Article contents
Pluralism and Reasonable Disagreement*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 18 June 2009
Extract
Liberalism is a distinctively modern political conception. Only in modern times do we find, as the object of both systematic reflection and widespread allegiance and institutionalization, the idea that the principles of political association, being coercive, should be justifiable to all whom they are to bind. And so only here do we find the idea that these principles should rest, so far as possible, on a core, minimal morality which reasonable people can share, given their expectably divergent religious convictions and conceptions of the meaning of life. No longer does it seem evident—as it did, let us say, before the seventeenth century—that the aim of political association must be to bring man into harmony with God's purposes or to serve some comprehensive vision of the good life. The causes of this transformation are various, and not all of them lie at the level of moral principle. But a change in moral consciousness has certainly been one of the factors involved. As Hegel observed, modern culture is inherently a reflective one: notions of principle are essential to our self-understanding and thus to the stability of the social forms in which we participate. Modern culture has no room for a dichotomy between “in principle” and “in practice.” It is worth determining, then, what new moral conceptions have been responsible for the emergence of modern liberalism. Not only will we thereby better understand how we have become who we are, we will also have a surer grasp of the principles that sustain our political life.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1994
References
1 For this characterization of liberalism, see my “Political Liberalism” Political Theory, vol. 18, no. 13 (08 1990), pp. 339–60.Google Scholar
2 Hegel, G. W. F., Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik, “Einleitung” (Lectures on Aesthetics, “Introduction”), in Werke (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970), vol. 13, pp. 24f.Google Scholar
3 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. xvii.Google Scholar
4 Ibid., p. 36. See also Rawls, , “Dewey Lectures” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 72, no. 9 (09 1980), p. 542.Google Scholar
5 Berlin, Isaiah, The Crooked Timber of Humanity (New York: Knopf, 1991), pp. 79–80.Google Scholar
6 Despite his misleading use of the term “pluralism,” Rawls himself does not do so. At one point, indeed, he seems close to acknowledging the difference between the two notions. See his “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus” New York University Law Review, vol. 64, no. 2 (05 1989), p. 237 n. 7.Google Scholar
7 See, for example, Kant, Immanuel, Kritik der praktischen Vemunft (Critique of Practical Reason), Akademieausgabe (Berlin: Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1900–1942), vol. 5, p. 25.Google Scholar
8 For more details, see my Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 131–53.Google Scholar
9 Berlin, , The Crooked Timber of Humanity, pp. 5, 24, 209.Google Scholar
10 Ibid., pp. 11, 79.
11 Hare, R. M., Moral Thinking (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981), pp. 25–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Lukes, Steven, Moral Conflict and Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), pp. 5f.Google Scholar
13 Levi, Isaac, Hard Choices (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1986), ch. 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14 See my Patterns of Moral Complexity, pp. 149–50.Google Scholar
15 Berlin, , The Crooked Timber of Humanity, pp. 79–80.Google Scholar
16 Ibid., pp. 37, 224.
17 Herder, J. G., Auch cine Philosophie der Geschichte (Yet Another Philosophy of History) (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1967), p. 46.Google Scholar
18 Herder, J. G., Briefe zur Beförderung der Humanität (Letters for the Promotion of Humanity), Sechste Sammlung, section 79.Google Scholar
19 See McNaughton, David, Moral Vision (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988).Google Scholar
20 Cf. Moore, G. E., “Four Forms of Scepticism,” in Philosophical Papers (New York: Macmillan, 1959), p. 222.Google Scholar
21 See Ackrill, J. L., “Aristotle on Eudaimonia,” in Rorty, A. O., ed., Essays on Aristotle's Ethics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp. 15–33Google Scholar; Nussbaum, Martha, The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1986), ch. 10, pp. 373–77Google Scholar, and Love's Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 56–66Google Scholar; Urmson, J. O., Aristotle's Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988), pp. 13ff., 119ff.Google Scholar; and Beiner, Ronald, “The Moral Vocabulary of Liberalism,” in Nomos XXXIV: Virtue, ed. Chapman, John W. and Galston, William A. (New York: New York University Press, 1992), pp. 145–84Google Scholar. Some of my remarks here are drawn from my essay “The Limits of Aristotelian Ethics,” in Nomos XXXIV: Virtue, pp. 185–96.Google Scholar
22 Nussbaum, , Thc Fragility of Goodness, p. 374Google Scholar; Beiner, , “The Moral Vocabulary of Liberalism,” pp. 161–62.Google Scholar
23 Nussbaum, , The Fragility of Goodness, pp. 373–77.Google Scholar
24 Urmson, , Aristotle's Ethics, p. 125.Google Scholar
25 Nussbaum, , The Fragility of Goodness, p. 376Google Scholar. Cf. also Ackrill, , “Aristotle on Eudaimonia,” p. 28.Google Scholar
26 Nussbaum, , The Fragility of Goodness, pp. 374f.Google Scholar
27 Lear, Jonathan, Aristotle: The Desire to Understand (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 320CrossRefGoogle Scholar. I also find very convincing the critique of the “inclusivist” interpretation of Aristotelian eudaimonia in Kraut, Richard, Aristotle on the Human Good (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
28 See the commentary in Hardie, W. F. R., Aristotle's Ethical Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968), pp. 55–56, 63–65.Google Scholar
29 See my Patterns of Moral Complexity, pp. 134ff.Google Scholar, and also “Théodicée et rationalité morale chez Malebranche, Leibniz, et Bayle,” in my Modernité et morale (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1993).Google Scholar
30 de Montaigne, Michel, Essais, III. 13, in Oeuvres complètes (Paris: Gallimard, 1962), pp. 1043–44:Google Scholar
By subdividing these subtleties they teach men to increase their doubts; they start us extending and diversifying the difficulties, they lengthen them, they scatter them. By sowing questions and cutting them up, they make the world frqctify and teem with uncertainty and quarrels, as the earth is made more fertile the more it is crumbled and deeply plowed. Learning makes difficulties. … Never did two men judge alike about the same thing, and it is impossible to find two opinions exactly alike, not only in different men, but in the same man at different times.
(Translation by Frame, Donald, The Complete Essays of Montaigne [Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1957], pp. 816–17.)Google Scholar Cf. also Paine, Thomas, The Rights of Man (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984), II.5, p. 271Google Scholar: “I do not believe that any two men, on what are called doctrinal points, think alike who think at all. It is only those who have not thought that appear to agree.”
31 Kundera, Milan, The Art of the Novel (New York: Harper and Row, 1988), p. 158.Google Scholar
32 Rawls, , “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus,” pp. 236–37Google Scholar, and Political Liberalism, pp. 56–57.Google Scholar
33 See, on these lines, the fascinating study by Shapin, Steven and Shaffer, Simon, Leviathan and the Airpump (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
34 Nagel, Thomas, “Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 16, no. 3 (Summer 1987), p. 232.Google Scholar
35 Cohen, Joshua, “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” manuscript, pp. 18, 21Google Scholar, forthcoming in Copp, David and Hampton, Jean, eds., The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
36 For more detail on the epistemology here, see my “Au-delà de la religion et des Lumières,” in Modernité el morale.
- 32
- Cited by