Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T18:04:41.420Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Democracy, Markets, and the Legal Order: Notes on the Nature of Politics in a Radically Liberal Society*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 June 2009

Don Lavoie
Affiliation:
Economics, Center for the Study of Market Processes, George Mason University

Extract

On the extreme wing of libertarian ideology are the individualist anarchists, who wish to dispense with government altogether. The quasi-legitimate functions now performed by government, such as the administration of justice, can, the anarchists claim, be provided in the marketplace.

George H. Smith

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Smith, George H., “Justice Entrepreneurship in a Free Market,” in Atheism, Ayn Rand, and Other Heresies (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1991), p. 295.Google Scholar

2 See Sidney, Algernon, Discourses Concerning Government (1698; Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1990).Google Scholar

3 Classical liberals are well-represented throughout Eastern Europe; they include Vaclav Havel and many of Boris Yeltsin's economic advisors. But those I have particularly in mind are a number of young radical liberals I met in Warsaw, Moscow, and St. Petersburg.

4 A good example of the disillusion with democracy is expressed in Vaclav Havel's article “Paradise Lost,” New York Review of Books, 04 9, 1992.Google Scholar

5 The compromises have divided liberalism into two kinds, each of which bears little similarity to the original ideal. Some self-styled liberals favor conservative policies such as aggressive militarism; others favor socialist ones such as intrusive welfare statism. Gone is the principled opposition to government so characteristic of classical-liberal doctrine.

6 Western ideological socialism was also parasitic on really existing socialism in its notion of totality, which presumed that the standpoint of the proletariat was a kind of privileged, totalistic view of history which gave it meaning. The gradual loss of faith in this totality has meant a loss of historical meaning, and thus a collapse of the whole socialist perspective on the world. See Jay, Martin, Morxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukács to Habermas (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984).Google Scholar

7 For a concise critique of the decline of radical liberalism, see Nock, Albert Jay, “Liberalism, Properly So Called,” in The State of the Union: Essays in Social Criticism (1943; Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1991).Google Scholar

8 The next section will briefly summarize the two main correctives I believe a post-socialist liberalism needs to be built upon, pertaining to the illusions of modernism in philosophy and social engineering in economics.

9 Fukuyama, Francis, “The End of History,” The Natiotial Interest, Summer 1989, pp. 318.Google Scholar

10 See, for example, Charles Taylor's critique of atomistic liberalism in “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Rosenblum, Nancy L., ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 See Prychitko, David L., “Socialism as Cartesian Legacy: The Radical Element within Hayek's The Fatal Conceit,” Market Process, vol. 8 (1990).Google Scholar

12 On this critique of socialism and the view of markets as knowledge-conveyance and discovery mechanisms, see Hayek, F. A., ed., Collectivist Economic Planning: Critical Studies on the Possibilities of Socialism (London: George Routledge & Sons, 1935)Google Scholar; Hayek, , The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism (London: Routledge, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Lavoie, Don, Rivalry and Central Planning: The Socialist Calculation Debate Reconsidered (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985).Google Scholar For an interesting view along these lines of markets as themselves a kind of language, see Horwitz, Steven, Monetary Evolution, Free Banking, and Economic Order (Boulder: Westview Press, 1992)Google Scholar; and Horwitz, , “Monetary Exchange as an Extra-Linguistic Social Communication Process,” Review of Social Economy, forthcoming.Google Scholar

13 The chief difficulty with extending this critique of government to a radical position that seeks its elimination altogether is the well-known argument that there are certain “public goods,” such as national defense (and, many would argue, courts), which cannot be supplied adequately by the market. See Hummel, Jeffrey Rogers and Lavoie, Don, “National Defense and the Public Goods Problem,” in Higgs, Robert, ed., Anns, Politics, and the Economy: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives (New York: Holmes & Meier, 1990)Google Scholar, for a discussion that suggests that this line of argument may not necessarily establish a case for government provision.

14 For a more extensive argument along these lines, see Lavoie, Don, “Glasnost and the Knowledge Problem: Rethinking Economic Democracy,” Cato Journal, vol. 2, no. 3 (Winter 1992), pp. 435–55.Google Scholar The idea of openness has been elaborated by hermeneutical philosophy in its account of the conditions for mutual understanding in everyday life, in the humanities, and in science. See, for example, Bernstein, Richard J., Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1983)Google Scholar; Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method, revised translation by Weinsheimer, J. and Marshall, D. (1960; New York: Crossroad, 1989)Google Scholar; and Warnke, Georgia, Gadamer Hermeneutics, Tradition, and Reason (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1987).Google Scholar

15 See Arendt, Hannah, Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought (1954; New York: Penguin, 1977).Google Scholar

16 On the common law, see Hayek, F. A., Law, Legislation, and Liberty: A Neiv Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy, vol. 1, Rules and Order (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973)Google Scholar; and Hogue, Arthur R., Origins of the Common Law (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1966).Google Scholar

17 See Habermas, Jürgen, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston: Beacon Press, 1984)Google Scholar, and vol. 2, Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason (Boston: Beacon Press, 1987).Google Scholar For a particularly stark presentation of this image of markets as impersonal, see Anderson, Elizabeth, “The Ethical Limitations of the Market,” Economics and Philosophy, vol. 6 (1990), pp. 179205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 See Lomasky, Loren E., “Duty Call,” Reason, 04 1992, p. 51.Google Scholar

19 For examples of analyses of economic phenomena that take culture seriously, see Douglas, Mary and Isherwood, Baron, The world of Goods: Towards an Anthropology of Consumption (London: Allen Lane, 1979)Google Scholar; and Simmel, Georg, Essays on Interpretation in Social Science, translated, edited, and introduced by Oakes, G. (1907; Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield, 1978).Google Scholar Even writings in the Austrian school, although far less guilty of this modernist vice than neoclassical economics, evidence an acultural view of human agents. See, for example, my critique of Israel Kirzner along these lines in “The Discovery and Interpretation of Profit Opportunities: Culture and the Kirznerian Entrepreneur,” in Berger, Brigitte, ed., The Culture of Entrepreneurship (San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies, 1991).Google Scholar

20 The postmodern liberalism that is occasionally being presented in the pages of the journal Critical Review is beginning to correct for this atomistic element in traditional liberalism. See also Madison, G. B., The Logic of Liberty (New York: Greenwood Press, 1986)Google Scholar, and Madison, , “Getting Beyond Objectivism: The Philosophical Hermcneutics of Gadamer and Ricoeur,” in Lavoie, Don, ed., Economics and Hermeneutics (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 3458.Google Scholar

21 Rothbard, Murray N., For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1973).Google Scholar

22 Friedman, David, The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism (New York: Harper & Row, 1973).Google Scholar

23 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974).Google Scholar

24 Hospers, John, “Will Rothbard's Free-Market Justice Suffice? No,” Reason, 05 1973, pp. 1823.Google Scholar

25 I think that this anarchist policy conclusion is more reasonable than it must appear to most readers; however, I find the atomistic individualist perspective in which it is couched by Rothbard and Friedman unacceptable. This notion of free-market anarchism has to be distinguished, of course, from traditional left-wing anarchism, which does not necessarily share its hyper-individualism, but which has other serious problems. On left-wing anarchism, see Bakunin, Michael, “Statism and Anarchy,” in Dolgoff, Sam, ed., Bakunin on Anarchy (1873; New York: Vintage, 1971)Google Scholar; and Shatz, Marshall S., ed., The Essential Works of Anarchism (New York: Bantam, 1971).Google Scholar

26 The study by Benson, Bruce L., The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the State (San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990)Google Scholar, raises the scholarly level of debate considerably above that of the Rothbard and Friedman polemics. It persuades me that a free-market anarchist society would be workable, at least under certain plausible cultural conditions; but I think it will convince very few readers, mainly because the cultural preconditions are not discussed. Free-market anarchism remains unpersuasive to most people not primarily because of any shortcomings of the arguments its proponents make, but because of shortcomings of our background notions of markets and democracy. Behind the objections most people have to the anarchist position is a fear that it would rob us of a deeply cherished value, democracy. In my own view, a radically market-oriented society with a severely limited or perhaps even abolished government could turn out to be a more “democratic” kind of system, properly understood, than the Western-style democracies we are used to.

27 The term “ideology” is misleading here, since we are not interested in articulated systems of ideas but rather in the sorts of tacit beliefs that inform concrete practices.

28 Rothbard, Murray, “Will Rothbard's Free-Market Justice Suffice? Yes,” Reason, 05 1973, pp. 1925.Google Scholar

29 Covven, Tyler, “Law as a Public Good: The Economics of Anarchy,” unpublished manuscript, George Mason University, 1991.Google Scholar

30 Indeed, this may be giving these authors too much credit. Political discourse presupposes an open exploration of issues of mutual concern. It seems that for Rothbard and his followers, genuine political discourse is not even needed in order to get to the free society. Instead, it seems there needs to be what is essentially a religious-conversion experience. The definition of rights is not open to exploratory dialogue but presumed to have been accomplished once and for all in Rothbard, 's Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1982).Google Scholar