Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T16:14:00.580Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Volunteers and Conscripts: Philippa Foot and the Amoralist

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2020

Nakul Krishna*
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge

Abstract

Philippa Foot, like others of her philosophical generation, was much concerned with the status and authority of morality. How universal are its demands, and how dependent on the idiosyncrasies of individuals? In the early years of her career, she was persuaded that Kant and his twentieth-century followers had been wrong to insist on the centrality to morality of absolute and unconditionally binding moral imperatives. To that extent, she wrote, there was indeed ‘an element of deception in the official line about morality’. In this paper, I shall explore her early alternative: a system of merely ‘hypothetical’ imperatives, imperatives that depend on the motivations of particular individuals. Could so contingent a system deserve to be termed a morality? How revisionary a proposal was this, and how serious its costs? And how might we reconcile ourselves to a morality stripped of what she called the ‘fictions’ that surrounded it? Foot's early answer, tentative and exploratory, remains of interest, long after she herself abandoned it.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Murdoch, Iris, Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Literature (London: Penguin Books, 1999), 73Google Scholar.

2 Foot, Philippa, ‘Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives’, in Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 167Google Scholar

3 Op. cit. note 2, 159.

4 Op. cit. note 2, 165.

5 Op. cit. note 2, 166.

6 Op. cit. note 2, 174.

7 Op. cit. note 2, 167; emphasis in original.

8 Op. cit. note 2, 167.

9 The quotation is from her interview with Alex Voorhoeve in Alex Voorhoeve, Conversations on Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 102.

10 Op. cit. note 9, 102.

11 Op. cit. note 9, 101; ‘brash’ is her word.

12 Op. cit. not 9, 92.

13 The phrase is from Wiggins, David, ‘A Sensible Subjectivism?’, in Needs, Values, Truth (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), 185215Google Scholar.

14 For a useful general discussion of these figures, see Barney, Rachel, ‘Socrates’ Refutation of Thrasymachus’, in The Blackwell Guide to Plato's Republic, ed. Santas, Gerasimos Xenophon (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2006), 4462Google Scholar; also, Williams, Bernard, ‘Plato Against the Immoralist’, in The Sense of the Past: Essays in the History of Philosophy, ed. Burnyeat, Myles (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009), 97107CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 For a thorough and insightful introduction to the history of the problem, see Hills, Alison, The Beloved Self: Morality and the Challenge From Egoism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Williams, Bernard, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972), 4Google Scholar.

17 Bernard Williams, ‘Fictions, Philosophy, and Truth’, Profession, 1 January 2003, 40.

18 This point about the modern self is put memorably, and satirically,  by William James in section VII of his lecture, ‘The Will to Believe’: ‘… he who says, “Better go without belief forever than believe a lie!” merely shows his own preponderant private horror of becoming a dupe. He may be critical of many of his desires and fears, but this fear he slavishly obeys'.

19 For a classic (and underappreciated) discussion of these difficulties, see Locke, Don, ‘The Trivializability of Universalizability’, The Philosophical Review 77, no. 1 (1968): 2544Google Scholar.

20 Op. cit. note 16, 10.

21 Op. cit. note 16, 11

22 Op. cit. note 16, 11.

23 Williams, Bernard, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (With a Commentary on the Text by A. W. Moore), Reissue (Abingdon: Routledge, 2006/1985), 26Google Scholar

24 I borrow the term ‘mitigation’ from Button, Tim, The Limits of Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 161CrossRefGoogle Scholar and passim, who uses it in connection with questions of metaphysical realism.

25 Nietzche's notorious remarks in Twilight of the Idols about English moral thinkers are relevant here: ‘They have got rid of the Christian God, and now think that they have to hold on to Christian morality more than ever […] In England, every time you take one small step towards emancipation from theology you have to reinvent yourself as a moral fanatic in the most awe-inspiring way'. (Nietzsche, Friedrich, Nietzsche: The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols: And Other Writings, ed. Ridley, Aaron and Norman, Judith, trans. Norman, Judith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 193–4Google Scholar.

26 Op. cit. note 2, 167.

27 Op. cit. note 2, 167.

28 Op. cit. note 2, 167.

29 A harrowing recent work of scholarship on the siege, Peri, Alexis, The War Within: Diaries from the Siege of Leningrad (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, recounts these stories and others yet worse.

30 Op. cit, note 16, 9.

31 Op. cit. note 2, 167.

32 For a classic discussion, see Herman, Barbara, ‘On the Value of Acting from the Motive of Duty’, The Philosophical Review 90, no. 3 (1981): 359–82Google Scholar.

33 For a wide-ranging and profound discussion of the contrast and affinities between these ways of conceiving of morality, see Murdoch, Iris, ‘Vision and Choice in Morality’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: Dreams and Self-Knowledge Supplement no. 30 (1956): 3258Google Scholar.

34 See Hare, R. M., ‘A Philosophical Autobiography’, Utilitas 14, no. 3 (November 2002): 269305CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Mehta, Ved, Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounters with Contemporary British Intellectuals (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1963), 4657Google Scholar and passim.

35 See Hare, R. M., The Language of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952)Google Scholar.

36 See Hare, R. M., Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963)Google Scholar.

37 Op. cit. note 34, 111.

38 Op. cit. note 34.

39 For an ingenious recent argument in this vein, see Hayward, Max Khan, ‘Immoral Realism’, Philosophical Studies 176, no. 4 (2019): 897914CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Similarly, see these remarks by Amia Srinivasan, whose first sentence nicely echoes Foot's own motivations for her adoption of a kind of ethical realism: ‘Those who think that Realism is the only morally sound meta-ethics are often motivated by the belief that the most important thing is to be able to condemn atrocities as always and everywhere wrong. Anti-Realists prefer to think that people are ultimately answerable, not to abstract principles or divine commands, but to each other. We should take this view seriously […] because it is ethically attractive in its own right'. (Amia Srinivasan, ‘In the Long Cool Hour’, London Review of Books, 6 December 2012.)

40 For a useful discussion of the growing pessimism in Williams's thought on these matters, see Sagar, Paul, ‘Minding the Gap: Bernard Williams and David Hume on Living an Ethical Life’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 11, no. 5 (24 September 2014): 615–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar.