Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T08:16:55.140Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Don't Go Chasing Waterfalls: Against Hayward's “Utility Cascades”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2022

Ryan Doody*
Affiliation:
Brown University, Providence, Rhode Island, USA

Abstract

In his article “Utility Cascades”, Max Khan Hayward argues that act-utilitarians should sometimes either ignore evidence about the effectiveness of their actions or fail to apportion their support to an action's effectiveness. His conclusions are said to have particular significance for the effective altruism movement, which centers seeking and being guided by evidence. Hayward's argument is that act-utilitarians are vulnerable to succumbing to “utility cascades”, that these cascades function to frustrate the ultimate goals of act-utilitarians, and that one apposite way to avoid them is by “ostriching”: ignoring relevant evidence. If true, this conclusion would have remarkable consequences for act-utilitarianism and the effective altruism movement. However, Hayward is mistaken – albeit in an interesting way and with broader significance for moral philosophy. His argument trades on a subtle mischaracterization of act-utilitarianism. Act-utilitarians are not especially vulnerable to utility cascades (or at least not objectionably so), and they shouldn't ostrich.

Type
Reply
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Berkey, Brian. 2018. The Institutional Critique of Effective Altruism. Utilitas, 30: 143–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkey, Brian. 2021. The Philosophical Core of Effective Altruism. Journal of Social Philosophy, 52(1): 93115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandt, Richard. 1959. Ethical Theory: The Problems of Normative and Critical Ethics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall).Google Scholar
Broi, Antonin. 2019. Effective Altruism and Systemic Change. Utilitas, 31: 262–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchak, Lara. 2010. Instrumental Rationality, Epistemic Rationality, and Evidence-gathering. Philosophical Perspectives, 24: 85120.Google Scholar
Collins, Stephanie. 2019. Beyond Individualism. In Effective Altruism: Philosophical Issues, ed. by Greaves, Hilary and Pummer, Theron (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 202–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietz, Alexander. 2019. Effective Altruism and Collective Obligations. Utilitas, 31(1): 106–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doody, Ryan. MS. Consider the Ostrich: Non-Utilitarians, Ex Ante Interest, and Burying Your Head in the Sand. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1965. Rule-Utilitarianism: Merely an Illusory Alternative? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 43: 211–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Good, I. J. 1967. On the Principle of Total Evidence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 17(4): 129–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halstead, John G. 2019. The ITN framework, cost-effectiveness, and cause prioritisation. Effective Altruism Forum. URL https://forum.effectivealtruism.org/posts/Eav7tedvX96Gk2uKE/the-itn-framework-cost-effectiveness-and-causeGoogle Scholar
Hayward, Max Khan. 2020. Utility Cascades. Analysis, 80(3): 433–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1991. Decision-theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection. Ethics, 101: 461–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacAskill, William. 2015. Doing Good Better: How Effective Altruism Can Help You Make a Difference (New York: Penguin Random House).Google Scholar
MacAskill, William. 2019. The Definition of Effective Altruism. In Effective Altruism: Philosophical Issues, ed. by Greaves, H. and Pummer, T. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 1028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulgan, Tim. 2001. The Demands of Consequentialism (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Oddie, Graham and Menzies, Peter. 1992. An Objectivist's Guide to Subjective Value. Ethics, 102: 512–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. MS. What We Together Do. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1984. Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13(2): 134–71.Google Scholar
Regan, Donald. 1980. Utilitarianism and Cooperation (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1907. The Methods of Ethics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1973. An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics. In Utilitarianism: For and Against, ed. by Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timmons, Mark. 2002. Moral Theory: An Introduction (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).Google Scholar
Todd, Peter M. and Gigerenzer, Gerd. 2012. Ecological Rationality: The Normative Study of Heuristics. In Ecological Rationality: Intelligence in the World, ed. by Todd, Peter M., Gigerenzer, Gerd, and the ABC Research Group (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 487–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiblin, Rob. 2016. A Framework for Comparing Global Problems in Terms of Expected Impact. 80,000 Hours. URL https://80000hours.org/articles/problem-framework/Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Michael. 1996. The Concept of Moral Obligation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar