No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Law and the Protection of Institutions
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
Extract
It is a pity that the question about the proper purpose of law has so often been formulated in terms of ‘the enforcement of morals’. Not only is that issue highly charged with emotion, but the sense of the expression is unclear and, taken in any ordinary sense, its importance is marginal. What Lord Devlin seems chiefly to be arguing, when he supports the enforcement of morals, is that there are in any society certain central institutions which receive and deserve protection by law and that without such protection the society in question would disintegrate. His examples in our own society are monogamy and private property. It is true that these institutions are closely bound up with parts of our morality in two different ways: (a) certain moral prohibitions are defined in terms of them, e.g. adultery and theft; (b) a host of obligations is associated with them upon whose general acceptance and discharge their continuance depends. But it is only in an extended sense that one could describe the institutions themselves as parts of the common morality. It is possible, therefore, to hold that the law may properly be used to protect such institutions without necessarily taking the further step of maintaining that their protection requires and justifies legal prohibition of acts which offend against the associated morality. Professor Hart states this position clearly (a position which he does not himself accept): ‘What is essential and to be preserved is the essential core. On this footing it would be an open and empirical question whether any particular moral rule or veto, e.g. on homosexuality, adultery or fornication, is so organically connected with the central core that its maintenance and preservation is required as a vital outwork or bastion.’
- Type
- Papers
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1970
References
page 204 note 1 ‘Social Solidarity and the Enforcement of Morality’, University of Chicago Law Review, xxxv (1967).Google Scholar
page 205 note 1 Ibid., p. 9; also The Concept of Law (Oxford, 1961) p. 167.Google Scholar
page 206 note 1 Republic of Kenya, Report of the Commission on the Law of Marriage and Divorce (Nairobi, 1968).Google Scholar
page 208 note 1 Nadel, , Anthropology and Modern Life, Inaugural Lecture Australian National University (Canberra, 1953)Google Scholar; quoted by Emmet, D., Rules, Roles and Relations (London, 1966) p. 27.Google Scholar
page 209 note 1 ‘The degree of anomie in a social system is indicated by the extent to which there is lack of consensus on norms judged to be legitimate, with its attendant uncertainty and insecurity in social relations’ (my italics). Rose, G., ‘Anomie, and Deviation — A Conceptual Framework for Empirical Studies’ (British Journal of Sociology, 1964)Google Scholar quoted in Sociology, Theology and Conflict, ed. Whiteley, D. E. H. and Martin, R. (Oxford, 1969) p. 21.Google Scholar
page 212 note 1 Para. 78.
page 212 note 2 East African Law Journal (03–06 1969) p. 59.Google Scholar
page 213 note 1 Loc. cit., p. 1.
page 214 note 1 Concept of Motivation, and ed. (London, 1960) p. 5.Google Scholar
page 214 note 2 ‘Interest in Politics’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1959).Google Scholar
page 215 note 1 The Times, 23 09 1969.Google Scholar
page 217 note 1 Or should be. Kidd, Harry points out (The Trouble at L.S.E. (Oxford, 1969) p. 133)Google Scholar that the fact that the police need not answer a call to evict trespassers who are disrupting the work of the university is ‘a gap in the system of law and order’.
page 217 note 2 On Justice in Society (London, 1965) p. 239.Google Scholar
page 217 note 3 Sex in Society (London, 1963) p. 168.Google Scholar