Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T14:26:54.574Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

XI. Emotion, Weakness of Will, and the Normative Conception of Agency1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

Empirical work on and common observation of the emotions tells us that our emotions sometimes key us to the presence of real and important reason-giving considerations without necessarily presenting that information to us in a way susceptible of conscious articulation and, sometimes, even despite our consciously held and internally justified judgment that the situation contains no such reasons. In this paper, I want to explore the implications of the fact that emotions show varying degrees of integration with our conscious agency—from none at all to quite substantial—for our understanding of our rationality, and in particular for the traditional assumption that weakness of the will is necessarily irrational.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Antony, Louise. 1993. ‘Quine as Feminist: The Radical Import of Naturalized Epistemology’, In Louise, Antony and Charlotte, Witt (eds) A Mind of One's Own (Bolder, Co: Westview Press).Google Scholar
Antony, Louise. 2000. ‘Naturalised Epistemology, Morality, and the Real World’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 26, 103–37.Google Scholar
Arpaly, Nomi. 2000. ‘On Acting Rationally Against One's Best Judgement’, Ethics 110, 488513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Jonathan. 1974. ‘The Conscience of Huckleberry Finn’, Philosophy 49, 123–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, Richard. 1983. ‘On the current status of the issue of scientific realism’, Erkenntnis 19, 4590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R.Gasper, P. and Trout, J. D. (eds). 1991. The Philosophy of Science (MIT Press: Cambridge).Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1996. ‘Our Entitlement to Self-Knowledge’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96, 91116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. 1984. ‘Cognitive Emotions?’ In Calhoun, and Solomon, 1984, 327–42.Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. 1989. ‘Subjectivity and Emotion’, The Philosophical Forum, Vol. 10, 195210.Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire, and Robert, Solomon, (eds), 1984. What is an Emotion? Classic Readings in Philosophical Psychology (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Descartes, Rene. 1985[1649]. The Passions of the Soul. In John, Cottingham, Robert, Stoothoff and Dugald, Murdoch (trans.) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes Vol. 1. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
de Sousa, Ronald. 1979. ‘The Rationality of Emotions’, In Rorty, 1980, 127–52.Google Scholar
de Sousa, Ronald. 1987. The Rationality of Emotion (Cambridge: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1999. Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Frank, Robert. 1988. Passions within Reason (New York: Norton).Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd, Todd, Peter and the ABC Research Group. 1999. Simple Heuristics that Make us Smart (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Greenspan, Patricia S. 1988. Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Jaggar, Allison. 1996. ‘Love and Knowledge: Emotion in Feminist Epistemology’, In Ann, Garry and Marilyn, Pearsall (eds), Women, Knowledge, and Reality. Second Edition. (New York: Routledge), 166190.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 1997. ‘The Normativity of Instrumental Reason’, In Garret, Cullity and Berys, Gaut (eds) Ethics and Practical Reason. (Oxford: Claredon Press).Google Scholar
Le Doux, Joseph. 1996. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life (New York: Simon and Schuster).Google Scholar
Moran, Richard. 1988. ‘Making Up Your Mind: Self-Interpretation and Self-Constitution’, Ratio, n.s. 1, 135–51.Google Scholar
Owen, David, n.d. ‘The Authority of Practical Judgement’.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2000. ‘When we are ourselves: the active and the passive’, In his, Engaging Reason (Oxford: OUP), 521.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Scheman, Naomi. 1980. ‘Anger and the politics of naming’, In Sally, McConell-Ginet, Ruth, Borker and Nellie, Furman (eds) Women and Language in Literature and Society (New York: Praeger), 174–87.Google Scholar
Schroeter, Francois. 2001. ‘Normative Concepts and Motivation’.Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert C. 1973. ‘Emotions and Choice’, In Rorty, 1980, 251–81.Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert C. 1976. The Passions (Garden City, New York: Anchor/Doubleday Press).Google Scholar
Stein, Edward. 1996. Without Good Reason (Oxford: The Claredon Press).Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael with Elizabeth, Hegeman. 1996. Valuing Emotions (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay 1999. ‘Three Conceptions of Rational Agency’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2, 217–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, Gary. 1975. ‘Free Agency.” Journal of Philosophy 72, 205–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1980. ‘Internal and External Reasons’, In his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980, 101–13. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1981.Google Scholar