Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T03:03:25.741Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Idea of a Life Plan

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2009

Charles Larmore
Affiliation:
Philosophy, University of Chicago

Extract

When philosophers undertake to say what it is that makes life worth living, they generally display a procrustean habit of thought which the practice of philosophy itself does much to encourage. As a result, they arrive at an image of the human good that is far more controversial than they suspect. The canonical view among philosophers ancient and modern has been, in essence, that the life lived well is the life lived in accord with a rational plan. To me this conception of the human good seems manifestly wrong. The idea that life should be the object of a plan is false to the human condition. It misses the important truth which Proust, by contrast, discerned and made into one of the organizing themes of his great meditation on disappointment and revelation, A la recherche du temps perdu: The happiness that life affords is less often the good we have reason to pursue than the good that befalls us unexpectedly.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Proust, Marcel, Albertine Disparue (Paris: Gallimard/Folio, 1992), p. 83Google Scholar. “In exchange for what our imagination leads us to expect and which we vainly give ourselves so much trouble to try to discover, life gives us something which we were very far from imagining.”

2 Johnson, Samuel, The History of Rasselas, Prince of Abissinia (1759; London: Penguin, 1976), ch. 16.Google Scholar

3 This is the theme of Nussbaum, Martha's magnificent book The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).Google Scholar

4 In this essay I elaborate a thesis which I first sketched in The Romantic Legacy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 95.Google Scholar

5 Cf. Taylor, Charles's idea of “strong evaluation” in “What Is Human Agency?”Google Scholar in Taylor, , Philosophical Papers, vol. I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 1544.Google Scholar

6 See in particular Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), section 63.Google Scholar

7 Plato, , Apology, 38a.Google Scholar

8 Williams, Bernard, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 4, 19.Google Scholar

9 Plato, , Republic, 618cGoogle Scholar. The Myth of Er describes an afterworld where souls, who are about to be reborn, choose the sort of life which they will lead.

10 Aristotle, , Eudemian Ethics, trans. Woods, Michael (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), Book 1, ch. 2, 1214b7–13.Google Scholar

11 Cooper, John M., Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975), p. 125.Google Scholar

12 For elements of a bibliography, see Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), pp. 129–30.Google Scholar

13 I shall be examining Rawls's notion of a rational life plan as an overall moral ideal, abstracting from the political role he gives it in A Theory of justice. In later writings, Rawls has said that he wishes that notion, along with the associated account of goodness as rationality, to be understood simply as part of a political conception, and not as an element of a comprehensive moral doctrine (Rawls, , Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], pp. 176–77n.)Google Scholar. I am unsure whether my criticisms touch the more circumscribed status he now assigns to the idea of a life plan, or whether, more generally, they have an important bearing on the foundations of a liberal theory of justice. Here I am pursuing a topic in ethics, and my reason for taking Rawls's views out of their political context is that they constitute by far the most powerful statement of the outlook I mean to question.

14 Royce, Josiah, The Philosophy of Loyalty (New York: Macmillan, 1908), p. 168.Google Scholar

15 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice, p. 408; see also pp. 421, 424.Google Scholar

16 Ibid., pp. 93, 409, 548–60.

17 Ibid., p. 399.

18 Ibid., p. 408. More exactly, a person's plan is “subjectively rational” if it is based on an accurate conception of his existing wants and the available knowledge concerning the consequences of his actions; it is also “objectively rational” if the future actually goes as he supposes (pp. 417, 422).

19 Ibid., pp. 416–17.

20 See ibid., p. 420.

21 Ibid., p. 422. A rational person, Rawls there observes, “does what seems best at the time, and if his beliefs later prove to be mistaken with untoward results, it is through no fault of his own. There is n o cause for self-reproach.”

22 A fine development of this objection is to be found in Slote, Michael, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), chs. 1 and 2.Google Scholar

23 Cf. Nozick, Robert's reflections on the “narrative direction” of the happy life, in The Examined Life (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1989), pp. 100102.Google Scholar

24 In his presentation of the objection just described, Slote introduces some interesting criticisms of this assumption as well (Goods and Virtues, pp. 4345)Google Scholar. There is also a very suggestive critique of this assumption in Seel, Martin, Versuch über die Form des Glücks (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1996), pp. 102–13.Google Scholar

25 Williams, Bernard, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

26 I develop the point somewhat in The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), particularly in ch. 2.Google Scholar

27 Williams, Bernard, Making Sense of Humanity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 170CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Williams, , Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, pp. 6769.Google Scholar

28 For further reflections along these lines, see my “Denken urtd Handeln,” Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, vol. 45, no. 2 (1997), pp. 183–95.Google Scholar

29 Williams, , Moral Luck, pp. 3436.Google Scholar

30 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice, p. 407.Google Scholar

31 See Elster, Jon, Sour Grapes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), ch. 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice, p. 423.Google Scholar