Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T01:49:20.676Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

J. S. Mill and Political Violence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 January 2009

Extract

The most common view of Mill sees him as the classic liberal and one key element in this liberalism is said to be that his thought ‘rests on the belief that the use of reason can settle fundamental social conflicts’. He is seen by a leading authority as ‘the rationalist, confident that social change could be effected by the art of persuasion and by the simple fact that men would learn from bitter experiences’. To point out that at various times in his life Mill supported the use of violence in political life is insufficient in itself to challenge this basic view. However, if it can be shown that Mill's support for political violence adds up to a coherent justificatory theory then Mill's standing as the model liberal upholder of reason might need to be revised. Or at least the commonly assumed opposition between reason and violence will need to be re-examined. Are there circumstances in which the use of violence rather than persuasion is the rational course? In looking at Mill's response to events in France, America, Ireland, and Canada as well as his attitude to British politics it is clear that there are numerous examples of his support for the use of violence: ‘I do not scruple to say that I have sympathised more or less ardently with most of the rebellions, successful and unsuccessful, which have taken place in my time’. Our present concern is to see whether he developed any general principles whereby such violence could be shown to be legitimate.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Gray, J., ‘John Stuart Mill: the Crisis of Liberalism’, Political Thought from Plato to NATO, ed. Redhead, B., London, 1984, p. 149.Google Scholar

2 Brady, A., ‘Introduction’Google Scholar, Mill, John Stuart, Essays on Politics and Society, ed. Robson, John M., 2 vols., Toronto, 1977Google Scholar (Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vols. xviii and xix), xviii. p. lxx.Google Scholar

3 By ‘political violence’ I mean the use of illegal force directed at changing the political structure or policies within the system. The types of violence examined here— insurrection, rebellion, revolution—involve a denial of the legitimacy of the state.

4 Mill, , ‘The Contest in America’, in Essays on Equality, Law and Education, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1984 (CW, vol. xxi), xxi. 137.Google Scholar

5 Mill, , ‘Three Essays on Religion’, in Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1969 (CW, vol. x), x. 387–88Google Scholar

6 Mill, , ‘The Close of the Session in France’, Newspaper Writings, ed. Robson, Ann P. and Robson, John M., 4 vols., Toronto, 1986 (CW, vols. xxii–xxv), xxiii. 453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Ibid., xxiii. 454–55.

8 Mill, , ‘Alison's History of the French Revolution’, in Essays on French History and Historians, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1985 (CW, vol. xx), xx. 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Ibid., xx. 120.

10 See Mueller, I. W., John Stuart Mill and French Thought, Urbana, 1956.Google Scholar Also Coleman, J., ‘John Stuart Mill and the French Revolution’, History of Political Thought, iv (1983), 89110.Google Scholar

11 Mill, to Mill, James, 21 08 1830Google Scholar, The Earlier Letters 1812–48, ed. Mineka, Francis E., Toronto, 1963 (CW, vols. xii–xiii), xii. 60.Google Scholar

12 Mill, , ‘Vindication of the French Revolution of February 1848’, in Essays on French History and Historians (CW), xx. 346.Google Scholar

13 Ibid., xx. 359.

14 Ibid., xx. 331–32.

15 Mill, to Chapman, Henry S., 29 02 1848Google Scholar, The Earlier Letters (CW), xiii. 732.Google Scholar

16 Mill, , ‘The French Law Against the Press’, in Newspaper Writings 1847–73 (CW), xxv. 1118.Google Scholar

17 Referred to in M. St. Packe, J., The Life of John Stuart Mill, London, 1954, p. 504.Google Scholar Orsini attempted to assassinate Napoleon III in 1858. He fled to England where Palmerston sponsored a bill to allow the arrest and imprisonment of those who conspired against the lives of foreign rulers. Mill opposed the bill, which was defeated. He praised Orsini as one of those who had ‘virtue enough to be his [i.e. Napoleon's] avowed enemies’. Mill, to Mazzini, Guiseppe, 21 02 1858Google Scholar, The Later Letters 1842–73, ed. Mineka, Francis E. and Lindley, Dwight N., 4 vols., Toronto, 1972 (CW, vols. xiv–xvii), xv. 548.Google Scholar

18 Mill, , ‘Radical Party and Canada’, in Essays on England, Ireland and the Empire, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1982 (CW, vol. vi), vi. 414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Ibid., vi. 416.

21 Mill, , ‘What is to be done with Ireland?’, in Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire (CW), vi. 503.Google Scholar

22 Mill, to Bridges, John Henry, 16 11 1867Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1329.Google Scholar

23 Mill, , ‘England and Ireland’, in Essays on England, Ireland, and the Empire (CW), vi. 512.Google Scholar

24 Ibid., vi. 509.

25 Mill, to Cairnes, John Elliot, 26 05 1867Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1272.Google Scholar

26 Mill, , ‘The Contest in America’, in Essays on Equality, Law, and Education (CW), xxi. 136.Google Scholar

27 Mill, to Cairnes, John Elliot, 7 02 1863Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xv. 835.Google Scholar

28 Mill, , ‘The Contest in America’, in Essays on Equality, Law, and Education (CW), xxi. 135.Google Scholar

29 Ibid., xxi. 139.

30 Ibid., xxi. 137.

31 Mill, to Hazard, Rowland G., 7 06 1865Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1066.Google Scholar

32 Mill, to Dickson, William Martin, 1 09 1865Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 10981101.Google Scholar

33 Mill, , ‘Poland’, Newspaper Writings (CW), xxv. 1203.Google Scholar

34 Mill, to Austin, John, 13 04 1847Google Scholar, The Earlier Letters (CW), xiii. 718.Google Scholar

36 Mill, , Autobiography in Autobiography and Literary Essays, ed. Robson, John M., Toronto, 1981 (CW, vol. i), i. 278.Google Scholar

37 Mill, to Sharp, G. W., 1 06 1867Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1275.Google Scholar The first of the quotations is from a speech at St. James's Hall, 25 May 1867, (footnote 2).

38 Mill, to Cremer, William Randal, 1 03 1867Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1248.Google Scholar

39 Mill, to Chapman, John, 9 06 1851Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xiv. 68.Google Scholar

40 Mill, to Smith, Thomas, 4 10 1872Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvii. 1912.Google Scholar

41 Mill, to Barry, M. Maltman, 20 04 1872Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvii. 1883.Google Scholar

42 Mill, , ‘The Contest in America’, Essays on Equality, Law, and Education (CW), xxi. 141–42.Google Scholar

43 Mill, to Beal, James, 17 04 1865Google Scholar, The Later Letters (CW), xvi. 1033.Google Scholar

44 Mill's formulation is reminiscent of Aquinas's justification of tyrannicide which specifies three conditions: the violation of natural law; no consequent deterioration in the situation; an actual improvement resulting from the killing. As with Mill, such violence calls for both moral and political judgement.