Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-04T19:44:27.927Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ethics of Co-operation in Wrongdoing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

There are a number of ways in which a person can share the guilt of another's wrongdoing. He might advise it, command it or consent to it. He might provoke it, praise it, flatter the wrongdoer, or conceal the wrong. He might stay silent when there is a clear duty to denounce the wrong or its perpetrator; or he might positively defend the wrong done. Finally, he might actively participate or cooperate in the wrongdoing. These various activities, apart from cooperation, typically occur before or after the commission of the wrong itself, only provocation being essentially before the fact. As such they fall into the categories of seduction or comfort, seduction being essentially pre-commission and comfort post-commission. In seduction (mutatis mutandis for comfort), the seducer typically leads another into doing wrong who has not definitely made up his mind. He does not assist in the commission, but he leads to its occurring. If the principal (as I will call the one who commits the wrong) has made up his mind, actions which might otherwise amount to seduction are best characterized as amounting to scandal, since they do not lead to wrong but reinforce the principal in his wrongful intent or provide to third parties a bad example since they connote approval of the principal's action. Closely related to the concept of seduction is that of solicitation, though perhaps these are best thought of as two aspects of the same kind of activity. Seduction can be thought of as a strong form of inducement to wrong, typified by command, counsel (where the seducer knows the advice is likely to be relied upon) and enticement through praise or provocation. Solicitation is a softer form of inducement typically involving requests, appeals, and invitations. Whereas the seducer or solicitor leads another into wrong but does not assist in its commission, the co-operator does not lead the principal into wrong but assists in its commission.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Even if they occur during the commission, they occur with a view to that part of the wrong which either has been done or is yet to be done.

2 Though the scandalous actions might also lead to future wrongs by the principal.

3 In the common law of complicity, the driver of a getaway car would probably be guilty as an accomplice by having ‘aided and abetted’ the burglary. As an aider and abettor he would still be guilty of the principal offence of burglary, but since his action would not be thought of as coming within the legal definition of the offence he would be treated has having assisted rather than committed it.

4 In the common law, an intent to co-operate may be inferred from proof that the accused realized that his conduct would, or would very probably, assist or encourage the principal: National Coal Board v Gamble [1959] 1 QB 11, [1958] All ER 203; Clarkson [1971] 3 All ER 344, [1971] 1 WLR 1402. According to Devil J in Gamble, if a man sells a gun to another which he knows will be used for murder, he cannot escape from guilt as an abettor merely because he sold the gun only for the money and not in order that the victim be killed. Even if the co-operator does not desire the commission of the principal offence, both morality and the common law recognize that intent to assist may be implied by the circumstances. But whether, in a given case, assistance is best characterized as implicitly formal or only material (though still unlawful) depends largely on difficult questions surrounding the distinction between knowledge and intent which have long dogged the philosophy of mind and action.

5 For an egregious example of the idea that there can be such a thing as ‘moral mathematics’, see Parfit, D., Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University, 1984)Google Scholar.

6 See Anscombe, G. E. M., ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ in her Ethics, Religion and Politics: Philosophical Papers, vol. III (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981), 2642Google Scholar.

7 The most probable answer is that one generally may not advise the commission of a lesser evil for the general reasons stated above; but that if the lesser evil were already a virtual part of the greater, one could advise that the other person commit it instead. Example: Anna intends to steal £100 from Bertha; Christina, to prevent the theft, advises Anna to steal £50 instead. Here the act of stealing £50 is a virtual part of the act of stealing £100; Anna has already made up her mind to steal from Bertha, so Christina is not acting at all as a cause of theft (or seducer into theft), a fortiori not as a cause of the theft of £50 (or seducer); and Anna thereby prevents the greater evil, namely the theft of £100.

8 See Oderberg, D. S., Moral Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), ch. 3Google Scholar. See also Chappell, T. D. J., ‘Two Distinctions that Do Make a Difference’, Philosophy 77 (2002), 211–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 If you think the latter is permissible, you can change the example to child pornography.

10 Note: if you do not know the hitch-hiker's purpose until after the event you are an unwitting, and hence not even material co-operator.

11 Should you worry that some people will be scandalized by your behaviour in virtue of not having been informed that you were held at gunpoint? No, since there is no obligation to suffer a great loss (e.g. your own life) just to avoid the scandal of those who rush to judgment (what is sometimes called Pharisaic scandal). The right answer to such people is: ‘If you are scandalized, that's your problem.’

12 Present with qualifications in the common law until its abolition by statute in 1967.

13 See note 8.

14 See note 7.

15 What about knowledge by the seller that some wrongful act will be committed, but ignorance as to which? The same considerations would apply to lack of knowledge of the identity of the offence as to lack of knowledge of the identity of the offender. Needless to say, formal co-operation in both cases is impermissible. In common law, intentional co-operation involving lack of knowledge of the identity of the offence is sufficient for liability: DPP for Northern Ireland v Maxwell [1978] All ER 1140; it is difficult to know whether the same would apply to lack of knowledge of the offender.

16 For a defence of realism about intention, see Moral Theory, pp. 110–26.