Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T16:14:00.394Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
References
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle, . 1972. De Partibus Animalium, trans. Balme, D. F.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1984. Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Barnes, J. after Ross. Princeton: Princeton University Press, Berlin: Becker.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1923. Confessions, trans. Matthew, R., ed. Huddleston, R.. London: Burns & Oates.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1968. The Teacher, The Free Choice of the Will and Grace and Free Will, trans. Russell, R. P.. Washington: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Bacharach, M. and Hurley, S. 1991. Foundations of Decision Theory: Issues and Advances. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Barry, B. 1989. Theories of Justice. London: HarvesterWheatsheaf.Google Scholar
Bartky, S. 1990. ‘Feminine Masochism and the Politics of Personal Transformation’, in Femininity and Domination. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Berlin, I. 1980. ‘From Hope and Fear Set Free’, in Concepts and Categories. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bernard, C. 1949. Introduction to the Study of Experimental Medicine, trans. Greene, H. C.. New York: Shuman.Google Scholar
Blair, H ugh. 1801. Sermons: To which is annexed a short account of the life and character of the author, by James Finlayson. 5 vols. Edinburgh: Wm. Creech; London: W. Strachan and T. Cadell; 1797‐1801.Google Scholar
Blake, W. 1966. Complete Works, ed. Keynes, G.. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blish, J. 1968. Black Easter. London: Faber.Google Scholar
Blish, J. 1974. The Day after Judgment. Harmondsworth: Penguin (1st publ. by Faber, 1972).Google Scholar
Bock, P. 1969. Modern Cultural Anthropology. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Boethius, 1973. Tractates and Consolation of Philosophy, trans. Stewart, H. F., Rand, E. K. and Tester, S. J.. London: Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library.Google Scholar
Brandt, R. B. 1959. Ethical Theory. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice‐Hall.Google Scholar
Brandt, R. B. 1979. A Theory of the Good and the Right. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Brink, D. 1989. Moral Realism dnd the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnet, J. (ed.) 1900. The Ethics of Aristotle. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Campbell, T. 1975. ‘Perfect and Imperfect Duties’, The Modern Schoolman, 102, 195‐204.Google Scholar
Carritt, E. F. 1935. Morals & Politics: Theories of their relation from Hobbes and Spinoza to Marx and Bosanquet. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Carritt, E. F. 1947. Ethical and Political Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Castell, A. 1954. An Elementary Ethics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice‐Hall.Google Scholar
Chandrasekhar, S. 1987. Truth and Beauty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Chesterton, G. K. 1961. Orthodoxy. London: Fontana (1st publ. 1908).Google Scholar
Chroust, A. (ed.) 1964. Aristotle's Protrepticus: A Reconstruction. Indiana: University of Notre Dame press.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. 1985. ‘Slaves and citizens’,Philosophy 60, 27‐46.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. 1990. A Parliament of Souls. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. 1993. ‘Natural Goods and Moral Beauty’, in Knowles, D. and Skorupski, J. (eds) 1993. Virtue and Taste, Essays in Memory of Flint Schier. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. 1992. ‘Incentives, Inequality and Community’, in Petersen, 1992.Google Scholar
Cohen, J. 1989. ‘On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice’, Ethics, 99.Google Scholar
Copp, D. and Zimmerman, D. (eds.) Morality, Reason and Truth. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Allanheld.Google Scholar
Craig, E. J. 1990, Knowledge and the State of Nature. Oxford: ????Google Scholar
Dancy, R. M. (ed.) 1993. Kant and Critique. London: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Daniels, N. 1979. ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics’, Journal of Philosophy, 76.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Diogenes, L aertius. 1925. Lives of the Philosophers, trans. Hicks, R. D.. London: Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library.Google Scholar
Dostoyevsky, F. 1962. Letters to Family and Friends, trans. Mayne, E. C.. London: Chatto & Windus.Google Scholar
Douglas, M. 1986. How Institutions Think. Syracuse: University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1991. The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dunne, J. S. 1965. The City of the Gods. London: Sheldon Press.Google Scholar
Eco, U. 1986. Art and Beauty in the Middle Ages, trans. Bredin, H.. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. 1961. ‘Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms’, Quarterly Journal of Economics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epictetus, . 1926. Discourses and Encheiridion, trans. Oldfather, W. A.. London: Heinemann, Loeb Classical Library.Google Scholar
Feibleman, J. 1956. The Institutions of Society. New York: Humanities Press, 1968 (1st publ. 1956).Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 1978. Introductory Ethics. Englewood Cliffs: PrenticeHall.Google Scholar
Fishkin, J. 1982. The Limits of Obligation. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Fowler, H. 1926. A Dictionary of Modern English Usage. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1957. Civilization and Its Discontents. London: Hogarth Press.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1979. ‘A child is being beaten’, in Selected Writings, vol. 10. Harmondsworth: Pelican.Google Scholar
Frey, R. (ed.) 1984. Utility and Rights. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, P. 1992. ‘Prepositional Attitudes and Multicultural Education, or Believing Others are Mistaken’, in Horton, J. and Nicholson, P. (eds) Toleration: Philosophy and Practice. Aldershot: Avebury Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Greider, W. 1989. Secrets of the Temple: How the Federal Reserve runs the Country. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. 1986. Weil‐Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1963. Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1967. ‘Some Alleged Differences between Imperatives and Indicatives’, Mind, 76, 309‐326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1971. ‘The Argument from Received Opinion’, in Essays on Philosophical Method. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1985. ‘A reductio ad absurdum of Descriptivism’, in Shanker, S. (ed.) Philosophy in Britain Today. London: Croom Helm. Reprinted in Hare, 1989.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1989. Essays in Ethical Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1993. ‘Could Kant have been a Utilitarian?’, Utilitas, 5. Also in Dancy, 1993.Google Scholar
Hart, H. 1963. Law, Liberty and Morality. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Havel, V. 1992. Selected Plays. London: Faber.Google Scholar
Hetherington, H. and Muirhead, J. 1918. Social Purpose. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (ed.) 1967. The Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hofstadter, D. and Dennett, D. (eds) 1982. The Mind's I. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Honore, A. 1988. ‘Responsibility and Luck’, Law Quarterly Review, 104, 530‐553.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 1990. Truth. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hospers, J. 1982. Human Conduct. London: Harcourt Brace Joyanovich.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1948. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Aiken, H. D.. New York: Hafner.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1729. A Treatise of Human Nature.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. 1989. Natural Reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
James, W. 1890. The Principles of Psychology. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, S. 1990. Anti‐Climax: A Feminist Perspective on the Sexual Revolution. London: The Women's Press.Google Scholar
Joad, C. E. M. 1938. Guide to the Philosophy of Morals and Politics. London: Gollancz.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1928. Critique of Judgement, trans. Meredith, C. J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1929. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Smith, N. Kemp(KrV.) London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1948. The Moral Law (Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitteri), trans. Paton, H.. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1964. Doctrine of Virtue, trans. Gregor, M.. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Keats, J. 1956. Poetical Works, ed. Garrod, H. W.. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, M. 1990. Determinism, Blameworthiness and Deprivation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. 1964. ‘Proofs and Refutations’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leicester, M. 1986. ‘Multicultural Curriculum or Anti‐racist Education: denying the gulf, Multicultural Teaching to Combat Racism in School and Community, 4, 4‐7.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1969.Totality and Infinity, trans. Lingis, A lphonso. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1972. Humanisme de I'autre homme. Montpellier: Fata Morgana.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1976. Difficile liberte. Paris: Albin Michel.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1981. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1982. De Dieu qui vient a I'idee. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Lewis, H. D. 1976. (ed.) Contemporary British Philosophy, Series IV. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Liebling, A. J. 1964. The Press. New York: Ballantine Books.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. 1976. ‘Mill's Theory of Morality’, Nous, 10, 101–120.Google Scholar
MacBeath, A. 1952. Experiments in Living. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
MacDonald, I. 1991. The New Shostakovich. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maclntyre, A. 1985. ‘Relativism, Power and Philosophy’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 59.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1946. ‘A Refutation of Morals’, Australian Journal of Philosophy, 24, 77‐90.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Malebranche, N.The Search after Truth, trans. Lennon, T. M. and Olscamp, P. J.. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.Google Scholar
Mayo, B. 1986. The Philosophy of Right and Wrong. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
McGhee, M. 1993. ‘Chastity and the Male Philosopher’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 10.Google Scholar
McMurrin, S. (ed.) 1988. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1879. System of Logic. London: Longmans Green.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1965. Collected Works. London: Routledge; Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1965—.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mothersill, M. 1984. Beauty Restored. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Murdoch, I. 1970. The Sovereignty of the Good. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1979. ‘Moral luck’, in Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Newman, J. H. 1985. The Grammar of Assent, ed. Ker, I. J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Newton‐Smith, W. 1981. The Rationality of Science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nozick, R.Philosophical Explanations. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O'Neill, O. 1989. ‘The Great Maxims of Justice and of Charity’, in Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O'Neill, O. 1992. ‘Theories of Justice, Traditions of Virtue’, in Gross, H. and Harrison, R. (eds) Jurisprudence: Cambridge Essays.Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Petersen, G. (ed.) 1992. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 13. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.Google Scholar
Pincoffs, E. 1966. The Rationale of Legal Punishment. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Plotinus, , 1956. Enneads, trans. McKenna, . London: Faber.Google Scholar
Pojman, L. 1990. Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong. Belmont: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Potter, N. and Timmons, M. (eds) 1985. Morality and Universality: Essays on Ethical Universalizabilty. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1953. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raphael, D. 1981. Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1951. ‘Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics’, Philosophical Review, 60.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1955. ‘Two Concepts of Rules’, Philosophical Review, 44.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1958. ‘Justice as Fairness’, Philosophical Review, 47.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1972. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1975. ‘The Independence of Moral Theory’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1980. ‘Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory’, Journal of Philosophy, 77.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1985. ‘Justice as Fairness: political not metaphysical’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14.Google Scholar
Roemer, J. 1985. ‘Equality of talent’, Economics and Philosophy, 1.Google Scholar
Roemer, J. 1986. ‘Equality of Resources Implies Equality of Welfare’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, CI.Google Scholar
Roemer, J. 1987. ‘Egalitarianism, Responsibility, and Information’, Economics and Philosophy, 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roemer, J. 1993. ‘A Pragmatic Theory of Responsibility for the Egalitarian Planner’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1980. Philosophy and The Mirror of Nature. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rosenzweig, F. 1925. ‘The New Thinking’ (‘Das neue Denken. Einige nachtragliche Bemerjungen zum Stern de Erlosung’), Der Morgen, Vol. 1.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roth, J. K. (ed.) 1969. The Moral Philosophy of William James. New York: Crowell.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. P. 1965. L'Existentialisme est un humanisme. Paris: Nagel.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. P. 1969. Being and Nothingness, trans. Barnes, H.. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1988. ‘The Significance of Choice’, in MacMurrin, 1988.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1990. ‘The Aims and Authority of Moral Theory’, Hart Lecture in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, University College, Oxford.Google Scholar
Schneewind, J. B. 1990. ‘The Misfortunes of Virtue’, Ethics, 101, 42–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. 1982. ‘Equality of What?’, in Choice, Welfare and Measurement. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Singer, M. 1961. Generalization in Ethics. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1963.Google Scholar
Singer, M. 1977. Morals and Values. New York: Charles Scribner's & Sons.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 1974. ‘Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium’, The Monist, 58.Google Scholar
Sircello, G. 1975. A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton & London: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. 1985. ‘Objectivity and Convergence’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXXXVI, 1985/6, 235–50.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. 1992. ‘Liberal elitism’, in Milligan, D. and Watts‐Miller, W. (eds.) Citizenship and Autonomy. Aldershot: Avebury Press.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. 1993. ‘Anti‐realism, Inference and the Logical Constants’, in Haldane, J. and Wright, C. (eds.) Realism and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Snitow, A. 1979. ‘Mass Market Romance: pornography for women is different’, Radical History Review, 20.Google Scholar
Solzhenitsyn, A. 1990. One Day in the Life of Ivan Denisovitch, trans. Parker, R.. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Starr, W. and Taylor, R. (eds) 1989. Moral Philosophy: Historical and Contemporary Essays. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Stevens, P. S. 1976. Patterns in Nature. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 1986. Freedom and Belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1950. ‘Truth’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 24.Google Scholar
Tawney, R. H. 1921. The Acquisitive Society. London: G. Bell & Sons.Google Scholar
Theweleit, K. 1987. Male Fantasies, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warnock, G. J. 1967. Contemporary Moral Philosophy. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Warnock, G. J. 1971. The Object of Morality. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Weber, R. 1986. Dialogues with Scientists and Sages. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Weil, S. 1959. Waiting on God, trans. Crawford, E.. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
Westermarck, E. 1932. Ethical Relativity. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.Google Scholar
Wieland, G. 1982. ‘Happiness: the perfection of man’, in Kretzmann, N., Kenny, A., and Pinborg, J. (eds.) Cambridge History of Later Mediaeval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 673‐686.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1987. Needs, Values, Truth, Essays in the Philosophy of Value. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1990. ‘Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Beliefs’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 1990‐91, 91.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1972a. ‘Knowledge and Reasons’, in Wright, G. H. (ed.) Entretiens de Helsinki (I.I.P). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1972b. Problems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1978 Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
Winch, P. 1958. The Idea of a Social Science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Windelband, J. 1921. An Introduction to Philosophy, trans. McCabe, J..London: T. Fisher Unwin.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1967. Zettel. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On Certainty, ed. Anscombe, G. and von Wright, G.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
WynneTyson, J. (ed.) 1985. The Extended Circle. Fontwell: Centaur Press.Google Scholar
Zaehner, R. C. 1974. Our Savage God. London: Collins.Google Scholar