Article contents
EUVOLUNTARY OR NOT, EXCHANGE IS JUST*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 31 May 2011
Abstract
The arguments for redistribution of wealth, and for prohibiting certain transactions such as price-gouging, both are based in mistaken conceptions of exchange. This paper proposes a neologism, “euvoluntary” exchange, meaning both that the exchange is truly voluntary and that it benefits both parties to the transaction. The argument has two parts: First, all euvoluntary exchanges should be permitted, and there is no justification for redistribution of wealth if disparities result only from euvoluntary exchanges. Second, even exchanges that are not euvoluntary should generally be permitted, because access to market exchange may be the only means by which people in desperate circumstances can improve their position.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2011
References
1 Versions of this apparent paradox have been described variously by Ferguson, Adam, An Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767), available on the Web site of the Constitution Society, http://www.constitution.org/af/civil.htmGoogle Scholar; Mandeville, Bernard, The Fable of the Bees or Private Vices, Publick Benefits, 2 vols., with a commentary by F. B. Kaye (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1988), http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/1863Google Scholar; and Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, vol. I, ed. Campbell, R. H. and Skinner, A. S., vol. II of the Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1981), http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/220Google Scholar.
2 The Greek prefix “eu-” means good, well, true, or pleasing. Thus, “euvoluntary” captures the meaning of being essentially or truly voluntary, as well as being good for or pleasing to both parties to the transaction.
3 Mill, John Stuart, The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume II—The Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy (Books I–II), ed. Robson, John M., Bladen, introduction by V. W. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965), http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/102/9661Google Scholar.
4 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 303–5Google Scholar.
5 Perhaps the earliest modern statement of the consequences of individual decisions for the justice of the overall distribution was Locke, John's 1695 “Venditio,” reprinted in Wooten, David, ed., John Locke: Political Writings (Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 2003), 442–46Google Scholar. My own view is probably closest to that argued by F. A. Hayek: “There can be no test by which we can discover what is ‘socially unjust’ because there is no subject by which such an injustice can be committed, and there are no rules of individual conduct the observance of which in the market order would secure to the individuals and groups the position which as such (as distinguished from the procedure by which it is determined) would appear just to us. It does not belong to the category of error but to that of nonsense, like the term ‘a moral stone’.” Hayek, Friedrich A., Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Volume 2: The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 78CrossRefGoogle Scholar; emphasis in the original. There are clearly problems with this view, and, as John Tomasi points out, it is hard to claim that even Hayek believed it fully. See Tomasi, John, “Hayek on Spontaneous Order and the ‘Mirage of Social Justice,’” (New York: Hayek Lecture, Manhattan Institute, June 20, 2007)Google Scholar. See also Galston, William, Justice and the Human Good (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Gaus, Gerald F., The Modern Liberal Theory of Man (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1983)Google Scholar; and Gaus, Gerald F., “Property, Rights, and Freedom,” Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 2 (1994): 209–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
6 Marx, Karl, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy (1867), trans. Fowkes, Ben (New York: Penguin, 1992)Google Scholar. The Marxist conception of class has both objective and subjective elements, the complete treatment of which is well beyond the scope of the present essay.
7 For exchange to be voluntary, it must also be true that there are no large-scale or dangerous externalities. In a private property regime with small numbers, this assumption is easily met by Coasen bargaining. If property is common and numbers are large, however, state action may be required. But this is more a problem with the property rights regime than with exchange itself. See Coase, Ronald, “The Problem of Social Cost,” Journal of Law and Economics 3 (1960): 1–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The problem of conceiving of “property” in this context is illustrated by Eric Mack's imaginative article on blackmail. Mack, Eric, “In Defense of Blackmail,” Philosophical Studies 41, no. 2 (1982): 273–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
8 Black, Henry C., A Treatise on the Rescission of Contracts and Cancellation of Written Instruments (Kansas City, MO: Vernon Law Book Co., 1916), chaps. 2, 4, and 5Google Scholar.
9 Ibid.
10 Thomas Hobbes argued that coercion must be relegated to government, not to private bargaining, because “covenants being but words, and breath, have no force to oblige, contain, constrain, or protect any man, but what it has from the public sword….” Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan (New York: Penguin Classics, 1982), Part Two, chapter XVIII, p. 44Google Scholar.
11 This concept of the “Best Alternative to a Negotiated Agreement,” or BATNA, comes from Fisher, Roger and Ury, William L., Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement without Giving In (Boston, MA: Penguin Books, 1981)Google Scholar.
12 This example highlights another feature of markets, one that economists call “consumer surplus.” If I am denied water, I will die. But if I am denied one opportunity to purchase water, my welfare is little affected, as long as there are other competing opportunities to purchase water. This idea that competition creates value for the consumer, in ways not reflected in prices, is called the “diamonds and water” paradox. See, e.g., Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, 31–32.
13 Turner, Sharon, The History of the Anglo-Saxons, 6th ed. (London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown, Green, and Longman, 1836), 115–16Google Scholar. Portions of this discussion are adapted from Munger, Michael, “Market Makers or Parasites?” (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, EconLib, 2009), http://www.econlib.org/library/Columns/y2009/Mungermiddlemen.htmlGoogle Scholar.
14 See, e.g., Greif, Avner, Institutions and the Path to the Modern Economy: Lessons from Medieval Trade (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
15 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 163Google Scholar.
16 Radford, R. A., “The Economic Organisation of a P.O.W. Camp,” Economica 12, no. 48 (November 1945): 189–201CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
17 Ibid., 197.
18 Aristotle makes this distinction most clearly, in arguing that value in use is different from, and superior to, value in exchange. Aristotle, , Politics, ed. Sinclair, and trans. Thomas Alan and Saunders, Trevor J. (New York: Penguin Classics, 1981), Book IGoogle Scholar. And this is precisely the origin of the “labor theory of value” that finds its way through the neoclassical economists into the work of Marx.
19 Radford, “The Economic Organisation of a POW Camp,” 198–99.
20 Bastiat, Frédéric, That Which Is Seen, and That Which Is Not Seen (Paris, 1850)Google Scholar; reprinted by Liberty Fund, http://www.econlib.org/library/Bastiat/basEss1.html, chap. 6, sec. 1.99.
21 Ibid., chap. 6.
22 This example is adapted from Munger, Michael, “They Clapped: Can Anti-Gouging Laws Prohibit Scarcity?” (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2007), http://www.econlib.org/library/Columns/y2007/Mungergouging.htmlGoogle Scholar.
23 The text of the law at the time read as follows: “(a) It shall be a violation of G.S. 75-1.1 for any person to sell or rent or offer to sell or rent at retail during a state of disaster, in the area for which the state of disaster has been declared, any merchandise or services which are consumed or used as a direct result of an emergency or which are consumed or used to preserve, protect, or sustain life, health, safety, or comfort of persons or their property with the knowledge and intent to charge a price that is unreasonably excessive under the circumstances.” The law was amended in August 2006 to be even more restrictive, outlawing price changes reflecting cost increases up the supply chain. See North Carolina SL2006-245, General Statutes 75-38. A much broader and more careful treatment of these issues can be found in Zwolinski, Matt, “The Ethics of Price Gouging,” Business Ethics Quarterly 18, no. 3 (July 2008): 347–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
24 Marx, Capital, Book I.
25 Ibid., Book I, chapter 26. Adam Smith used the phrase “previous accumulation” to refer to this phenomenon (Wealth of Nations, Book 2, chap. 3).
26 Euripides, in the Phrixus Fragment 970, said: “The gods visit the sins of the fathers upon the children.” Collard, Christopher and Cropp, Martin, trans., eds. and, Euripides: Volume VIII: Oedipus-Chrysippus, Other Fragments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Loeb Classical Library, 2009), 436Google Scholar.
27 The relation between liberalism and Marx's theory of exploitation is rather complex, and beyond my scope in this essay. But see Buchanan, Allen, “Exploitation, Alienation, and Injustice,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9, no. 1 (March 1979): 121–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Buchanan, Allen, Marx and Justice: The Radical Critique of Liberalism (London: Methuen, 1982)Google Scholar for an extensive critical review. Finally, a fascinating short story of the industrial revolution and the artistic sensibility, written by Herman Melville, asks whether it is possible for an individual simply to “prefer not” to participate in markets. Melville's character Bartleby repeatedly states that he would just rather not sell his labor, even if the alternative is to be sent to the madhouse. Melville, Herman, “Bartleby, the Scrivener: A Story of Wall Street,” Putnam's Magazine, Part I, November 1853, pp. 546–50; Part II, December 1853, pp. 609–16Google Scholar.
28 Freeman, Samuel, Rawls (New York: Routledge, 2007), 262–64Google Scholar. See also Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993)Google Scholar; Spragens, Thomas, Civic Liberalism: Reflections on Our Democratic Ideals (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999)Google Scholar; and Lomasky, Loren E., “Liberalism Beyond Borders,” Social Philosophy and Policy 24, no. 1 (2007): 206–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
29 See, e.g., Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Stigler, George, “The Theory of Economic Regulation,” Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 3 (1971): 3–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Posner, Richard A., “Theories of Economic Regulation,” Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 5 (1974): 335–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
31 See, e.g., Peltzman, Sam, “Constituent Interest and Congressional Voting,” Journal of Law and Economics 27 (1984): 181–213CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
32 Lowenfish, Lee, Branch Rickey: Baseball's Ferocious Gentleman (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 2007)Google Scholar.
33 Keynes, John Maynard, The Economic Consequences of the Peace (1919; London: General Books, 2009), 236Google Scholar.
- 31
- Cited by