Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T17:27:44.128Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Domains, Brains and Evolution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Extract

According to Darwinian thinking, organisms are (for the most part) designed by natural selection, and so are (for the most part) integrated collections of adaptations, where an adaptation is a phenotypic trait that is a specialized response to a particular selection pressure. For animals that make their living in the Arctic, one adaptive problem is how to maintain body temperature above a certain minimum level necessary for survival. Polar bears' thick coats are a response to that selection pressure (surviving in extreme cold). A thick coat makes a positive difference to a polar bear's fitness, since polar bears with very thin coats left fewer offspring than those with thicker coats. The foundational idea of evolutionary psychology is that brains are no different from any other organ with an evolutionary function, insofar as brains too are systems shaped by natural selection to solve adaptive problems. Thus brains have a particular functional organization because their behavioural effects tend, or once tended, to help maintain or increase the fitness of organisms with those brains. Prominent evolutionary psychologists (for example: Cosmides and Tooby, 1987; Cosmides and Tooby, 1994 and Symons, 1992) have endorsed the view that the last time any significant modifications were made by natural selection to the human brain's functional architecture, we were hunter-gatherers, inhabiting a world quite different from that which we now inhabit. That world was the Pleistocene epoch, between about 2 million years ago and 10 thousand years ago. On this view, then, the Pleistocene constitutes what evolutionary psychologists often call our environment of evolutionary adaptedness (or EEA), and the information- processing structure and organization of our present-day cognitive architecture is no different from that of our recent huntergatherer ancestors.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. (eds) 1992. The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books).Google Scholar
Bracewell, R. J. and Hidi, S. E. 1974. ‘The Solution of an Inferential Problem as a Function of the Stimulus Materials’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 26, 480–88.Google Scholar
Brooks, R. A. 1991. ‘Intelligence Without Reason’, in Proceedings of the Twelfth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence San Mateo, California (Morgan Kauffman), pp. 569–95.Google Scholar
Bullock, S. 1998. Evolutionary Simulation Models: On Their Character and Application to Problems Concerning the Evolution of Natural Signalling Systems. D-Phil Thesis, University of Sussex.Google Scholar
Buss, D. M. 1992. ‘Mate Preference Mechanisms: Consequences for Partner Choice and Intrasexual Competition’, in Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (eds) (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 249–66.Google Scholar
Calvin, W. 1983. The Throwing Madonna: Essays on the Brain (New York: McGraw-Hill).Google Scholar
Clark, A. and Thornton, C. 1997. ‘Trading Spaces: Computation, Representation and the Limits of Uninformed Learning’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 5790.Google Scholar
Connell, J. H. 1989. ‘A Colony Architecture for an Artificial Creature’, MIT AI Lab Memo 1151.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1987. ‘From Evolution to Behavior: Evolutionary Psychology as the Missing Link’, in Dupre, J. (ed.) (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 227306.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. 1989. ‘The Logic of Social Exchange: Has Natural Selection Shaped How Humans Reason? Studies with the Wason Selection Task’, Cognition, 31, 187276.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1989. ‘Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, Part II. Case Study: A Computational Theory of Social Exchange’, Ethology and Sociobiology, 10, 5197CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1992. ‘Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange’, in Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (eds) (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 163228.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1994. ‘Beyond Intuition and Instinct Blindness: Toward an Evolutionary Rigorous Cognitive Science’, Cognition, 50, 4177.Google Scholar
Dupre, J. (ed.) 1987. The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D. and Plunkett, K. 1996. Rethinking Innateness: A ConnectionistPerspective on Development (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books)Google Scholar
Feigenbaum, E. A. and Feldman, J. (eds) 1963. Computers and Thought (New York: McGraw-Hill)Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1983. The Modularity of Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Franceschini, N., Pichon, J. M. and Blanes, C. 1992. ‘From Insect Vision to Robot Vision’, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 337, 283–94.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. and Hug, K. 1992: ‘Domain-Specific Reasoning: Social Contracts, Cheating, and Perspective Change’, Cognition, 43, 127–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gould, S. J. and Vrba, E. S. 1982: ‘Exaptation: A Missing Term in the Science of Form’, Paleobiology, 1.8, 415.Google Scholar
Griggs, R. A. and Cox, J. R. 1982. ‘The Elusive Thematic-Materials Effect in Wason's Selection Task’, British Journal of Psychology, 73, 407–20.Google Scholar
Griggs, R. A. and Cox, J. R. 1983. ‘The Effects of Problem Content and Negation on Wason's Selection Task’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 35A, 519–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayes, P. J. 1979. ‘The Naive Physics Manifesto’, in Michie, D. (ed.) (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press), pp. 242–70.Google Scholar
Hirschfeld, L.A. and Gelman, S. A. (eds.) 1994a: Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture. (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. A. 1994b. ‘Toward a Topography of Mind: An Introduction to Domain Specificity’, in Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. A. (eds) (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 335.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. 1994. ‘A Nonclassical Framework for Cognitive Science’, Synthese, 101, 305–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Janzen, D. H. 1980. ‘When is it Co-Evolution?’, Evolution, 34, 611–12.Google Scholar
Leslie, A. M. 1994. ‘ToMM, ToBy, and Agency: Core Architecture and Domain Specificity’, in Hirschfeld, L. A. and Gelman, S. A. (eds) (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press), pp. 119–48.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R.C. 1978. ‘Adaptation’, Scientific American, 239.3, 156–69.Google Scholar
Michie, D. (ed.) 1979. Expert Systems in the Micro-Electronic Age (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press).Google Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H. A. 1963. ‘GPS—A Program that Simulates Human Thought’, in Feigenbaum, E. A. and Feldman, J. (eds) (New York: McGraw-Hill), pp. 279–96.Google Scholar
Nilsson, N. J. 1984. ‘Shakey the Robot’, S.R.I. AI Centre Tech. Report, no. 323.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. and Bloom, P. 1990. ‘Natural Language and Natural Selection’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, 707–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollard, P. 1981. ‘The Effect of Thematic Content on the “Wason selection task’”, Current Psychological Research, 1, 2129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (ed.) 1987. The Robot's Dilemma: The Frame Problem in Artificial Intelligence (New Jersey: Ablex).Google Scholar
Raup, D. M. 1991. Extinction: Bad Genes or Bad Luck? (New York: W. W. Norton).Google Scholar
Samuels, R. 1998. ‘Evolutionary Psychology and the Massive Modularity Hypothesis’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 575602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, L. and Epstein, W. 1998: ‘Evolutionary Theory Meets Cognitive Psychology: A More Selective Perspective’, Mind and Language, 13, 171–94.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. 1995. ‘Review of The Adapted Mind’, Biology and Philosophy, 10, 255–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. and Griffiths, P. E. 1999. Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).Google Scholar
Symons, D. 1992. ‘On the Use and Misuse of Darwinism in the Study of Human Behavior’, in Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (eds) (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 137–59.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. 1992. ‘The Psychological Foundations of Culture’, in Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (eds) (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 19136.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. 1998: ‘Evolutionizing the Cognitive Sciences: A Reply to Shapiro and Epstein’, Mind and Language, 13, 195204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar