Article contents
The Problem of the Empirical Basis
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
Extract
In this paper I shall venture into an area with which I am not very familiar and in which I feel far from confident; namely into phenomenology. My main motive is not to get away from standard, boring, methodological questions like those of induction and demarcation; but the conviction that a phenomenological account of the empirical basis forms a necessary complement to Popper's falsificationism. According to the latter, a scientific theory is a synthetic and universal, hence unverifiable proposition. In fact, in order to be technologically useful, a scientific hypothesis must refer to future states-of-affairs; it ought therefore to remain unverified. But in order to be empirical, a theory must bear some kind of relation to factual statements. According to Popper, such a relation can only be one of potential conflict. Thus a theory T will be termed scientific if and only if T is logically incompatible with a so-called basic statement b, where b is both empirically verifiable and empirically falsifiable. (We shall see that neither the verifiability nor the falsifiability of b was meant, by Popper, in any literal sense.) In other words: T is scientific if it entails ¬b; where b, hence also ¬b, is an empirically decidable proposition.
- Type
- Papers
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1995
References
1 See Popper, : BG, p. 125.Google Scholar
2 Duhem, P., The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, Part 2, Chapter 4 (Princeton, 1914).Google Scholar
3 Quine, W. v. O., From a Logical Point of View, Chapter 2 (Harvard, 1961).Google Scholar
4 Watkins, J. W. N., Science and Scepticism, Chapter 3. (Princeton 1984).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5 See Popper, : BG, p. 125.Google Scholar
6 Watkins, , Science and Scepticism, Chapter 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7 Zahar, E. G., ‘The Popper-Lakatos Controversy’, Section 2 , in Fundamenta Scientiae, Vol. 3, No. 1, pp. 21–54.Google Scholar (Pergamon, 1982).
8 Popper, : LSD, p. 105.Google Scholar For the rejection of the view that experiences confer a degree of certainty onto protocol statements, see LSD, p. 104, footnote 1.Google Scholar
9 See Popper, , BG, p. 125.Google Scholar
10 See Popper, , BG, p. 130.Google Scholar
11 See Popper, , BG, p. 125.Google Scholar
12 See Popper, , BG, p. 127.Google Scholar
13 Duhem, , The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, Chapter 4, Section 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14 See Popper, , BG, pp.129–130.Google Scholar
15 See Popper, ; BG, p. 132.Google Scholar
16 See Popper, , BG, p. 53.Google Scholar Unfortunately, Popper changed his mind—but only partially—as to the inadmissibility of transcendent criticism. Still, he regarded the latter as insufficient to refute the criticized position.
17 See Popper, , BG, p. 122 (my translation).Google Scholar
18 See Popper, , BG, p. 110.Google Scholar
19 Brentano, F., Wahrheit und Evidenz, Section 4 (Meiner, F., 1930).Google Scholar
20 Ibid. Section 4.
21 Ibid. Einleitung.
22 Ayer, A. J., The Problem of Knowledge, pp. 106, 111, 115, 118 (Penguin, 1956).Google Scholar
23 Brentano, F., Psychologie, Vol. 1, Chapter 3 (Meiner, F., 1924).Google Scholar
24 Brentano, F., Psychologie, Vol. 3, Chapter 1 (Meiner, F., 1968).Google Scholar
25 Watkins, , Science and Scepticism, Chapter 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
26 For more details, see Zahar, E. G. ‘John Watkins on the Empirical Basis and the Corroboration of Scientific Theories’, in d'Agostino, F. (ed.), Freedom and Rationality (Kluwer, 1989).Google Scholar
- 1
- Cited by