1 Introduction
Recent literature (Turner, Reference Turner2006; Fineman, Reference Fineman2008; Fineman and Grear, Reference Fineman and Grear2013; Goodin, Reference Goodin1985; Kittay, Reference Kittay1999; Beckett, Reference Beckett2006), in the realms of philosophy, legal theory and ethics, particularly feminist legal theory (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014; Fineman, Reference Fineman2015; Grear, Reference Grear2010), approaches vulnerability as a means to revolutionise the architecture of law, which is constructed around the ideal of a rational subject excised from both embodiment and socio-cultural context (Grear, Reference Grear, Jones, Grear, Fenton and Stevenson2011). The ‘vulnerable subject’ is advanced instead as a more realistic alternative (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008), stressing vulnerability and the ontological experience of all human beings as part of the personal, economic, social, and cultural circumstances in which individuals find themselves at different points in their lives, and as a fundamental feature of humanity (Turner, Reference Turner2006).
Such a shared ‘ontological insecurity’, characterised as a constant exposure to potential harm (whether intentional or accidental), may arise from: (i) ‘our corporeality, our neediness, our dependence on others, and our affective and social natures’ (inherent vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014); (ii) situational and context-specific conditions including personal, social, economic and environmental conditions, so being a product of genetic, social and environmental factors actually present or latent (situational vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers, and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014; Fineman, Reference Fineman2008; Peroni and Timmer, Reference Peroni and Timmer2013; Neal, Reference Neal2012); (iii) the exacerbation or compounding of existing types of vulnerability, including ‘morally dysfunctional interpersonal and social relationships characterised by disrespect, prejudice or abuse, or by socio-political situations characterised by oppression, domination, repression, injustice, persecution or political violence’ (pathogenic vulnerability) (Mackenzie, Rogers and Dodds, Reference Mackenzie2014); or (iv) contingencies that follow a choice (discretionary vulnerability) (Lotz, Reference Lotz2016). Such different and complex kinds of vulnerability may be superposed and experienced simultaneously (compounded vulnerability) (Luna, Reference Luna2009). As applied to the context migration, migrant vulnerability (Bronfenbrenner, Reference Bronfenbrenner1979) – or ‘migratory vulnerability’ (Baumgärtel, Reference Baumgärtel2020; Baumgärtel and Ganty, in this issue) – is normally associated with multiple factors. Some relate to individuals and their family circumstances. In other cases, vulnerability is associated with community factors, including availability of quality educational opportunities, health care and social services; equal access to resources; livelihood and income-generating opportunities; the natural environment and social norms and behaviours. Finally, structural factors of migrant vulnerability are the political, economic, social, and environmental conditions and institutions at national, regional and international levels. Footnote 1 The law also plays a key role (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue).
Most recently, however, building on Fineman’ conceptualisation, a theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’ has also been elaborated (Harris, Reference Harris2014) to make evident the relationship and interactions between the human being/body and the environment/non-human world. Through the concept of ‘ecological vulnerability’ it is recognised that humans are vulnerable not only because they age, become ill and die, ‘but because their survival depends on complex macro- and micro-ecologies – all of which are, in turn, vulnerable to harm’. As Harris (Reference Harris2014) underlines, adopting the language of ‘ecological vulnerability’ implies the necessity – well-explained by Bennet – of having to ‘admit that humans have crawled or secreted themselves into every corner of the environment; admit that the environment is actually inside human bodies and minds, and then proceed politically, technologically, scientifically, in everyday life, with careful forbearance’ (Bennet, Reference Bennet2010). According to Harris, ‘ecological vulnerability’ recognises that human lives are part of complex ecosystems that operate on various levels of scale, from the local to the global. She acknowledges that ‘in the age of the Anthropocene, when human activity is rapidly causing large-scale, not fully predictable, and potentially irreversible changes to our inner and outer environments’, the fully ‘responsive State’ (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008) should recognise that soil degradation, water scarcity, warming oceans, and depleted fishing stocks structure our options and create opportunities just as market and family relations do. In the age of the Anthropocene, it can no longer be argued that these environmental processes and events are outside the circle of justice. ‘Human behaviour’ and ‘the natural world’ are now locked in an ever-tightening feedback loop. Climate change represents the most dramatic example of this indivisibility of humans and ‘the environment’ (Pachauri etal., 2014; Grant, Kotze and Morrow, Reference Grant, Kotze and Morrow2013) being evident in the close interrelationship between greenhouse gas emissions, large-scale ecosystem and trans-human system disruptions, and human life and health. Thus, the applicability of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ notion to environmentally induced migration can serve to reframe the reach of law, including the scope of non-refoulement, that is, to assess the situation in the country of destination in the event of forcible expulsion of ‘climate refugees’. Accordingly, what this article proposes is that the non-refoulement principle – the main protection of those in need of international protection – should be re-interpreted in the sense that the risk of exposure to inhuman treatment to be assessed in the country of destination should encompass not only the individual situation (regarding threats of persecution or ill treatment) but also the overall conditions in the country, considering especially the level of an adequate standard of living in line with basic human rights. This – the recognition in law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) of ‘ecological vulnerability’ as a relevant factor in the non-refoulement assessment – could generate a (virtuous) expansion of traditional asylum norms and the flexibilization of access to international protection for that particular category of migrants (European Commission, 2022) in line with the evolving standards of international law.
2 Law as generator and exacerbator of environmental migrants’ vulnerability and the resilience of human rights
Since the expression ‘climate/or environmental refugees’ was first used in 1985 by El-Hinnawi and subsequently recurred in literature and political/institutional documents (e.g. European Parliament, 2011), it has served to bring to the fore the existence of three cumulative elements that characterise the plight of this category of persons: (i) the departure from the usual location; (ii) the existence of a climatic breach (due to natural or human causes, slow onset or not) that impacts and threatens human life and (iii) serious perturbances to living conditions. Despite the literal tenor of the expression (climate/or environmental refugees), however, the international refugee law framework, enshrined in the 1951 Convention Relative to the Status of Refugees Footnote 2 and its 1967 Protocol, Footnote 3 does not represent the normative source of their protection. In fact, the element of persecution that characterises the current definition of a ‘refugee’, based on ‘race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social group or political opinion’ (Goodwin-Gill and McAdam, Reference Goodwin-Gill and McAdam2007), is absent in the case of climate or environmentally induced migrations. Although adverse environmental and climate impacts could characterise any related harm as sufficiently severe (Foster, Reference Foster2009); environmental and climate change consequences are indiscriminate, and thus not tied to individuals’ backgrounds or beliefs (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011). There is nonetheless scope for some exceptions, where exposure to climate impacts or environmental degradation in themselves amount to persecution: if government policies target particular groups reliant on agriculture for survival or use starvation or famine as a political tool (Schmeidl, Reference Schmeidl, Zolberg and Benda2001), or contribute to environmental destruction, Footnote 4 or even desertification (Cooper, Reference Cooper1998; Kozoll, Reference Kozoll2004). This flows from developments in international human rights law that have informed the meaning of persecution and harm within the international refugee law regime (Foster, Reference Foster2009; McAdam, Reference McAdam2009) allowing for persecution to take the form of socio-economic deprivation (Foster, Reference Foster2009).
Moreover, as climate change is a gradual process, it is possible that some individuals will voluntarily leave the affected area before it becomes uninhabitable so that the characterisation of any ensuing harm as akin to persecution becomes too remote. This relates to a third issue, namely that it is extremely difficult to disentangle the specific cause of displacement from other connected factors, due to the incremental impacts of climate change on the broader political and socio-economic context (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011). Arelated matter concerns the problematic notion of climate change as violating human rights per se. Furthermore, while Article 1(A)(2) of the 1951 Convention requires the refugee to be ‘unable or owing to such fear … unwilling to vail himself from the protection of that country’, the country of origin may still be willing to protect its displaced inhabitants; the problem lying instead in its (in)capacity to do so.
But the limits of the notion of ‘environmental/climate refugees’ do not end in its inability to include environmental and climate refugees within the frame of international refugee law. Such a notion is not a shared one at either the international or the European level. In fact, a definition according to which climate-induced migration occurs every time a person cannot stay in their home due to a habitual climatic event is too vague and broad to come within the remit of international refugee law (Myers and Kent, Reference Myers and Kent1995). An agreement instead exists about the crossing of an international border and the vulnerability of such migrants, which bears strict similarities with the vulnerabilities of those who are unable to access safe, affordable and regular migration pathways (UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, 2018). The need for a coercive element to exist to qualify for international protection (Keane, Reference Keane2004) is not without criticism either. Thus, it can hardly be determined whether a migrant anticipating a rise in sea level or a drought is allowed (under international law) to organise his/her departure and even choose his/her receiving state (Gonin and Lassailly-Jacob, Reference Gonin and Lassailly-Jacob2002). Anyhow, at least the idea that the coercion that makes people leave, at the basis of climate/environmentally induced migration, shall be linked to an irresistible (sudden or gradual) environmental disaster/event that inexorably impacts the living conditions of those concerned should be retained.Footnote 5 The lack of consensus on how to define climate refugees makes it extremely difficult to develop an international instrument to protect them – whether in the form of an ad hoc Convention or an Additional Protocol to the 1951 Refugee Convention (Bierman and Boas, Reference Biermann and Boas2007; Hulme, Reference Hulme2008; Traore Chazalnoel and Ionescoor, Reference Traore Chazalnoele, Ionesco, Behrman and Kent2018) or to the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011), or as a reformulation of Article 1(A) of the 1951 Refugee Convention, to encompass within the refugee definition also those at risk to their personal psycho-physical integrity due to the effects of environmental degradation. This puts environmentally displaced persons outside the law’s protection (in quite a literal sense), with the consequence that the law’s exclusion ends up exacerbating vulnerabilities (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) and manifests itself as ill-suited to address their plight (McAdam, Reference McAdam2011).
Law, nonetheless, offers some respite in the specific regional context represented by the Organisation of African Unity (OAU) Convention (1974) and the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights (1986), which provide an extended refugee definition, encompassing those displaced due to ‘events seriously disturbing public order’ (Atapattu, Reference Atapattu2010) that could be read as accommodating climate disasters. People may therefore be eligible as refugees when displaced by climate change or an environmental disaster and fall under the protection of these regional instruments.
At the international level, the work of the International Law and Sea Level Rise Committee, which operates within the International Law Association (ILA) and of the International Law Commission’s working-group on Sea-level rise (ILA, 2022; Marchegiani, Reference Marchegiani2022; European Commission, 2016), is promising. The same applies to international human rights law, which offers some possibilities to bounce back from the challenges of climate/environmentally induced migration, giving expression to the different capacities of: (i) coping (Keck and Sakdapolrak, Reference Keck and Sakdapolrak2013) or maintaining, (ii) adapting and/or (iii) transforming (Methmann and Oels, Reference Methmann and Oels2015) the environmental vulnerability-exacerbating effects of climate change. The applicability of international human rights law persists in the context of forced migration, in particular, the positive duties attached to the obligation of non-refoulement. Footnote 6 Extreme situations of socioeconomic destitution, particularly in relation to vulnerable individuals, in fact, may amount to inhuman or degrading treatment and hence trigger the application of the principle of non-refoulement under human rights law. Footnote 7 Anon-refoulement effect has been applied also to non-absolute rights, Footnote 8 where there was a risk of a ‘flagrant violation’ Footnote 9 of attendant guarantees. Arisk of ‘irreparable harm’ in the receiving state, Footnote 10 a ‘reasonable risk of [a] violation of their fundamental rights’, Footnote 11 or a risk for the individual of suffering ‘serious forms of discrimination’ or gender-based violence have been considered sufficient to halt deportations. Footnote 12 Against this background, it is worth exploring whether human rights law has the potential of offering additional protection (through the concept of ‘ecological vulnerability’) in order to extend the protective application of the principle of non-refoulement to displaced persons who have crossed an international border due to environmental degradation or climate change. Adding to the reflections in this Special Issue, the next section thus turns to examine the potential of ‘ecological vulnerability’, when recognised in and through law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue) to expand the non-refoulement obligation to cover and offer protection to environmental migrants.
3 The potential of vulnerability to expand the non-refoulement obligation to environmental migrants
Non-refoulement operates on the basis of the ‘returnability test’, thus on the ‘permissibility, feasibility (factual possibility) and reasonableness of return’ (Kälin, Reference Kälin and McAdam2010) in the light of the individual situation of the applicant in the event of expulsion. Therefore, state authorities should provide an adequate and individualised assessment of the risk of a threat to the applicant’s right to life or his/her right to not be subjected to inhuman or degrading treatment in the country of envisaged return. In such an assessment, vulnerability theories have played a role in the reasoning of human rights courts and UN monitoring bodies, expanding the protection by, for instance, lowering the threshold of risk (Ippolito, Reference Ippolito2020). On this basis, what this section will determine, when non-returnability is analysed in relation to climate induced displacement, is whether, through the protection par ricochet of the right to life, the application of vulnerability, and especially of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory on the dependence of mankind on the environment and various ecosystems as recalled in the previous section, should entail an expansion of the positive obligations attached to the principle of non-refoulement vis-a-vis environmentally displaced migrants.
The decision by the UN Human Rights Committee in the case of Ioane Teitiota v. New Zealand Footnote 13 – assessed positively by some (Behlert, Reference Behlert2020; McAdam, Reference McAdam2020; Schuetze, Reference Shuetze2020) or more critically by others (Behrmane and Kent, Reference Behrmane and Kent2020; Cullen Reference Cullen2020; Imbert, Reference Imbert2020; Le Moli, Reference Le Moli2020; Rive, Reference Rive2020; Scott, Reference Scott2019) – illustrates some of such a protective potential of a vulnerability-inspired reading of non-refoulement. The case concerned a family from the Republic of Kiribati, a Pacific Island-nation projected to be completely submerged by water by 2050, who applied in New Zealand for refugee status based on ‘changes to their environment in Kiribati caused by sea-level-rise associated with climate change’ that threatened their lives and wellbeing – having arrived there in 2007 and stayed well after their permits expired in 2010. All the national levels of jurisdiction dismissed the request for refugee status on the grounds that the Kiribati citizens did not ‘objectively face a real risk of being persecuted if returned to Kiribati’ (at 4) and that there was insufficient evidence to show that Mr Teitiota and his family faced a ‘real chance of suffering serious physical harm from violence’, or that he would be unable to find land accommodation to grow food and obtain potable water. Furthermore, there was no evidence that the environmental conditions in Tarawa were ‘so perilous that Teitiota’s life [and that of his family] would be jeopardised’ (ibid.). When the case reached the UN Human Rights Committee, arguing that New Zealand had violated Mr Teitiota’s right to life under Article 6 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), that argument was dismissed.
However, building on the consideration that the protection of the right to life implies positive obligations, including those arising from international environmental law (acknowledged first in the Portillo Càceres case),Footnote 14 the Committee interpreted the normative content of the right in an evolutionary way, comprehensive of the positive duty to protect not only against imminent risks to life but also against ‘reasonably foreseeable threats and life-threatening situations that can result in loss of life’, Footnote 15 even if they do not result in actual (and immediate) loss of life. Footnote 16 The Committee further recalled that environmental degradation and climate change constitute some of the most pressing and serious threats to the ability of present and future generations to effectively enjoy the right to life. Footnote 17 Interpreting the right to life as the right to enjoy a life with dignity, together with the acknowledgment of the existence of a close correlation between the obligations placed on states under international environmental law and the protection of the right to life enshrined in Article 6 ICCPR, Footnote 18 brought the Human Rights Committee to recognise that, without robust national and international efforts, the effects of climate change in receiving states may expose individuals to a violation of their rights under Articles 6 and/or 7 of the Covenant, thereby triggering their non-refoulement obligations. Furthermore, given the risk of an entire country becoming submerged under water and its potentially extreme consequences, the conditions of life in such a country may become incompatible with the right to a life with dignity before the risk materialises. Footnote 19 However, the risk of serious harm to life must be personal and cannot result simply from the general conditions of the receiving country, except in extreme cases. Therefore, Mr. Teitiota, not complaining of a strictly personal risk and with the Committee not taking into account a ‘cumulative assessment’ of all the relevant factors (McAdam, Reference McAdam2020) to assess the risk holistically, would have needed to provide proof of the uninhabitability of Kiribati to avoid expulsion.
The application of the ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory could have helped in refocusing the assessment in the light of the specific vulnerabilities of the applicant in relation also to the overall conditions in the country, in particular considering the level of an adequate standard of living, whose components include access to adequate food, clothing, housing and the continuous improvement of living conditions, as well as the right not to be deprived of livelihood means – all elements that are extremely affected by both environmental degradation and climate change. In particular, the theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’ could have been used to demonstrate that intermediate degrees of exposure to climate-induced harms may trigger non-refoulement protection. The theory would have served to jointly consider extreme conditions, making life unliveable, alongside the unbearable effects of environmental degradation, before the risk is realised (at 9.11) but being nonetheless imminent (at 9.12). Footnote 20
Namely, ‘ecological vulnerability’ may lower the evidence threshold necessary to prove the risk, giving rise to a ‘wider and more tailored net than the generic non-refoulement obligations’ (Pobjoy, Reference Pobjoy2017), as well as a broader and more flexible definition of harm (Sommario, Reference Sommario2021). ‘Ecological vulnerability’ draws from an intersectional evaluation of all the relevant risk factors as they interact together. If generalised, an ecological vulnerability-inspired evaluation would transform the assessment of, for instance, age-related vulnerabilities in a revolutionary way. In this regard, the Committee on the Rights of the Child (CRC Committee) has developed the notion of ‘other irreparable harm’ as ‘also includ[ing] harm to the survival, development, or health (physical or mental) of the child’, Footnote 21 which in the Committee’s jurisprudence requires the right to survival and development as implemented through the combined enforcement of the rights to health, adequate nutrition, an adequate standard of living, and a healthy and safe environment. Footnote 22 This, interpreted in light of the best interests of the child, is gaining momentum and becoming an effective strategy in the fight against climate change (Ippolito, Reference Ippolito2020, Reference Ippolito2022, Reference Ippolito2023; Liguori, 2022).
A similar approach might also turn to be applicable before the Human Rights Committee in future cases. Article 24(1) ICCPR entitles every child to special measures designed to protect its life in addition to the general measures required under Article 6 ICCPR for the protection of the lives of all individuals. Accordingly, when taking special measures of protection, states should be guided by the best interests of the child and the need to ensure the survival and development of all children and their well-being. This should apply also with specific regard to those positive obligations of a ‘special character’, which deal ‘with the conditions of the causes of the violation’ of Article 2 and 6 ICCPR. Footnote 23
The Human Rights Committee has partially embraced this understanding in its most recent case law, specifically in a case concerning aboriginal Australians with ancestral ties to the land and territorial sea in Torres Islands, Footnote 24 on consideration that their way of life and culture were being seriously threatened by the prospect of becoming displaced (together with the disappearance of certain species in the sea that are basic foodstuff the complainants depend on). In this case, the vulnerability of the applicants as indigenous people played a role in the configuration of their status as ‘victims’ under the Covenant, which was contested by the defendant state because it related to a form of future harm which had yet to materialise in any existing or foreseeable violation of, or threat to, their rights due to climate impacts. Using a precautionary approach to the interpretation of the notion of ‘imminence’ of the harm concerned (Anderson, Foster, Lambert and McAdam, Reference Anderson, Foster, Lambert and McAdam2019), the Committee did not reason in the sense that the risk must materialise within a short time (using a temporal frame). Instead, it considered those risks that directly (in a causal sense) threaten the persons involved, Footnote 25 linking the ‘alleged serious adverse impacts that have already occurred and are ongoing’ with the foreseeable consequent impairment of rights under the Covenant.
Thus, vulnerability played a role in the determination of the responsibility of Australia, as the destination country, for failing to adopt timely and adequate adaptation measures to protect the collective ability of people to maintain their traditional way of life, to transmit to their children and future generations their culture and traditions, and make use of ancestral land and sea resources. This amounted to a violation of the positive obligation to protect the right to enjoy their minority culture Footnote 26 and should be considered in the individual assessment of the applicant risk situation, as complemented by the overall conditions in the country, considering the level of (for example) an adequate standard of living.
In light of the statement contained in para 9.12 of the Teitiota decision, according to which ‘the assistance of the international community, to take affirmative measures to protect and, where necessary, relocate its population’, this reasoning might also pave the way to a possible application of the positive obligation of non-refoulement, binding the returning/expelling state to a form of subsidiary responsibility to protect third-country nationals (Schefer and Cottier, Reference Schefer and Cottier2015) in those cases where the countries of return are not able to protect them (Maneggia, Reference Maneggia2022). This would considerably extend the non-refoulement protection available to environmentally displaced migrants.
4 Vulnerability as a tool for an expansive reading of complementary protection regimes under EU law able to encompass environmentally-induced migration
Another way in which ‘ecological vulnerability’ might expand human rights protection is via favouring an extensive interpretation of complementary protection regimes, such as humanitarian forms of national protection and the ‘subsidiary protection’ offered by the Qualification Directive in the European Union to persons who do not qualify as refugees but are ‘otherwise’ in need of ‘international protection’. Footnote 27 According to Article 2(e) of the Directive, in fact, a person who is eligible for subsidiary protection is:
‘any third country national or stateless person who does not qualify as a refugee, but in respect of whom there are substantial grounds for believing that the person concerned, if returned to his or her country of origin or, in the case of a stateless person, to his or her country of former habitual residence, would face a real risk of being subjected to serious harm, would face a real risk of suffering the serious harm defined in Article 15, Article 17(1) and (2) not being applicable to that person, and that person being unable or, in view of that risk, unwilling to avail himself or herself of the protection of that country’.
Article 15 further defines ‘serious harm’ as:
-
(a) the death penalty or execution, or
-
(b) torture or inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment of an applicant in his or her country of origin, or
-
(c) serious and individual threat to the life or person of a civilian by reason of indiscriminate violence or in case of internal or international armed conflict.
This list of different types of ‘serious harm’ does not explicitly include harm caused by global environmental problems. However, serious environmental problems may have similar effects to inhuman treatment as those set out in Article 15(b) of the Directive.
According to the case law of the European Court of Justice (CJEU), to qualify for subsidiary protection it is necessary to show that a threat of ‘serious harm’ is ‘individual’, either by reasons of ‘specific risk’ factors to do with a person’s particular characteristics or circumstances or by the ‘general risk’ factors arising out of an exceptional situation of a very high level of violence in the country of origin. Footnote 28 The Court appears to be following a ‘sliding scale’ approach (see further, Moreno-Lax and Garlick, Reference Moreno-Lax, Garlick, Peers, Moreno-Lax, Garlick and Guild2015), balancing individual threat and indiscriminate violence as two extremes of the same continuum, applying a notion of ‘general risk’ similar to the one developed in the case law of the ECtHR relating to Article 3 ECHR. Footnote 29 However, it seems to only apply this reasoning to situations related to Article 15(c) of the Qualification Directive, despite the fact that Article 15(b) of the Directive is based upon the jurisprudence of the ECtHR on Article 3 ECHR. In this connection, the Court has noted, in the case M’Bodj, Footnote 30 precisely that Article 15(b):
‘must be interpreted as meaning that serious harm … does not cover a situation in which inhuman or degrading treatment … to which an applicant suffering from a serious illness may be subjected if returned to his country of origin, is the result of the fact that appropriate treatment is not available in that country, unless such an applicant is intentionally deprived of health care’ (para. 41).
It seems therefore clear that the relevant ‘serious harm’ must necessarily derive from the conduct of an actor, rather than simply result from general shortcomings in the health system of the country of origin (para. 35). Applied to climate change-related effects, the logical consequence seems to be that, under Article 15(b) of the Qualification Directive, ‘serious harm’ cannot stem from a general situation obtaining from climate-change effects. However, the wording of Article 6 of the Qualification Directive does not preclude the application of subsidiary protection to cases of illness where the risks are situational rather than coming from an identifiable actor, as the list provided in this provision is merely indicative. Moreover, the wording and risk assessment criteria used by the Directive in Article 15(b) are borrowed from Strasbourg’s jurisprudence on Article 3 ECHR and, as noted, the main significance of Article 15(b) is precisely found in it ‘affording a status, rather than simply rendering non-removable, persons in these circumstances’ (Costello, Reference Costello2015). Therefore, a different reading of Article 15(b) could be imagined, inclusive of the risks facing environmentally induced migrants. The recent jurisprudence of the CJEU in Hamed seems to go towards this direction. Footnote 31 In Hamed, the CJEU insisted on the concept of the violation of human dignity linked to Article 4 of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights on the prohibition of ill-treatment as requiring a particularly high threshold of seriousness. It, however, acknowledged that such seriousness encompasses cases where state authorities’ acts or omissions create a situation of extreme material deprivation that would prevent the claimant from meeting their most basic needs and that would impair their physical or mental health or place them in a state of degradation incompatible with human dignity. This should not exclude cases where the serious humanitarian emergency is also caused or exacerbated by climate change and is connected with the vicious circle of poverty, conflict, violence, and the high level of insecurity in which the civilian population may find itself.
National case law concerning requests for asylum or entry visas in connection with phenomena related to climate change, environmental degradation, or natural or man-made disasters, already offers inspiring prospects. The case of Italy, to which the next section turns, identifies specific solutions, including the possibility of issuing a residence permit for disasters and of recognising special protection for those who, as a result of repatriation, would find themselves in a condition of vulnerability, including as a consequence of environmental or climate change.
5 The protective potential of vulnerability-based reasoning in national humanitarian jurisprudence
The case of Italy is particularly illustrative of a proactive vulnerability-inspired reading of the principle of non-refoulement applied to environmentally induced migration, Footnote 32 demonstrating the protective potential of the concept as and when mediated through law (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue). Initially, the possibility of issuing a residence permit for ‘serious reasons of a humanitarian nature or arising from constitutional or international obligations of the Italian State’ Footnote 33 facilitated such a proactive outcome. Such a permit could be released by the Questore upon request or, in cases of rejection of the application for international protection, by the Territorial Commissions where the applicant did not qualify for refugee status or subsidiary protection proper, but still was confronted in the state of origin with ‘serious reasons’ of a humanitarian nature. In the absence of specifications regarding the requirements necessary for the issuance of such permits, the institutions have lent themselves to a broad interpretation regarding those persons who have suffered, or would be at risk of suffering upon removal, an ‘effective deprivation of human rights’. The risk assessment is conducted considering the applicant’s personal conditions in light of the prevailing situation in the country of origin. Indeed, the reference to their individual vulnerability on account also of slow-onset events has allowed Territorial Commissions Footnote 34 – and also Courts Footnote 35 – to extend these permits with respect to serious natural disasters, Footnote 36 droughts, Footnote 37 famine Footnote 38 and floods, Footnote 39 so enlarging the spectrum of situations of non-returnability in case of undignified and unsafe conditions in the country of return. Footnote 40
In the reasoning of the superior jurisdictions, it has been the situational vulnerability of applicants that has been central to extend the recognition of humanitarian non-refoulement in cases where situations that include adverse climatic conditions Footnote 41 may expose the applicant, upon removal, to the risk of a standard of living that does not respect core fundamental rights (including situations of drought, famine, or of unsustainable poverty). Footnote 42 That was the case, for instance, in the most recent jurisprudence of the Italian Court of Cassation, Footnote 43 following the appeal of a man from the Niger Delta against a decision by the Tribunal of Ancona rejecting international protection. The Court recognized the applicability of humanitarian protection (Passarini, Reference Passarini2022; Perrini, Reference Perrini2021) when the situation in the country of origin does not allow for a ‘minimum essential guarantee’ for the individual’s right to life. In particular, the recognition of humanitarian protection on the basis of Article 5(6) of the Testo Unico (TU) on immigration Footnote 44 was significantly anchored to an international obligation, with explicit references to the Teitiota case. The need for the expelling state to assess the individual risk of inhuman or degrading treatment in the country of expulsion alongside the general risk of undignified leaving conditions due to environmental degradation, climate change or unsustainable development in the area, was acknowledged. Footnote 45 Moreover, the Court reduced the burden of proof on asylum seekers in need of humanitarian protection on account of the effects of climate change, so that the more severe the situation of environmental degradation existing in the country of origin, the lesser the need to prove individual vulnerability; and this, especially, if environmental degradation derives from human action or inaction that excludes entire parts of the population from access to essential natural resources, such as cultivable land and drinkable water. In the case at hand, according to the Court, there was no doubt that the appellant was exposed to a situation of serious environmental degradation insofar as no policies were provided in the country of origin to fight against pollution and mitigate climate change. Footnote 46 To the contrary, it retained that the disastrous climatic situation of the country of origin was determined by the conduct of government authorities regarding industrial shrimp farming, the occupation of the territory with expanses of aquaculture tanks and an active policy of deforestation Footnote 47 that exposed the individual to the risk of seeing his fundamental rights to life and dignified existence annihilated, or in any case reduced below the threshold of their essential and inescapable core. Footnote 48 Following the Court of Cassation, an analogous reasoning has been applied by lower courts when confronted with environmental disasters stemming from intentional human misconduct or the over-exploitation of natural resources that endangers a claimant’s life or safety Footnote 49 .
Turning the attention to other European jurisdictions, it is possible to notice the same evolutive interpretation of non-refoulement and humanitarian protection in other countries as well (Scissa, Reference Scissa2021). For instance, the High Administrative Court of Baden-Württemberg, in 2020, annulled the repatriation decree issued to an Afghan national, partly because of the environmental and climatic conditions obtaining in the country of origin. Footnote 50 Like in the Italian jurisprudence, the situational vulnerability of the applicant was instrumental to a reinterpretation of the notion of inhumane and degrading treatment, considering not only the humanitarian situation in the country of origin, covering both the social and economic conditions there, but also the individual situation of the individual concerned. Footnote 51 Accordingly, the principle of non-refoulement has been considered applicable even when the terrible humanitarian conditions facing applicants are attributable to poverty or lack of state resources to deal with a natural phenomenon (Schloss, Reference Schloss2021).
A similar reasoning has been deployed by the Court of Appeal of Bordeaux, Footnote 52 which ruled that a temporary residence permit (carte de séjour temporaire) for medical treatment should be issued to an asylum seeker from Bangladesh because, due to the health and environmental conditions in his country, he would not have access to the essential health treatment he needed. The French Code on the Entry and Stay of Foreigners and the Right of Asylum provides for the possibility of issuing a temporary residence permit to a foreigner, habitually residing in France, who presents a state of health such that, if not treated, he would risk consequences of exceptional seriousness. In this sense, Article L. 313-11 provides that:
‘Sauf si sa présence constitue une menace pour l’ordre public, la carte de séjour temporaire portant la mention “vie privée et familiale” est délivrée de plein droit : … 11° Al’étranger résidant habituellement en France, si son état de santé nécessite une prise en charge médicale dont le défaut pourrait avoir pour lui des conséquences d’une exceptionnelle gravité et si, eu égard à l’offre de soins et aux caractéristiques du système de santé dans le pays dont il est originaire, il ne pourrait pas y bénéficier effectivement d’un traitement approprié’.
In the case at hand, the plaintiff suffered from a certified chronic respiratory condition, aggravated by a severe form of allergic asthma and sleep apnoea syndrome, which required the use of an electric ventilation device every night, as well as frequent maintenance and replacement of the mask, filters, and tubes. The Court of Appeal, once more, based on the vulnerability of the applicant and in the light of the general situation in his country of origin, ordered the issuance of the temporary residence permit. The reasoning stressed how in Bangladesh the rate of particulate matter pollutants is one of the highest in the world, so that, the mortality rate from respiratory diseases is 12.92 percent compared to 0.82 percent in France. Footnote 53 Those grounds served the Court to take account of the ‘very compelling humanitarian grounds’ standard, as articulated by the ECtHR in its case-law on ‘humanitarian non-refoulement’ of persons at risk of ill-treatment on health grounds, due to the lack of sufficient resources to deal with their condition in the receiving country. Footnote 54 Anchoring its reasoning in this ECtHR jurisprudence, Footnote 55 the Court formulated a positive obligation on the expelling state for the prevention of the further vulnerabilisation of the applicant. Such a positive obligation, insofar as the non-refoulement principle was at stake, implied that an individual assessment of the applicant’s condition in the receiving state had to include how his condition would evolve upon expulsion, Footnote 56 particularly in the light of the distinguishing features that make the lack of health services especially deleterious in the applicant’s regard, especially when combined with environmental degradation and underlying socio-economic vulnerabilities.
This reasoning, in the case at hand, led the applicant to obtain the extension of his residence permit for medical treatment given the severe environmental and health conditions prevailing in the country of origin. Footnote 57 Its extension to similar cases could even lead to new forms of asylum based on the cumulative impacts of climate change on people’s ability to enjoy their socio-economic rights when removal to ‘destitution’ amounts to inhuman or degrading treatment. Footnote 58
6 Concluding remarks: vulnerability to shore up an emerging law for the protection of environmental migrants?
Environmentally induced migration, together with the other drivers of migration, such as economic deprivation, social discrimination, and politically adverse conditions, acts as a push factor on human mobility (cf. Grundler, in this issue). However, environmental migrants remain undefined under international law and the lack of any conceptualisation of the notion of vulnerability, letalone an articulation of the theory of ‘ecological vulnerability’, in their regard makes it difficult to develop an international legal instrument to protect them, while at the same time leaving them unprotected under current (refugee) law. The law itself exacerbates the vulnerability facing environmental migrants (Moreno-Lax and Vavoula, in this issue). Nonetheless, as the previous sections have shown, human rights law and, in particular, the principle of non-refoulement may offer some respite when interpreted through an intersectional, holistic lens that takes account of all the relevant circumstances of each individual case (Moreno-Lax, Reference Moreno-Lax2021).
In particular, the vulnerability (whether situational, contextual, or compounded) of environmental migrants could well become an empowering tool, if the notion of ‘ecological vulnerability’ would be legally employed by Courts and decision-makers around the world. The analysis above has shown how that notion may help in reconceptualizing non-refoulement obligations, generating a (virtuous) expansion of traditional asylum norms and the flexibilisation of access to international protection for environmentally and climate-induced migrants (European Commission, 2021). Namely, in the same vein that feminist studies have valorised the notion of ‘vulnerability’ to generate a more ‘responsive State’ (Fineman, Reference Fineman2008), discharging positive obligations of redistributive justice, when applied to the expulsion of environmental and climate-induced migrants, an ecological vulnerability-mediated interpretation of the law allows for an expansive (and principled) application of the non-refoulement obligation and the generation of additional humanitarian protection. The advent of the Anthropocene era requires a heightened awareness of the relationship between humans and the environments in which they live, which provides the grounds for said vulnerability to be considered pertinent and applicable in legal assessment. Emphasizing the ‘prognosis’ function of the ‘returnability test’, the application of an ‘ecological vulnerability’ lens should imply a refocusing of the assessment of individual situations in the destination country by expelling states to determine the ‘reasonableness of return’ (Kälin, Reference Kälin and McAdam2010). This should be conducted in the light of both the individual risk situation facing applicants and the general conditions obtaining in the country of origin, which should not amount to a breach of the right to a dignified life, including due to climate change and environmental degradation, interpreting the imminence of the risk not as the necessity that the risk materialises within a short period of time, but rather as comprising those risks that are directly threatening the persons involved in a material and causal sense.
Alternatively, or complementarily, the application of the same ‘ecological vulnerability’ theory could not only exclude or nuance the returnability of environmental migrants, but additionally serve to advance the case for their substantive protection. An ecological vulnerability-imbued reinterpretation of the law favours an extensive construal of the complementary protection regimes such as the ‘subsidiary protection’ offered under the EU Qualification Directive and similar national forms of humanitarian protection. Should some of the national practices explored in this article further expand, (ecological) vulnerability may become a helpful device to alleviate harm and produce new forms of asylum from the worst collateral effects of unsustainable development and climate change. In so doing, this expansion would help realising justice by contributing to achieving ‘just resilience’, which is essential for the equitable distribution of climate adaptation benefits (European Commission, 2021).
Acknowledgments
This article belongs to the Special Issue: Law, Migration and Vulnerability: From the Margins to the Centre, edited by Violeta Moreno-Lax and Niovi Vavoula, which is a deliverable of the Migration and Asylum Policy Systems (MAPS) Jean Monnet Network <https://www.mapsnetwork.eu/> funded by the Jean Monnet Programme (2018-2022) 599856-EPP-1-2018-1-IT-EPPJMO-NETWORK, Grant decision 2018-1606/001-001. Iam indebted to the editors and peer-reviewers for their generous feedback.
Competing Interests
None.