Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-dtkg6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-12T14:09:57.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanation in Psychology: Truth and Teleology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

A number of recent writers have argued that we should explain mental representation teleologically, in terms of the biological purposes of beliefs and other mental states.

A rather older idea is that the truth condition of a belief is that condition which guarantees that actions based on that belief will succeed.

What I want to show in this paper is that these two ideas complement each other. The teleological theory is inadequate unless it incorporates the thesis that truth is the guarantee of successful action. Conversely, the success-guaranteeing account of truth conditions is incomplete until it is placed in a teleological context.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Appiah, A. 1986. ‘Truth Conditions: A Causal Theory’, in Butterfield, J. (ed.), Language, Mind and Logic (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1979. ‘Individualism and the Mental’, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1982. ‘Other Bodies’, in Woodfield, 1982.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1969. Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1987. The Intentional Stance (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 1984. Realism and Truth (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1986. ‘Misrepresentation’, in Bogdan, R. (ed.), Belief (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining Behaviour (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1974. The Justification of Deduction, British Academy Lecture (Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Field, H. 1972. ‘Tarski's Theory of Truth’, Journal of Philosophy, 69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. 1978. ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis, 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. 1986. ‘The Deflationary Conception of Truth’, in MacDonald, G. and Wright, C. (eds), Fact, Science and Morality (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1984: ‘Semantics, Wisconsin Style’, Sythèse, 59.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987. Psychosemantics (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. 1982. ‘Three Forms of Realism’, Synthèse, 51.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 1987. ‘Pure Truth’, unpublished draft.Google Scholar
Leeds, S. 1978. ‘Theories of Reference and Truth’, Erkenntnis, 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, B. 1982. Mind and Meaning (Cambridge, University Press).Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1986. ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space’, in Pettit, P. and McDowell, J. (eds), Subject, Thought and Context (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1982. ‘The Structure of Content’, in Woodfield, 1982.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1989. Mental Content (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1988. ‘I and Now’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 89.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. 1986. ‘Thought without Laws: Cognitive Science with Content’, Philosophical Review, 95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. 1984. ‘Abnormal Psychobiology’, PhD dissertation. La Trobe University.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 1984. ‘Representation and Explanation’, Philosophy of Science, 51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 1986. ‘Semantic Reduction and Reference’, in Butterfield, J. (ed.) Language, Mind and Logic, (Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 1987. Reality and Representation (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in his Mind, Language and Reality (Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1978. ‘Reference and Understanding’, in his Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. 1927. ‘Facts and Propositions’, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 7.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1984. Inquiry (Cambridge Mass: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1982. ‘Dennett on Intentional Systems’, in Biro, J. and Shahan, R. (eds.), Mind, Brain and Function (Brighton: Harvester).Google Scholar
Quine, W. 1970. Philosophy of Logic (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall).Google Scholar
Woodfield, A. (ed.) 1982. Thought and Object (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Wright, L. 1973. ‘Functions’, Philosophical Review, 82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar