No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Extract
Few major philosophers show evidence of having studied the works of their predecessors with special care, even in cases where they were subject to particular influences which they were ready to acknowledge. Hume knew that he was working in the tradition of ‘some late philosophers in England, who have begun to put the science of man on a new footing’—‘Mr Locke, my Lord Shaftsbury, Dr Mandeville, Mr Hutchinson, Dr Butler, &c.’ But there is not much sign in the Treatise or elsewhere in Hume's writings of any close acquaintance with the works of these authors; the presumption must be that he had read them at some time and extracted the main ideas, but was not in the habit of returning to their texts. He had something more important to do, namely to work at philosophical problems of his own. Similarly Kant, though he said that the Critique of Pure Reason was not meant to be ‘a critique of books and systems, but of the faculty of reason in general’, had clearly felt the impact of the thought of some important past philosophers, but equally had never spent much time in finding out just what these philosophers had to say. Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Locke, Leibniz and Hume all get fairly frequent mention in his pages. But Kant takes his knowledge of Plato and Aristotle from J. J. Brucker's Historia critica philosophiae, a six-volume compilation which first appeared in 1742, or from doubtful sources such as Mendelssohn's doctored translation of the Phaedo, and though he doubtless knew the more recent authors at first hand clearly felt no need to study them in any depth. This was true even of writers to whom he attributed a particular importance, such as Leibniz and Hume. The references to Hume in the Critique and Prolegomena are all disappointingly general, and though the summary of Leibniz's philosophy in the section called ‘The Amphiboly of Concepts of Reflection’ has a certain force, it is not documented with references to Leibnizian texts. Kant knows that there is a difference between the views of the historical Leibniz and those which constituted the ‘Leibnizian-Wolffian system’ of his successors. But he is not very curious about the difference, or inclined to explore it.
- Type
- Papers
- Information
- Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements , Volume 13: Idealism Past and Present , March 1982 , pp. 93 - 109
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1982
References
1 He obviously read Malebranche more carefully, and must have studied Hobbes, who is mentioned only once in the Treatise and not at all in the first Enquiry.
2 Quoted here and elsewhere in the translation by Wallace, William, The Logic of Hegel, 2nd edn (London: Oxford University Press, 1892).Google Scholar
3 I do not discuss these objections here but have done so in a subsequent paper: ‘The Idea of a Critique of Pure Reason: Kant and Hegel’, forthcoming in Akten des 5. internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Mainz, 1981.Google Scholar
4 Lectures on the History of Philosophy, 3 vols, translated by Haldane, E. S. and Simson, F. H. (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Co., 1892–1895).Google Scholar
5 Translated as Faith and Knowledge by Cerf, Walter and Harris, H. S. (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977).Google Scholar
6 Hegel's Science of Logic, translated by Miller, A. V. (London: Allen and Unwin, 1969).Google Scholar
7 For a discussion of this issue see my paper ‘Subjective and Objective Idealism’, to be published in the proceedings of the Hegel Congress at Stuttgart, 1981.
8 Translated by T. M. Knox (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975).