Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T23:14:30.880Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

UNDERSTANDING NORMS AND CHANGING THEM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 December 2018

Ryan Muldoon*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University at Buffalo

Abstract:

It is crucial for policymakers to focus their attention on social norms if they want to improve policy outcomes, but doing so brings in new normative questions about the appropriate role of the state. Indeed, I argue that efforts to reduce coercion at the state level can create potentially pernicious and difficult to eliminate forms of coercion at the informal level. This creates a new normative challenge for thinking about the broader regulatory apparatus, and complicates our approach in utilizing social norms for democratic policy ends. I will distinguish between two forms of social norms orientations in policy: a diagnostic approach and a design approach. We will see that the diagnostic approach better models a Humean approach to supporting social norms, and a design approach has a more Millian character. While it is easier to justify a design approach in the abstract, as it has very little room for abuses of state authority, if Mill is right that social norms can be a source of coercive power that runs afoul of the harm principle, then a design approach will sometimes be necessary to counter this form of tyranny. However, this latter approach is complex, and as such we may want to take a recommendation from Mockus to focus on deliberative approaches to norm change.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Thaler, Richard and Sunstein, Cass, Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth and Happiness (New York: Penguin Books, 2009)Google Scholar

2 Lessig, Lawrence, “The Regulation of Social Meaning,” University of Chicago Law Review 62 (1995): 943.Google Scholar

3 For a detailed review of several of the most prominent accounts of social norms, see Bicchieri, Cristina and Muldoon, Ryan, “Social Norms,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N. (Spring, 2014), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/social-norms/>.Google Scholar

4 Bicchieri, Cristina, The Grammar of Society (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006).Google Scholar The Grammar of Society is a book-length examination of the nature and structure of social norms. Bicchieri’s Norms in the Wild (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016) is more focused on the policy consequences of the definition, along with a detailed account of how norms can be measured and how they can be changed. Much of this essay is inspired by Bicchieri’s approach.

5 See Michael P. Haines, “A Social Norms Approach to Binge Drinking at Colleges and Universities,” The Higher Education Center for Alcohol and Other Drug Prevention; Perkins, H. Wesley, “Social Norms and the Prevention of Alcohol Misuse in Collegiate Contexts,” Journal of Studies on Alcohol and Drugs 14 (2002): 164.Google Scholar

6 Hans Christian Anderson’s The Emperor’s New Clothes is an exemplary account of pluralistic ignorance in a fictional context.

7 Alesina, Alberto, Giuliano, Paola, and Nunn, Nathan, “On the Origins of Gender Roles: Women and the Plough,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 128, no. 2 (2013): 469530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 This process follows analytically from Bicchieri’s definition of norms in The Grammar of Society.

9 Bicchieri, Norms in the Wild.

10 Importantly, social norms can also cause people to fail to exhibit certain behaviors: norms may dictate that individuals should not trust people outside of the group, for instance. Norms can likewise be so onerous that people avoid putting themselves in certain situations, to avoid triggering the obligations that a norm might impose: earning more money than one immediately needs may obligate the earner to loan or give her excess money to extended family or friends who have less. Accepting help or a gift may trigger an obligation to reciprocate even more generously. These norms can be powerful, even if we never see their prescribed behavior. Norms can also proscribe behavior: anti-corruption norms will mean that we systematically would not see public officials accept bribes.

11 Gneezy, Uri and Rustichini, Aldo, “A Fine is a Price,” Journal of Legal Studies 29, no. 1 (2000).Google Scholar

12 Allcott, Hunt, “Social Norms and Energy Conservation,” Journal of Public Economics 95, no. 9 (2011): 10821095.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Interestingly, some of the variation in power savings appears to be explained by ideological affiliation. Liberals were more likely to conserve, and conservatives were more likely to be bothered by the attempt at invoking a norm. Costa, Dora L. and Kahn, Matthew E., “Energy Conservation “Nudges” and Environmentalist Ideology: Evidence from a Randomized Residential Electricity Field Experiment,” Journal of the European Economic Association 11, no. 3 (2013): 680702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 Christakis, Nicholas and Fowler, James, “The Spread of Obesity in a Large Social Network over 32 Years,” The New England Journal of Medicine 357 (2007): 370–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edition, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978 [1896]), 60.Google Scholar

15 Hume, Treatise, 70–71.

16 Hume, Treatise, 70.

17 Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty (New York: Hackett, 1978), 4.Google Scholar

18 Ibid.

19 Lessig, Lawrence, “The Regulation of Social Meaning,” University of Chicago Law Review 62 (1995): 9431045.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Bicchieri, Norms in the Wild.