Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T15:52:54.575Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mental Substances1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

Philosophers of mind typically conduct their discussions in terms of mental events, mental processes, mental properties, mental states—but rarely in terms of minds themselves. Sometimes this neglect is explicity acknowledged. Donald Davidson, for example, writes that ‘there are no such things as minds, but people have mental properties, which is to say that certain psychological predicates are true of them. These properties are constantly changing, and such changes are mental events’. Hilary Putnam agrees, though for somewhat different reasons:

The view I have long defended is that the mind is not a thing, talk of our minds is talk of World-involving capabilities that we have and activities that we engage in. As Dewey succinctly put it, ‘Mind is primarily a verb. It denotes all the ways in which we deal consciously and expressly with the situation in which we find ourseleves. Unfortunately, an influential manner of thinking has changed modes of action into an underlying substance that performs the activities in question. It has treated mind as an independent entity which attends, purposes, cares and remembers’. But the traditional view, by treating mental states as states of the ‘underlying substance’, makes them properties of something ‘inside’, and, if one is a materialist philosopher, that means properties of our brains. So the next problem naturally seems to be: ‘Which neurological properties of our brains do these mental properties “reduce” to?’ For how could our brains have properties that aren't neurological? And this is how materialist philosphers saw the problem until the advent of such new alternatives in the philosophy of mind and philosophy of language as Functionalism and Semantic Externalism.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

2 Davidson, Donald, ‘Davidson, Donald’ in A Companion in the Philosophy of Mind Guttenplan, Samuel (ed.) (Oxford: Blackwell 1995)Google Scholar

3 Putnam, Hilary, The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body and World (New York, Columbia UP 1999) 169–70Google Scholar; the quotations from Dewey is from Dewey, J., Art as Experience in John Dewey: The Later Works, 1925–1953, vol. 10, 1934 (Carbondale, Ill.'Southern Illinois UP, 1991) 268Google Scholar.

4 See, e.g., Lewis, David, ‘An argument for the Identity Theory’ in Lewis, , Philosophical Papers Volume I (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1985)Google Scholar, where no such assumption is explicitly made.

5 For recent defences of this idea of substance see Hoffman, Gary and Rosenkrantz, Joshua, Substance: its Nature and Existence (London: Routledge 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Lowe, E. J., The Possibility of Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1998)Google Scholar. Some of these claims are discussed in section 3 below.

6 Thus Jaegwon Kim Writes: ‘The idea of minds as souls or spirits, as entities or objects of a special kind, has never gained a foothold in a serious scientific study of the mind and has also gradually disappeared from philosophical discussions of mentality⃛ There has been a near consensus among philosophers that the concept of mind as a mental substance gives rise to too many difficulties and puzzles without compensating explanatory gains.’ Philosophy of Mind (Boulder: Westview 1996) 3Google Scholar.

7 For agreement on this point, see Rosenthal, David ‘Identity theories’ in Guttenplan, Samuel (ed.) op. cit., 348Google Scholar.

8 This view is still quite common in contemporary philosophy. For example, when discussing dualism, Jackson, Frank says that ‘ectoplasm is to be understood as the kind of stuff incompatible with the physicalists' view of what kinds there are—perhaps the stuff out of which thoughts are made according to Descartes.’ From Metaphysis to Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 15Google Scholar. For a useful corrective, see Lowe, E. J., The Possibility of Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998) 201Google Scholar.

9 ‘Substance’ in her Collected Philosophical Papers Volume II: Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981)Google Scholar.

10 For example: ‘Since there seems no reason to deny the intelligibility of souls, we affirm their logical possibility’, Hoffman and Rosenkrantz, op.cit. 6.

11 SeePapineau, David, Thinking about Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Loewer, Barry, ‘From physics to physicalism’ in Physicalism and its Discontents, Loewer, Barry and Gillet, Carl (eds.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2001)Google Scholar.

12 For more on this conception of the mind-body problem, see my Elements of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001),§19Google Scholar.

13 Foder, Jerry, ‘The mind-body problem’ in The Mind-Body Problem, Szubka, T. and Warner, R. (eds.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 25Google Scholar.

14 A notable exception is E. J. Lowe. See his ‘Event causation and agent causation’, Grazer Philosophische Studien forthcoming.

15 It might be objected that fundamental to substance dualism is the idea that the world does not have one kind of explanation, but that fundamentally different styles of explanation are required for mental and physical substances and their effects. Monists (e.g. physicalists) may then argue that the same form of explanation (e.g. subsmption under physical law) applies to mental and physical things, and this is because they are fundamentally the same kind of substance. This does link the rejection of substance dualism to the current debate in an interesting way, and requires further discussion. My basic response is that the driving idea here is the idea of a single kind of explanation, an idea I was expressing in terms of the causal closure of the physical world. I am indebted here to discussions with Mike Martin.

16 See, for example, Simons, Peter, ‘Farewell to substance: a differentiated leave-takingRatio New Series 11 (1998), 253–252CrossRefGoogle Scholar; also in Form and Matter. Themes in Contemporary Metaphysics, Oderberg, D. S. (ed.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), 2239Google Scholar.

17 See Davidson, Donald, ‘Events as particulars’ in Davidson, , Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Broad, C. D., An Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1933,) 138Google Scholar.

19 Wiggins, David, Sameness and Substance Renewed (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 31, note 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 This presupposes that attributes are universals in D. M. Armstrong's sense, rather than tropes or ‘abstract particulars’ see Universals and Scientific Realism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978)Google Scholar especially volume I. For further discussion of the kind of issue discussed in this paragraph, see Lowe, E. J., The Possibility of Metaphysics Chapter 6, especially 141–2Google Scholar, and Hoffman, G. and Rosenkrantz, J., ‘The independence criterion of substance’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1991) 835–52Google Scholar.

21 Descartes, R., Principles of Philosophy I.51 in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes trans. & eds. Cottingham, J. et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), vol. 1, 210Google Scholar.

22 For the necessity of origin, see Kripke, Saul, Naming and Necessity Oxford Blackwell, 1980Google Scholar, Lecture 3. E. J. Lowe willingly accepts this consequence of the independence criterion in The Possibility of Metaphysics op. cit., 152, but usefully distinguishes between saying that A might have not been born—i.e. might have come into existence without parents, or might have always been in existence—and saying that given that A was born, A might have had different parents. He admits only the possibility of the first of these.

23 See Wigging, Sameness and Substance Renewed chapter 4.

24 See, for example, the criticism in Leibniz's Discourse on Metaphysics §12. All page and other references to Leibniz's works in this paper are to the translation in G. W. Leibniz Philosophy Texts Woolhouse, R. and Francks, R. (eds.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

25 See Monadology §1–3, and ‘Principles of Nature and Grace, Based on Reason’, §1.

26 Leibniz, letter to Arnauld, 30 April 1687.

27 Leibniz, letter to Arnauld, 23 March 1690.

28 See especially Material Beings (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990)Google Scholar,

29 Op. cit. section 9, especially 81–3.

30 On the reasons why there are simples, see op. cit., 99.

31 Op. cit., 121.

32 Leibniz, letter to Arnauld, 30 April 1687.

33 Leibniz, letter to Arnauld, 23 March 1690.

34 The locus classicus of this kind of view is Quine's, W. V. ‘Identity, ostension and hypostasis’, in Quine, , From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1953)Google Scholar.

35 David Lewis's metaphysical system is perhaps the best and most sophisticated example of the combination of these two theories. But the theories are independent of each other.

36 Meditation VI, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes volume IIGoogle Scholar.

37 Strawson, P. F., Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Strawson, , op. cit., p. 115Google Scholar.

39 Snowdon, Paul, ‘Persons and personal identity’ in Essay for David Wigging: Identity, Truth & Value, Lovibond, S. and Williams, S. (eds.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996) 44Google Scholar.

40 This is the consequence drawn by Lowe, E. J., The Possibility of Metaphysics, op. cit., 172Google Scholar.