/DMM/MPA/1-part1-thedomv.pdf.

2 Opened for signature 28 July 1951, 189 UNTS 137 (entered into force 22 April 1954) (‘Refugee Convention’).

3 The 1967 Protocol relating to the Status of Refugees, opened for signature 31 January 1966, 606 UNTS 267 (entered into force 4 October 1967), removed the temporal limitation of Art. 1A(2) (‘[a]s a result of events occurring before 1 January 1951’) and, for new contracting parties, removed the option of entering a geographical reservation (‘events occurring in Europe’).

4 See e.g. Social and Economic Rights Action Center v Nigeria, Communication No 155/96 (2001), reproduced in African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, Fifteenth Annual Activity Report of the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights 2001–2002 (7 May 2002) annex V, 31 [2].

5 On this, see the International Centre of Comparative Environmental Law of the University of Limoge, Draft Convention on the international status of environmentally displaced persons, 2nd version, May 21. Available at: www.cidce.org.

6 X v. Belgium, Application No 984/61, ECommHR (1961) para. 8; X v. Austria and Yugoslavia, Application No 2143/64, ECommHR (1964) para. 6; X v. the Netherlands, Application No 1983/63, ECommHR (1965) para. 12; X v. Federal Republic of Germany, Application No 3040/67, ECommHR (1967) at 3; X v. Federal Republic of Germany, Application No 3110/67, ECommHR (1968) para. 11; X v. Federal Republic of Germany, Application No 4162/69, ECommHR (1969) para. 6; X v. Federal Republic of Germany, Application No 4314/69, ECommHR (1970) paras 1–2; Kemal Altun v. Federal Republic of Germany, Application No 10308/83, ECommHR (1983) paras 219–220; M.C. v. France, Application No 10078/82, ECommHR (1984) para. 111; Kirkwood v. United Kingdom, Application No 10479/83, ECommHR (1984) para. 183; Soering v. United Kingdom, Application No 14038/88, ECtHR (1989); The Haitian Centre for Human Rights v. United States, Inter-Am Comm HR, No 10675 (1997) paras 167–171; The Institution of Asylum and its Recognition as a Human Right in the Inter-American System of Protection (interpretation and scope of articles 5, 22.7 and 22.8 in relation to article 1(1) of the American Convention on Human Rights), Advisory Opinion OC-25/18, Inter-Am Ct HR (Ser A) No 25 2018, para. 181. The travaux préparatoires of the European and American Conventions show that the issue of ill-treatment of a non-national after removal to another state was not debated among the drafters. ‘Preparatory Work on Article 3 of the European Convention of Human Rights’, Council of Europe, European Commission on Human Rights, DH (56) 5 (1956), and OAS, General Assembly, Conferencia Especializada Interamericana sobre Derechos Humanos, paras 41, 100, 246–250.

7 See especially M.S.S. v. Belgium and Greece, Application No 30696/09, ECHR (2011), paras 367–368; Warda Osman Jasin v. Denmark, HRC, 114th Sess, UN Doc CCPR/C/114/D/2360/2014 (2015), paras 1, 8.9–8.10.

8 Golder v. United Kingdom, Application No 4451/70, ECHR (1975) 34–36; Young, James and Webster v. United Kingdom, Application No 7601/76, ECHR (1981), paras 51–52.

9 That is the case of situations in which non-derogable rights have their essence completely denied or nullified in the receiving country so that the threshold of ‘flagrant violation’ takes into account a level of severity comparable to that resulting from violations of the prohibition of cruel and degrading treatment, which is within states’ powers to verify. The reasoning is not that some rights cannot trigger an obligation of non-refoulement but instead that the harm arising from their potential breach would hardly, if ever, reach the required level of severity. That was the case of the guarantees of the rights to fair trial or to liberty and security: Othman (Abu Qatada) v. United Kingdom, Application No 8139/09, ECHR (2012), paras 198–205, 233, 281–287; Al Nashiri v. Romania, Application No 33234/12, ECHR (2018), paras 596, 689–692; Nars & Ghali v. Italy, Application No 44883/09, ECHR (2016), paras 244, 299–303; El-Masri v. Former Yugoslav Republic of Macedonia, Application No 39630/09, ECHR (2012), paras 239–241; the right to private and family life: Al Nashiri v. Romania, Application No 33234/12, ECHR (2018), paras 698–699; El-Masri v. Former Yugoslav Republic of Macedonia, Application No 39630/09, ECHR (2012), paras 249–250 and the freedom of thought, conscience, and religion: Z and Tv. United Kingdom, Application No 27034/05, ECHR (2006), paras 7–8.

10 UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No 31, 80th Sess, UN Doc CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.13 (2004) 1, para. 12; UN Committee on the rights of the child, General Comment No 6, 39th Sess, UN Doc CRC/GC/2005/6 (2005) 1, para. 27; Z.H. and A.H. v. Denmark, 82nd Sess, UN Doc CRC/C/82/D/32/2017 (2019) 1, paras 8.7–8.8, where, although the Committee found the claims inadmissible due to lack of substantiation, it did not reject the possibility that a risk of irreparable harm could arise in relation to the right to health, to an adequate standard of living and to education.

11 Advisory Opinion OC-21/14, ‘Rights and Guarantees of Children in the Context of Migration and/or in Need of International Protection’, OC-21/14, Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACrtHR), 19 August 2014, para. 231.

12 UN Committee on the elimination of any discrimination against women (CEDAW), General recommendation No 32 on the gender-related dimensions of refugee status, asylum, nationality, and statelessness of women, CEDAW, UN Doc. CEDAW/C/GC/32 (2014) 1, para. 23.

13 UN Human Rights Committee, Ioane Teitiota v. New Zealand, CCPR/C/127/D/2728/2016, 23 September 2020.

14 UN Human Rights Committee, Portillo Cáceres etal. v. Paraguay, CCPR/C/126/D/2751/2016, 20 September 2019.

15 UN Human Rights Committee, Ioane Teitiota v. New Zealand (n 13), paras. 9.4, 9.11. Committee member Vasilka Sancin’s (dissenting) Individual Opinion even eventually requested to evidence that such a threat does not exist. See also Citroni, Reference Citroni2020, at 3, critically highlighting how the burden of proof entirely beard on the applicant.

16 Footnote Ibid ., para. 9.4 and already in Portillo Cáceres etal. v. Paraguay (n 14), para. 7.3.

17 UN Human Rights Committee, Ioane Teitiota v New Zealand, para. 9.5. See also UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No 36 (CCPR/C/GC/36), para. 62; UN Human Rights Committee, Portillo Cáceres etal. v. Paraguay (n 14), para. 7.4; Inter-American Court of Human Rights, Advisory Opinion OC-23/17 of 15 November 2017 on the environment and human rights, series A, No. 23, para. 47; Kawas Fernández v. Honduras, judgment of 3 April 2009, series C, No. 196, para. 148. See also African Commission on Human and People’s Rights, General Comment No 3 on the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights: The Right to Life (article 4), para. 3 (states’ responsibilities to protect life ‘extend to preventive steps to preserve and protect the natural environment, and humanitarian responses to natural disasters, famines, outbreaks of infectious diseases, or other emergencies’).

18 UN Human Rights Committee, General Comment No 36, Article 6 Right to Life adopted on 30 October 2018, UN Doc CCPR/C/GC/36 of 3 September 2019, paras 26, 62.

19 UN Human Rights Committee, Ioane Teitiota v. New Zealand (n 13), para. 9.11.

20 The Committee observed in paras 9.9 and 9.19 the finding of the domestic authorities that it was not impossible to grow crops, as well as. that there was no evidence that the author would lack access to potable water in the Republic of Kiribati while the author has not provided sufficient information indicating that the supply of fresh water is inaccessible, insufficient or unsafe so as to produce a reasonably foreseeable threat of a health risk that would impair his right to enjoy a life with dignity or cause his unnatural or premature death. It equally observed that the author refers to sporadic incidents of violence between land claimants that have led to an unspecified number of casualties, and he has not demonstrated clear arbitrariness or error in the domestic authorities’ assessment as to whether he faced a real, personal and reasonably foreseeable risk of a threat to his right to life as a result of violent acts resulting from overcrowding or private land disputes in Kiribati.

21 UN Committee on the Rights of the Child, General Comment No. 6 (2005): Treatment of unaccompanied and separated children outside their country of origin. UN Doc. CRC/GC/2005 e/6.

22 UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (CRC), General comment No. 7 (2005): Implementing Child Rights in Early Childhood, 20 September 2006, CRC/C/GC/7/Rev.1, para. 10.

23 Discussion of the GC No. 36 (Cont’d), HRC, 3323rd meeting, 118th Session (n 45) Special Rapporteur Mr Yuval Shany, 1.23.41 min.

24 UN Human Rights Committee, Billy etal v. Australia, Communication No. 3624/2019, 22 September 2022.

25 The protection of Art. 2 ECHR also regards risks that may only materialise in the longer term according to the Dutch Supreme Court, The State of The Netherlands (Ministry of Economic Affairs and Climate Policy) and Stichting Urgenda, para 5.2.2; Öneryldz v. Turkey, Application No 48939/99, ECHR (2004) affirming that where an environmental problem creates risks to life and where the state has known of those risks over a period of years, yet has failed to take action to address them, resulting in eventual loss of life and other serious human rights impacts, the responsibility of the State is engaged. As to Art. 2 ECHR, in particular, it was held that ‘… the Turkish authorities at several levels knew or ought to have known that there was a real and immediate risk to a number of persons living near the Ümraniye municipal rubbish tip. They consequently had a positive obligation under Art. 2 of the Convention to take such preventive operational measures as were necessary and sufficient to protect those individuals …’ (para. 101).

26 UN Human Rights Committee, Billy etal (n 24), para 8.14.

27 Directive 2011/95/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 13 December 2011 on standards for the qualification of third-country nationals or stateless persons as beneficiaries of international protection, for a uniform status for refugees or for persons eligible for subsidiary protection, and for the content of the protection granted (recast), [2011] OJ L337/9.

28 Case C-465/07 (CJEU), Elgafaji, 17 February 2009, ECLI:EU:C:2009:94.

29 Sufi and Elmi v. the United Kingdom, Application Nos. 8319/07 and 11449/07 ECHR (2011) para. 218.

30 Case C-542/13 (CJEU) M’Bodj, 18 December 2014, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2452.

31 Cases C-540/17 and C-541/17 (CJEU), Bundesrepublik Deutschland v Adel Hamed and Amar Omar, 13 November 2019, EU:C:2019:964, para 36.

33 See Turco-Napolitano Law (L. n. 40/1998).

34 The National Commission for the Right of Asylum had then collected the practice that had emerged in administrative and judicial proceedings in Circular No. 3716 of 30 July 2015, specifying that humanitarian protection was to be granted to the applicant in the following cases: 1) exposure to torture or inhuman or degrading treatment in the event of repatriation; 2) serious psycho-physical conditions or serious pathologies that cannot be adequately treated in the country of origin; 3) temporary impossibility of repatriation due to the insecurity of the country or area of origin, not attributable to the provisions of Art. 3) temporary impossibility of repatriation due to the insecurity of the country or area of origin, not ascribable to the provisions of Art. 14, letter c) of the legislative decree no. 251/2007; 4) serious natural disasters or other serious local factors hindering a return in dignity and safety; 5) family situation of the asylum seeker, which must be assessed in accordance with the provisions of Art. 8 ECHR, concerning the right to respect for private and family life.

35 See for instance, Court of Cassation, ICivil Section, Judgement of 23 February 2018, n 4455, 8 and the Tribunal of L’Aquila, Order of 16 February 2018, 4, according to whom vulnerability needed to be interpreted broadly to encompassing also any exposure to famine, natural or environmental disasters and land grabbing, as well as the general environmental and climatic conditions of the country of origin, if these are such as to jeopardise the core of basic human rights of the individual.

36 Territorial Commission for the Recognition of International Protection of Rome, Section II, Decision of 21 December 2015.

37 Tribunal of Cagliari, Order of 31 March 2019, n 4043.

38 Tribunal of Milan, Order of 31 March 2016, n 64207.

39 Tribunal of Naples, Order of 5 June 2017, n 7523.

40 This has not been set back following the ‘Salvini Law’ converted Decree-Law no. 113 of 4 October 2018, followed by Decree-Law no. 53/2019, into Law no. 77/2019), to art. 5 c. 6 D. Lgs. 286/98 and to the amendments made by Law 286/2018 to art. 5 c. 6 D. Lgs. 286/98. Lgs. 286/98 that made disappear humanitarian protection which has been replaced by new forms of residence permit for specific hypotheses, among whose natural disaster; and a temporary form of protection (six months) against expulsion for those foreign nationals already present in Italy in a situation of irregularity, who, as a result of contingent and exceptional calamity, find themselves unable to return to their country of origin in conditions of safety. Only with Decree-Law No. 130/2020, adopted and converted into Law No. 173/2020, humanitarian protection was finally reinserted with some improvements as to the issue of residence permits for natural disasters. It is a two-year permit (and no longer annual) possibly convertible into a residence permit for employment reasons; making it forbidden (art. 1, para. 1) to reject, expel or extradite ‘a person to a State if there are reasonable grounds to believe that he would risk being subjected to torture or inhuman or degrading treatment’ as well any removal ‘if there are reasonable grounds to believe that removal from the national territory would result in violation of the right to respect for one’s private and family life’.

41 Court of Cassation, third civil section, no. 25143/20 of 10 November 2020; Court of Cassation, ICivil Section, Order of 4 February 2020, n 2563.

42 Court of Cassation first section, judgement no. 4455/2018 of 23 February 2018; Court of Cassation 10686 of 2012; and Court of Cassation 16362 of 2016; Court of Cassation, ICivil Section, Order of 4 February 2020, n 2563, para. 6.

43 Court of Cassation, II Civil Section, Order of 24 February 2021, n 5022.

44 Legislative Decr. 27 July 1998 n. 286 as modified by d. l. 21 October 2020 n. 130.

45 Court of Cassation, II Civil Section, Order of 24 February 2021, n 5022.

46 Footnote Ibid ., at 5.

47 According to the Court, instead, the rejection of the asylum application by the lower instances was wrongfully based on the illegitimate failure to assess ‘the situation of environmental disaster existing in the Niger Delta’, in violation of Art. 5 of Legislative Decree no. 286/1998. Recalling the observations made by the Human Rights Committee in the Teitiota case, the Court noted that ‘States have an obligation to ensure and guarantee the right to life of persons’, also with regard to ‘reasonably foreseeable threats’ that lead to a substantial deterioration of living conditions, including environmental degradation, climate change and sustainable development.

48 Footnote Ibid ., at 6.

49 Order by the Court of Genoa of 27 July 2022.

50 VGH Baden-Württemberg, Dec. No A11 S2042/20, 17 December 2020.

51 See the German Supreme Court on the interpretation of humanitarian conditions in the country of origin, BVerfG 2. Senat 1. Kammer, 9 February 2021, ECLI:DE:BVerfG:2021:qk20210209.2bvq000821.

52 CAA de Bordeaux, decision n. 20BX02193, 20BX02195, 18 December 2020. The case concerned a forty-year-old waiter-cook, who had obtained a temporary residence permit on medical grounds in 2015. In 2019, his renewal was rejected by the Haute-Garonne prefecture, which considered that he could access his treatment in Bangladesh. The administrative court of Toulouse annulled the decision in June 2020. The prefecture decided to appeal. The Bordeaux Court of Appeal annulled, on the 18 December 2020, the obligation to leave French territory addressed to the applicant, on the grounds that he would be confronted in his country of origin – ranked 179th in the world for its air quality – with an aggravation of his respiratory pathology due to atmospheric pollution.

53 Footnote Ibid ., at 4.

54 See i.e. D. v. United Kingdom, Application No 30240/96, ECHR (1997); N. v. United Kingdom, Application No 26565/05, ECHR (2008); Yoh-Ekale Mwanje v. Belgium, Application No 10486/10, ECHR (2011); S.J. v. Belgium, Application No 41738/10 ECHR (2016); Tatar v. Switzerland, Application No 65692/12, ECHR (2014).

55 Chowdury and Others v. Greece, Application No 21884/15, ECHR (2017).

56 Paposhvili v. Belgium, Application No 41738/10, ECHR (2016), para. 188.

57 The Council of State has confirmed that the hypothesis is limited to a protection provided for in national law to the sole question of health. See CE, 2ème et 7ème chambres réunies, 30 décembre 2021, Ministre de l’intérieur c. M. A, n° 449917.

58 R v Secretary of State Department ex parte Adam [2005] UKHL 66. See also UNHCR, ‘Guidelines on International Protection’, 23 July 2003, para. 29.

References

Adger, WN (2006) Vulnerability. Global Environmental Change 16(3), 268281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, A, Foster, M, Lambert, H, and McAdam, J (2019) Imminence in refugee and human rights law: a misplaced notion for international protection. International and Comparative Law Quarterly 68(1), 111140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atapattu, S (2010) Human Rights Approaches to Climate Change: Challenges and Opportunities. London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Ltd.Google Scholar
Baumgärtel, M (2020) Facing the Challenge of Migratory Vulnerability in the European Court of Human Rights. Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights 38, 1229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumgärtel Mand Ganty S (2024) On the Basis of Migratory Vulnerability: Activating Article 14 of the European Convention on Human Rights in the Context of Migration. International Journal of Law in Context. This Special Issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckett, A (2006) Citizenship and Vulnerability: Disability and Issues of Social and Political Engagement. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Behlert, B (2020) ASignificant Opening. On the HRC’s Groundbreaking First Ruling in the Case of a ‘Climate refugee’. Voelkerrechtsblog, 30 January 2020. Available at: https://voelkerrechtsblog.org/de/a-significant-opening/.Google Scholar
Behrmane, S and Kent, A (2020) The Teitiota Case and the Limitations of the Human Rights Framework, Questions of International Law 75, 2539.Google Scholar
Bennet, J (2010) Vibrant Matter: APolitical Ecology of Thing. Durham/London: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Biermann, F and Boas, I (2007) Preparing for a Warmer World: Towards a Global Governance System to Protect Climate Refugees. Global Governance Working Paper No 33, November.Google Scholar
Biermann, F and Boas, I (2010) Preparing for a Warmer World: Towards a Global Governance System to Protect Climate Refugees. Global Environmental Politics 10(1), 6088.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bronfenbrenner, U (1979) The Ecology of Human Development. Harvard: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Citroni, G (2020) Human Rights Committee’s decision on the case Ioane Teitiota v New Zealand: Landmark or will-o’-the-wisp for climate refugees? Questions of International Law 75, 15.Google Scholar
European Commission (2022) Communication from the commission to the european parliament, the council, the european economic and social committee and the committee of the regions on the Report on Migration and Asylum. COM (2022) 740 final.Google Scholar
Cooper, J (1998) Environmental Refugees: Meeting the Requirements of the Refugee Definition. NYU Environmental Law Journal 6(2), 480529.Google Scholar
Costello, C and Foster, M (2016) Non-refoulement as Custom and Jus Cogens? Putting the Prohibition to the Test. Netherlands Yearbook of International Law 46, 273327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costello, C (2015) ‘Defining Protection: Refugeehood, Non-Refoulement, and Human Rights’, The Human Rights of Migrants and Refugees in European Law (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullen, M (2020) The Un Human Rights Committee’s Recent Decision on Climate Displacement. Available at: https://www.asyluminsight.com.Google Scholar
Da Lomba, S (2014) Vulnerability, irregular migrants’ health-related rights and the ECtHR. European Journal of Health Law 21(4), 339364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Docherty, B and Giannini, T (2009) Confronting a rising tide: a proposal for a convention on climate change refugees. Harvard Environmental Law Review 33, 349403.Google Scholar
Durieux, JF (2010) The Elusive War Refugee: Violence and Discrimination in the Construct of Refugees as a Legal Category, Refugee Studies Centre Lecture, University of Oxford, 10 November 2010.Google Scholar
El-Hinnawi, E (1985) Environmental Refugees. Nairobi: UN Environment Programme (UNEP).Google Scholar
Ellis, J (2019) Crisis, Resilience, and the Time of Law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 32(2), 305320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
EU Commission (2016) Lives in dignity: From aid-dependence to self-reliance, COM(2016) 234 final, 26.4.2016.Google Scholar
EU Commission (2021), Forging a climate-resilient Europe - the new EU Strategy on Adaptation to Climate Change, COM(2021) 82 final, 24.2.2021.Google Scholar
EU Parliament (2011), Climate refugees. Legal and policy responses to environmentally induced migration, PE 462.422.Google Scholar
Fineman, M (2008) The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition. Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 20, 123.Google Scholar
Fineman, M and Grear, A (eds) (2013) Vulnerability: Reflections on a New Ethical Foundation for Law and Politics. Farnham: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Fineman, MA (2015) Equality and Difference - The Restrained State. Emory Legal Studies Research Paper No. 15-348.Google Scholar
Flegar, V (2016) Vulnerability and the Principle of Non-refoulement in the European Court of Human Rights: Towards an Increased Scope of Protection for Persons Fleeing from Extreme Poverty? Contemporary Readings in Law and Social Justice 8(2),148169.Google Scholar
Foster, M (2009) International Refugee Law and Socio-Economic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gonin, P and Lassailly-Jacob, V (2002) Les réfugiés de l’environnement. Revue Européenne de Migrations Internationales 18(2), 139160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R (1985) Protecting the Vulnerable: ARe-analysis of our Social Responsibilities. London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Goodwin-Gill, G and McAdam, J (2007) The Refugee in International law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grant, E, Kotze, LJ and Morrow, KL (2013) Human Rights and the Environment: In Search of a New Relationship. Oñati Socio-Legal Series 3(5), 953965.Google Scholar
Grear, A (2010) Redirecting Human Rights: Facing the Challenge of Corporate Legal Humanity. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grear, A (2011) ‘Sexing the Matrix’: Embodiment, Disembodiment and the Law. Towards the Re-Gendering of Legal Rationality? In Jones, J, Grear, A, Fenton, RA and Stevenson, K (eds), Gender, Sexualities and Law. Oxford/New York: Routledge, pp. 3952.Google Scholar
Grundler, M (2024) ‘Route Causes’ and Consequences of Irregular (Re-)Migration: Vulnerability as an Indicator of Future Risk in Refugee Law. International Journal of Law in Context. This Special Issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, AP (2014) Vulnerability and Power in the Age of the Anthropocene. Washington and Lee Journal of Energy, Climate, and the Environment 9, 98161.Google Scholar
Hathaway, JC (1991) The Law of Refugee Status. Toronto/Vancouver: Butterworths Canada Ltd.Google Scholar
Holling, CS (1973) Resilience and Stability of Ecological Systems. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 4, 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hulme, M (2008) Commentary: Climate Refugees: Cause for a New Agreement? Environment: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development 50(6), 5054.Google Scholar
Humby, TC (2014) Law and Resilience: Mapping the Literature. Seattle Journal of Environmental Law 85, 8990.Google Scholar
Imbert, L (2020) Premiers éclaircissements sur la protection internationale des «migrants climatiques». La Revue des droits de l’homme. Available at: https://journals.openedition.org/revdh/9262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
International Law Association (ILA) (2022), International Law and Sea level rise. Report. Resolution 5/2018. Committee On International Law And Sea Level Rise, 19-24 August 2018. Available at: file:///D:/Downloads/Conference%20Resolution%20Sydney%202018%20English.pdf.36https://legal.un.org/ilc/guide/8_9.shtml.Google Scholar
Ippolito, F (2020) Struggling with climate change: environmental rights as children’s rights and the potential of an ‘hybrid’ nature of the UN Convention of the Rights of the Child. German Yearbook of International Law 63, 511539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ippolito, F (2022) The Best Interests of the Child: Another string to environmental and climate protection’ bow? Questions of International Law, 7–27.Google Scholar
Ippolito, F (2023) Children’s Environmental Rights under International and EU Law. The Changing Face of Fundamental Rights in Pursuit of Ecocentrism. The Hague: TMC Asser Press/Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jastram, K (2010) Economic harm as a basis for refugee status and the application of human rights law to the interpretation of economic persecution. In Simeon, JC (ed), Critical Issues in International Refugee Law: Strategies toward interpretative harmony. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kälin, W (2010) Conceptualising Climate-Induced Displacement. In McAdam, J (ed), Climate Change and Displacement: Multidisciplinary Perspectives. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Keane, D (2004) The Environmental Causes and Consequences of Migration: ASearch for the Meaning of “Environmental Refugees”. Georgetown International Environmental Law Review, 209.Google Scholar
Keck, M and Sakdapolrak, P (2013) What Is Social Resilience? Lessons Learned and Ways Forward. Erdkunde 67, 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kittay, E (1999) Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependency. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kozoll, C (2004) Poisoning the Well: Persecution, the Environment, and Refugee Status. Colorado Journal of International Environmental Law and Policy 15(2), 271307.Google Scholar
Le Moli, G (2020) The Human Rights Committee, Environmental Protection and the Right to Life. International and Comparative Law Quarterly 69, 735752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liguori A (2022) Cambiamento climatico e diritti umani dinanzi al Comitato dei diritti del fanciullo. La Comunità Internazionale LXXVII, 117133.Google Scholar
Little, I (2018) Out with the Old Approach: ACall to Take Socio- Economic Rights Seriously in Refugee Status Determination. New Zealand Yearbook of International Law 16, 145173.Google Scholar
Lotz, M (2016) Vulnerability and Resilience: ACritical Nexus. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37, 4559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luna, F (2009) Elucidating the Concept of Vulnerability: Layers not Labels. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2, 121139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, C Rogers Wand Dodds S (2014) Introduction: What is Vulnerability and Why Does It Matter for Moral Theory? In Mackenzie C, RogersW and Dodds S(eds), Vulnerability: New Essays in Ethics and Feminist Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–32.Google Scholar
Maneggia, A (2022) Quale protezione per i migranti climatici? Considerazioni sul caso Teitiota . Liber Amicorum Sergio Marchisio. Il diritto della comunità internazionale tra caratteristiche strutturali e tendenze innovative. Naples: Editoriale Scientifica, pp. 15071520.Google Scholar
Marchegiani, M (2022) The implications of sea-level rise for international law. Questions of International Law, 14.Google Scholar
McAdam, J (2011) Climate Change Displacement and International Law: Complementary Protection Standards. UNHCR Legal and Protection Policy Research Series. Available at: https://www.unhcr.org/4dff16e99.pdf.Google Scholar
McAdam, J (2011) Swimming Against The Tide: Why AClimate Change Displacement Treaty Is Not The Answer. International Journal of Refugee Law 23(1), 227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAdam, J (2020) Climate Refugees Cannot Be Forced Back Home. The Sydney Morning Herald, 20 January. Available at: https://www.smh.com.au/environment/climate-change/climate-refugees-cannot-be-forced-back-home-20200119-p53sp4.html.Google Scholar
McAdam, J (2020) Protecting People Displaced by the Impacts of Climate Change: The UN Human Rights Committee and the Principle of Non-refoulement. American Journal of International Law 114(4), 708725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAdam, J (2009) Environmental Migration Governance. UNSW Law Research Paper No. 2009-1, Jane McAdam, ‘Environmental Migration’ in Alexander Betts (ed) Global Migration Governance (Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLeman, RA and Smit, B (2006) Migration as an adaptation to climate change. Climate Change 76, 3153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menghistu, F (1985) The Satisfaction of Survival Requirements. In Ramcharan, BG (ed), The Right to Life in International Law. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Methmann, C and Oels, A (2015) From ‘fearing’ to ‘empowering’ climate refugees: Governing climate-induced migration in the name of resilience. Security Dialogue 46(1), 5168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreno-Lax, V (2021) Intersectionality, Forced Migration and the Jus-generation of the Right to Flee: Theorising the Composite Entitlement to Leave to Escape Irreversible Harm, In Çali B, Bianku L and Motoc I (eds), Migration and the European Convention on Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4384.Google Scholar
Moreno-Lax, V and Garlick, M (2015) The Qualification Directive. In Peers, S, Moreno-Lax, V, Garlick, M and Guild, E (eds), EU Immigration and Asylum Law, 2nd ed., Vol. 3. Leiden/Boston: Brill, pp. 65210.Google Scholar
Moreno-Lax, V and Vavoula, N (2024) Vulnerability’s Legal Life: An Ambivalent Force of Migration Governance. International Journal of Law in Context. This Special Issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myers, N and Kent, J (1995) Environmental Exodus: An Emergent Crisis in the Global Arena. Washington DC: Climate Institute.Google Scholar
Neal, M (2012) ‘Not Gods but Animals’: Human Dignity and Vulnerable Subjecthood. Liverpool Law Review 33, 177200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pachauri etal. (eds) (2014) Intergovernmental panel on climate change, climate change 2014 synthesis report: summary for policymakers. Available at: https://www.ipcc.ch/site/assets/uploads/2018/02/AR5_SYR_FINAL_SPM.pdf.Google Scholar
Passarini, F (2022) Oltre il caso Teitiota: la tutela dei migranti ambientali nelle recenti pronunce della cassazione italiana, ADIM Blog, Analisi & Opinioni 5, 45.Google Scholar
Perch-Nielsen SBättig Mand Imboden D (2008) Exploring the link between climate change and migration. Climate Change 91, 375393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peroni, L and Timmer, A (2013) Vulnerable Groups: The Promise of an Emerging Concept in European Human Rights Convention Law. International Journal of Constitutional Law 11, 10561085.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perrini, F (2021) Il riconoscimento della protezione umanitaria in caso di disastri ambientali nel recente orientamento della Corte di Cassazione. Ordine internazionale e diritti umani 2, 349362.Google Scholar
Pobjoy, JM (2017) The Child in International Refugee Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsay, P (2008) The Theory of Vulnerable Autonomy and the Legitimacy of the Civil Preventative Order. LSE Working Paper 1. LSE: London.Google Scholar
Reeh, G (2020) Climate Change in the Human Rights Committee. EJIL:Talk!, 18 February 2020. Available at: https://www.ejiltalk.org/climate-change-in-the-human-rights-committee/.Google Scholar
Rive, V (2020) Is an Enhanced Non-refoulement Regime under the ICCPR the Answer to Climate Change-related Human Mobility Challenges in the Pacific? Reflections on Teitiota v New Zealand in the Human Rights Committee, Questions of International Law 75, 724.Google Scholar
Ruhl, JB (2011) General Design Principles for Resilience and Adaptive Capacity in Legal Systems – With Applications to Climate Change Adaptation. North Carolina Law Review 89, 13731404.Google Scholar
Ruhl, JB et al. (2021) Resilience of Legal Systems. In Ungar, M (ed), Multisystemic Resilience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schefer, KN and Cottier, T (2015) Responsibility to Protect (R2P) and the Emerging Principle of Common Concern. In Hilpold P(ed), The Responsibility to Protect (R2P). ANew Paradigm of International Law?. Brill, pp. 123142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schloss, C (2021) Climate migrants – How German courts take the environment into account when considering non- refoulement. Völkerrechtsblog, 3 March 2021. Available at: https://voelkerrechtsblog.org/climate-migrants/.Google Scholar
Schmeidl, S (2001) Conflict and Forced Migration: AQuantitative Review, 1964–1995. In Zolberg, AR and Benda, P (eds), Global Migrants, Global Refugees: Problems and Solutions. New York/Oxford: Berghahn.Google Scholar
Scissa, C (2021) Migrazioni ambientali tra immobilismo normativo e dinamismo giurisprudenziale: Un’analisi di tre recenti pronunce. Quaderni Costituzionali 2, 78.Google Scholar
Scott, M (2019) Migration/Refugee Law (2018). Yearbook of International Disaster Law 1, 462472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shuetze, L (2020) AGroundbreaking Ruling on Climate Refugees Puts the World on Notice. The Spinoff. Available at: https://thespinoff.co.nz/society/23-01-2020/a-groundbreaking-ruling-on-climate-refugees-puts-the-world-on-notice.Google Scholar
Sommario, E (2021), When climate change and human rights meet: Abrief comment on the UN Human Rights Committee’s Teitiota decision. Questions of International Law 77, 5165.Google Scholar
Tacoli, C (2009) Crisis or adaptation? Migration and climate change in a context of high mobility. Environment and Urbanisation 21(2), 513525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Traore Chazalnoele, M and Ionesco, D (2018) Advancing the global governance of climate migration through the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change and the Global Compact on Migration. In Behrman, S and Kent, A (eds), ‘Climate Refugees’. Beyond the Legal Impasse? Routledge: London.Google Scholar
Tsourdi, E (2014) What Protection for Persons Fleeing Indiscriminate Violence? The Impact of the European Courts on the EU Subsidiary Protection Regime. In Cantor, D and Durieux, J-F (eds), Refuge from Inhumanity? War Refugees and International Humanitarian Law. Leiden: Brill/Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Turner, B (2006) Vulnerability and Human Rights. Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park.Google Scholar
UN High Commissioner for Human Rights (2018) Addressing human rights protection gaps in the context of migration and displacement of persons across international borders resulting from the adverse effects of climate change and supporting the adaptation and mitigation plans of developing countries to bridge the protection gaps, UN Doc. A/HRC/38/21, 23 April 2018.Google Scholar