Published online by Cambridge University Press: 26 January 2009
This paper focuses on two works of nineteenth-century feminism: Harriet Taylor's essay, Enfranchisement of Women, and John Stuart Mill's The Subjection of Women. My aim is to indicate that these texts are more radical than is usually allowed: far from being merely criticisms of the legal disabilities suffered by women in Victorian Britain, they are important moral texts which anticipate central themes within twentieth-century radical feminism. In particular, The Subjection of Women is not merely a liberal defence of legal equality; it is a positive statement of the inadequacy of ‘male” conceptions of reason and its powers. So understood, I shall argue, it coheres with Mill's other moral and political writings, and draws much of its persuasive power from the doctrines advanced in Harriet Taylor's Enfranchisement of Women.
1 References to The Subjection of Women and Enfranchisement of Women are to the Virago edition, London, 1983Google Scholar. References in square brackets are to the Collected Works edition of The Subjection of Women, Essays on Equality, Law, and Education, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1984Google Scholar, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, xxi. 259–340.Google Scholar
2 Packe, Michael St. J., The Life of John Stuart Mill, London, 1954, p. 492.Google Scholar
3 Robson, Ann ‘No Laughing Matter: John Stuart Mill's Establishment of Women's Suffrage as a Parliamentary Question”, Utilitas, ii (1990), 101.Google Scholar
4 Packe, , p. 495.Google Scholar
5 Stephen, James Fitzjames, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity, ed. White, R. J., Cambridge, 1967, pp. 190–1.Google Scholar
6 All quotations as cited in Packe, , p. 495 ff.Google Scholar
7 Stephen, Fitzjames, pp. 196–7.Google Scholar
8 Soper, Kate, Introduction to the Virago edition of The Subjection of Women and Enfranchisement of Women, p. viii.Google Scholar
9 Annas, Julia, ‘Mill and the Subjection of Women”, Philosophy, lii (1977), 191.Google Scholar
10 Pateman, Carole The Sexual Contract, Cambridge, 1988, pp. 160–3.Google Scholar
11 The Subjection of Women, pp. 1–2, [p. 261].Google Scholar
12 Ibid., p. 177, [p. 336].
13 Collini, Stefan, Introduction to Essays on Equality, Law and Education, CW, xxi. p. xv.Google Scholar
14 As quoted in John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor: Essays on Sex Equality, ed. Rossi, Alice S., Chicago, 1970, p. 35.Google Scholar
15 Rose, Phyllis, Parallel Lives: Five Victorian Marriages, Harmondsworth, 1985, p. 15.Google Scholar
16 Himmelfarb, Gertrude, Of Liberty and Liberalism: The Case of John Stuart Mill, New York, 1974.Google Scholar
17 Pateman, , p. 160.Google Scholar
18 As quoted in Soper, , p. xiv, n. 14.Google Scholar
19 Enfranchisement of Women, pp. 26–30, 37.Google Scholar
20 Rossi, , p. 85.Google Scholar
21 Ibid., p. 70.
22 Ibid.
23 Jaggar, Alison, Feminist Politics and Human Nature, Sussex, 1983, p. 264.Google Scholar
24 ‘Early Essay on Marriage and Divorce” in Rossi, , p. 85.Google Scholar
25 The Subjection of Women, p. 27, [p. 271].Google Scholar
26 Ibid., p. 150, [p. 324].
27 Enfranchisement of Women, pp. 38, 24.Google Scholar
28 Jaggar, , p. 97.Google Scholar
29 Ibid., p. 95 ff.
30 Mill on Bentham and Coleridge, ed. Leavis, F. R., Cambridge, 1980, p. 9.Google Scholar
31 Mill, J. S., Autobiography, ed. Stillinger, J., Oxford, 1985, p. 89.Google Scholar
32 Ibid., p. 106.
33 Annas, Julia, p. 184.Google Scholar
34 Firestone, Shulamith, The Dialectic of Sex, London, 1979.Google Scholar
35 Wordsworth, William, The Prelude, 1850, ed. de Selincourt, Ernest, Oxford, 1959, XIII 169–172.Google Scholar