Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:01:55.005Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

OWNERSHIP AND THE MORAL SIGNIFICANCE OF THE SELF

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2020

Victor Tadros*
Affiliation:
Criminal Law and Legal Theory, University of Warwick

Abstract:

The idea of self-ownership has played a prominent role in justifying normative conclusions in moral and political philosophy. I argue that whether or not we are self-owners, there is no such role for it to play. Self-ownership is better thought a conclusion of moral and political arguments rather than their source. I then begin to explore an alternative idea—that the self is morally significant—that provides what those who rely on self-ownership ought to be looking for.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2020 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, II, 4.

2 See Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974), 167–74.Google Scholar

3 Otsuka, Michael, Libertarianism Without Inequality (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 See, especially, Steiner, Hillel, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994).Google Scholar

5 See Peter Vallentyne, “Left-Libertarianism and Liberty,” in Christiano, Thomas and Christman, J., Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy (Chichester: Wiley, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 See van Parijs, Phillipe, Real Freedom for All: What (If Anything) Can Justify Capitalism? (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995).Google Scholar

7 See, further, Tadros, VictorIndependence Without Interests?Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31, no. 193 (2011) for an argument against the Kantian view about this.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 See, especially, Ripstein, Arthur, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Political Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 See Bennett, Karen, Making Things Up (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Sometimes constituting is treated as an instance of the more general class of grounding relations. This is just a matter of terminology, but I find it more natural to use grounding in the more restrictive sense and building or dependence to capture the more general class.

11 Jurisprudential debates are a standard example of a debate about grounding relations—hard positivists believe that only social facts ground laws where anti-positivists disagree. See, for example, G. Rosen “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction” in Hale, Bob and Hoffmann, Aviv, Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 See, especially, Berker, SelimThe Unity of Grounding,” Mind 127 (2018): 729–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 See, especially, Vallentyne, Peter, Steiner, Hillel, and Otsuka, MichaelWhy Left-Libertarianism is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005): 201, 204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 As Vallentyne, Steiner, and Otsuka acknowledge. See “Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant,” 207. See, also, Otsuka, Libertarianism Without Inequality, 12–15.

15 See Otsuka, Libertarianism Without Inequality, 15.

16 See Fried, B.Left-Libertarianism: A Review Essay,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (2004): 66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 See, for an especially influential discussion, Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), chap. 12.Google Scholar

18 The view that physical continuity of the brain matters to egoistic concern is defended in McMahan, Jeff, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002),CrossRefGoogle Scholar chap. 1. I am sympathetic to the significance of physical continuity, but doubt that it is only continuity of the brain that matters.

19 See Cohen, G. A., Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), chap. 10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Ibid., 243–44.