Article contents
An Uneasy Case against Property Rights in Body Parts*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 18 June 2009
Extract
This essay deals with property rights in body parts that can be exchanged in a market. The inquiry arises in the following context. With some exceptions, the laws of many countries permit only the donation, not the sale, of body parts. Yet for some years there has existed a shortage of body parts for transplantation and other medical uses. It might then appear that if more sales were legally permitted, the supply of body parts would increase, because people would have more incentive to sell than they currently have to donate. To allow sales is to recognize property rights in body parts. To allow sales, however, makes body parts into “commodities”—that is, things that can be bought and sold in a market. And some view it as morally objectionable to treat body parts as commodities.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1994
References
1 Munzer, Stephen R., A Theory of Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 55–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2 Munzer, Stephen R., “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, vol. 6, no. 2 (07 1993), pp. 319–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3 See, for example, Boyce, Richard Michael, “Organ Transplantation Crisis: Should the Deficit Be Eliminated Through Inter Vivos Sales?” Akron Law Review, vol. 17, no. 2 (Fall 1983), pp. 283–302Google ScholarPubMed; Brams, Marvin, “Transplantable Human Organs: Should Their Sale Be Authorized by State Statutes?” American Journal of Law & Medicine, vol. 3, no. 2 (Summer 1977), pp. 183–95Google ScholarPubMed; Hylton, Keith N., “The Law and Economics of Organ Procurement,” Law & Policy, vol. 12, no. 3 (07 1990), pp. 197–224CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; and Perry, Clifton, “Human Organs and the Open Market,” Ethics, vol. 91, no. 1 (10 1980), pp. 63–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
4 Cohen, Lloyd R., “Increasing the Supply of Transplant Organs: The Virtues of a Futures Market,” George Washington Law Review, vol. 58, no. 1 (11 1989), pp. 1–51.Google ScholarPubMed
5 Hansmann, Henry, “The Economics and Ethics of Markets for Human Organs,” Journal of Health Politics, Policy, and Law, vol. 14, no. 1 (Spring 1989), pp. 57–85.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
6 Ibid., pp. 74–78.
7 Chadwick, Ruth F., “The Market for Bodily Parts: Kant and Duties to Oneself,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, vol. 6, no. 2 (1989), pp. 129–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8 Ibid., p. 137 (“one undesirable consequence …” and “dire consequences for society's values …”).
9 Kass, Leon R., “Organs for Sale? Propriety, Property, and the Price of Progress,” The Public Interest, no. 107 (Spring 1992), pp. 65–86.Google Scholar
10 Ibid., pp. 81–83.
11 Radin, Margaret Jane, “Reflections on Objectification,” Southern California law Review, vol. 65, no. 1 (11 1991), pp. 341–54Google ScholarPubMed; see esp. pp. 345, 347, 351.
12 Radin, Margaret jane, “Property and Personhood,” Stanford Law Review, vol. 34, no. 5 (05 1982), pp. 957–1015, at p. 960.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13 Ibid., p. 960.
14 Ibid., p. 978.
15 Ibid., pp. 971–78, 984–1013.I leave aside the question of whether a sophisticated rule utilitarian could draw a similar distinction. For a powerful interpretation and development of Hegel's views on property, see Waldron, Jeremy, The Right to Private Property (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), ch. 10.Google Scholar
16 See Radin, , “Property and Personhood,” pp. 968–70, 987–88.Google Scholar
17 For a different account of the interconnections between persons and property, and varied justificatory arguments for property based on different conceptions of persons, see Munzer, , A Theory of Property, chs. 3–11.Google Scholar
18 Radin, Margaret Jane, “Market-Inalienability,” Harvard Law Review, vol. 100, no. 8 (06 1987), pp. 1849–1937CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For change in her views over time, see Radin, Margaret Jane, “Lacking a Transformative Social Theory: A Response,” Stanford Law Review, vol. 45, no. 2 (01 1993), pp. 409–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see esp. pp. 422–24.
19 Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” pp. 1851, 1859–1909, 1936.Google Scholar
20 Ibid., pp. 1921–36.
21 Radin, , “Property and Personhood,” p. 966Google Scholar; Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” p. 1924 n. 261Google Scholar; and Radin, , “Reflections on Objectification,” pp. 342, 347, 351.Google Scholar
22 Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” p. 1852 n. 11.Google Scholar
23 Ibid., pp. 1852 n. 11,1909 and n. 222.
25 Ibid., p. 1882.
26 Radin, , “Property and Personhood,” p. 966 (footnote omitted).Google Scholar
27 Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” p. 1897 (footnote omitted).Google Scholar
28 Cf. Ibid., p. 1897 n. 179.
29 Radin, , “Reflections on Objectification,” pp. 345, 347, 351.Google Scholar
30 In fact, Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” pp. 1891–94, 1896–98Google Scholar, criticizes Kant for distinguishing between persons and things.
31 Ibid., p. 1882.
32 Ibid., pp. 1903–9, 1937.
33 Radin, , “Reflections on Objectification,” p. 345 (footnote omitted).Google Scholar
34 Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals [1785], trans. Paton, H. J. as The Moral Law (London: Hutchinson University Library, 1948), pp. 96–97.Google Scholar
35 See, for example, ibid., pp. 96–97; Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals [1797], trans. Gregor, Mary (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 216–17, 230–31, 254–55.Google Scholar
36 See, for example, Kant, Immanuel, Lectures on Ethics [1775–80], trans. Infield, Louis and foreword by Beck, Lewis White (Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, 1963), pp. 196–97.Google Scholar
37 Kant, , Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, p. 97.Google Scholar
38 Ibid., pp. 96, 97.
39 For a sensitive exposition and use of Kant's views on dignity, see Hill, Thomas E. Jr., Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Ethical Theory (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1992), pp. 10, 47–50, 56, 166–67, 178, 202–17, 246–47.Google Scholar
40 Kant, , Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, pp. 97–98.Google Scholar
41 Ibid., pp. 98–100.
42 See Hill, , Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Ethical Theory, pp. 178, 208–9, 246–47Google Scholar, as well as Hill's general treatment of the “kingdom of ends” on pp. 58–66.Google Scholar
43 James Tully suggested to me this way of looking at Kant's position.
44 See Pufendorf, Samuel, De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo (The Law of Nature and Nations in Eight Books) [1672], vol. 1, Latin text of 1688; vol. 2, trans. , C. H. and Oldfather, W. A. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, and London: Humphrey Milford, 1934), bk. 3, ch. 2, sections 1–9Google Scholar. Pufendorf almost always uses the terms aequalitas, aequalitas naturalis, aequalitas juris (“equality,” “natural equality,” “equality of right”) rather than dignatio (“dignity”). See also Berger, Peter, “On the Obsolescence of the Concept of Honor,” in Revisions: Changing Perspectives in Moral Philosophy, ed. Hauerwas, Stanley and Maclntyre, Alasdair (Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 172–81Google Scholar; Taylor, Charles. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modem Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), pp. 16, 20, 23, 25, 44, 65, 83–84, 94, 152–55, 214, 285, 365, 450Google Scholar; and Tully, James, “Introduction,”Google Scholar in Pufendorf, Samuel, On the Duty of Man and Citizen According to Natural Law [1673], ed. Tully, James and trans. Silverthome, Michael (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. xxvi.Google Scholar
45 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan [1651], ed. Smith, W. G. Pogson (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1909), pt. 1, ch. 10, p. 67Google Scholar. Actually, a willing buyer and a willing seller would jointly determine the price.
46 Munzer, , “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts”Google Scholar (supra note 2) surveys the stronger pronouncements and suggests ways of using Kant's general moral theory to soften them.
47 Kant, , Lectures on Ethics, p. 166Google Scholar (emphasis added); cf. ibid., pp. 147–48.
48 Kant, , The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 219.Google Scholar
49 For a more careful textual reconstruction of this and other Kantian arguments, see Munzer, , “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts.”Google Scholar
50 Kant, , The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 219.Google Scholar
51 Scott, Russell, The Body as Property (New York: Viking Press, 1981), pp. 222–23Google Scholar, mentions a testicle transplant between identical twins.
52 Radin, , “Market-Inalienability” (supra note 18), pp. 1903–9Google Scholar; Radin, , “Lacking a Transformative Social Theory: A Response” (supra note 18), pp. 409–10Google Scholar and n. 2, 414 and n. 18,422 n. 43.
53 Munzer, , “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts,” p. 10 and n. 17.Google Scholar
54 See Waldron, Jeremy, “A Right to Do Wrong,” Ethics, vol. 92 (10 1981), pp. 21–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
55 Kant seems to oscillate on this point. In one passage he says that “everything has either a price or a dignity.” Kant, , Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, p. 96Google Scholar (emphasis omitted). In another work he writes that man regarded as a natural being can have a “price” even while, regarded as a “person,” he has a “dignity.” Kant, , The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 230 (emphasis omitted).Google Scholar
56 Cf. Waker, Michael, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books, 1983), ch. 4.Google Scholar
57 Kant, , Lectures on Ethics, p. 124Google Scholar. But see ibid., pp. 196–97.
58 See Hampton, Jean, “Forgiveness, Resentment, and Hatred,” in Jeffrie G. Murphy and Jean Hampton, Forgiveness and Mercy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 35–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Her chapter offers a fuller discussion of the varieties of human worth than can be attempted here.
59 See Munzer, , “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts,” pp. 10–12.Google Scholar
60 Ibid., p. 4.
61 Kant, , Lectures on Ethics, p. 165Google Scholar. See also Munzer, , “Kant and Property Rights in Body Parts,” pp. 7, 8–10.Google Scholar
62 See, for example, Wallace, Charles P., “For Sale: The Poor's Body Parts,” Los Angeles Times, 08 27, 1992, p. A1.Google Scholar
63 Marx, Karl, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, ed. Struik, Dirk J. (New York: International Publishers, 1964), p. 119Google Scholar. Cf. Munzer, , A Theory of Property (supra note 1), pp. 158, 177–78.Google Scholar
64 See, for example, Klammer, Arjo, McCloskey, Donald N., and Solow, Robert M., eds., The Consequences of Economic Rhetoric (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).Google Scholar
65 “The Laws of Æthelberht,” cap. 34–72Google Scholar, in The Laws of the Earliest English Kings, ed. and trans. Attenborough, F. L. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1922), pp. 8–15.Google Scholar
66 Ibid., cap. 37, 40, 43–50, 54, 56, 65–66, pp. 8–13.
67 “The Laws of Alfred,” cap. 44–77, in ibid., pp. 86–93.
68 Ibid., cap. 46–47, pp. 86–87. The standard text for Anglo-Saxon laws from 600 a.d. until the Norman Conquest in 1066 a.d. remains Liebermann, F., Die Gesetze der Angelsachsen, 3 vols. (Halle am Saale: Max Niemeyer, 1903–1916).Google Scholar
69 Calabresi, Guido and Melamed, A. Douglas, “Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral,” Harvard Law Review, vol. 85, no. 6 (04 1972), pp. 1089–1128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
70 Workers, ' Compensation Law, in McKinney's Consolidated Laws of New York Annotated (St. Paul, MM: West, 1993), Book 64, section 15(3), pp. 5–6.Google Scholar
71 Abel, Richard L., “A Critique of Torts,” UCLA Law Review, vol. 37, no. 5 (06 1990), pp. 785–831, at p. 790 (footnote omitted).Google Scholar
72 Ibid., pp. 808–9 (footnote omitted):
Economists cannot tell us the value of bodily integrity, emotional well-being, or life because these are not defined by the market. The costs of accidents can only be determined collectively—after the fact by a judge or jury, or before by a legislature or regulatory agency.
73 Ibid., pp. 790, 820.
- 30
- Cited by