Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T17:28:38.220Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evaluative Delusions: Their Significance for Philosophy and Psychiatry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 August 2018

K. W. M. Fulford*
Affiliation:
University Department of Psychiatry, Warneford Hospital, Oxford OX3 7JX

Extract

The significance of delusions for psychiatry is well recognised. Scientifically respectable, delusions are reliably identifiable clinically (Wing et al, 1974), widely acknowledged across diverse cultural norms as genuine symptoms of illness (Wing, 1978), and central to the historical notion of insanity (Jaspers, 1913). What is not so well recognised, however, is that delusions are also highly significant for philosophy. This is not well recognised either by philosophers or by doctors. Yet the key to recognising it lies not in some obscure philosophical analysis of delusions but in a feature of their everyday clinical phenomenology.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal College of Psychiatrists 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

American Psychiatric Association (1980) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (3rd edn) (DSM-III). Washington, DC: APA.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1956–57) A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 130. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Action (ed. White, A. R., 1968). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berrios, G. E. (1991) Delusions as “wrong beliefs”: a conceptual history. British Journal of Psychiatry, 159 (suppl. 14 ), 613.Google Scholar
Boorse, C. (1975) On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5, 4968.Google Scholar
Duff, A. (1977) Psychopathy and moral understanding. American Philosophical Quarterly, 14, 189200.Google Scholar
Flew, A. (1973) Crime or Disease? New York: Barnes and Noble.Google Scholar
Fulford, K. W. M. (1990) Moral Theory and Medical Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Glover, J. (1970) Responsibility. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1963) Descriptivism. Proceedings of the British Academy, 49. Reprinted in Hare, R. M. (1972) Essays on the Moral Concepts. London: The Macmillan Press Ltd.Google Scholar
Harre, R. & Lamb, R. (1986) (eds) The Dictionary of Physiological and Clinical Psychology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.Google Scholar
Hemsley, D. R. & Garety, P. A. (1986) The formation and maintenance of delusions: a Bayesian analysis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 149, 5156.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1980) Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science. Brighton: The Harvester Press.Google Scholar
Hudson, W. D. (1970) Modern Moral Philosophy. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hundert, E. M. (1989) Philosophy, Psychiatry and Neurosciences: Three Approaches to the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jaspers, K. (1913) General Psychopathology. (Transl. by Hoenig, J. & Hamilton, M. W. (1963).) Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Mullen, P. (1979) Phenomenology of disordered mental function. In Essentials of Postgraduate Psychiatry (eds Hill, P., Murray, R. & Thorley, A.), chapter 2. London: Academic Press. New York: Grune & Stratton.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981) The Structure of Science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Quinton, A. (1985) Madness. In Philosophy and Practice (ed. Griffiths, A. P.), ch. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1940) An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: George Allen and Unwin (Pelican Books).Google Scholar
Scadding, J. G. (1988) Health and disease. What can medicine do for philosophy? Journal of Medical Ethics, 14, 118124.Google Scholar
Spitzer, M. & Maher, A. (1989) (eds) Philosophy and Psychopathology. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Vauhkonen, K. (1968) On the Pathogenesis of Morbid Jealousy, with Special Reference to the Personality Traits of and Interaction Between Jealous Patients and their Spouses. Copenhagen: Munksgaard.Google Scholar
Warnock, G. J. (1967) Contemporary Moral Philosophy. London and Basingstoke: The Macmillan Press Ltd.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wing, J. K. (1978) Reasoning about Madness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wing, J. K., Cooper, J. E. & Sartorius, N. (1974) Measurements and Classification of Psychiatric Symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.