No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Vorprung durch Logik: The German Analytic Tradition
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 January 2010
Extract
Although at present analytic philosophy is practiced mainly in the English-speaking world, it is to a considerable part the invention of German speakers. Its emergence owes much to Russell, Moore, and American Pragmatism, but even more to Frege, Wittgenstein, and the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle. No one would think of analytic philosophy as a specifically Anglophone phenomenon, if the Nazis had not driven many of its pioneers out of central Europe.
- Type
- Papers
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1999
References
Danto, A. ‘Naturalism’, in Edwards, P. (ed), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967).Google Scholar
Dummett, M. A. E.Frege and other Philosophers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991).Google Scholar
Føllesdal, D.. ‘Analytic Philosophy: what is it and why should one engage in it’, in Glock, H. J. (ed), The Rise of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).Google Scholar
Frege, G.The Foundations of Arithmetic, trans. Austin, J. L. (Oxford, 1953 [l. edn. 1884]).Google Scholar
Frege, G.. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Vol. I (Hildesheim: Olms, 1996 [1. edn. 1893]).Google Scholar
Glock, H. J. ‘Kant and Wittgenstein: Philosophy, Necessity and Representation’, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 5 (1997a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glock, H. J. ‘Philosophy, Thought and Language’, in Preston, J. (ed.), Thought and Language (Cambridge University Press, 1997b).Google Scholar
Glock, H. J. Review Article of Frege by Anthony Kenny, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 52.Google Scholar
Glock, H. J. ‘Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein: Language as Representation and Will, Janaway, R. C. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. ‘The Rise of Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy’, in Glock, H. J. (ed.), The Rise of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).Google Scholar
Hamilton, W.Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic, Vol. III (Edinburgh & London: Blackwood, 1860).Google Scholar
Kant, I.Prolegomena to any future Metaphysics, trans. Lucas, P. G. (Manchester University Press, 1953 [1. edn. 1783]).Google Scholar
Kant, I.On a Discovery according to which any New Critique of Pure Reason has been made Superfluous by an Earlier One, trans. Allison, H. (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1973 [1. edn. 1790]).Google Scholar
Kant, I. ‘The Jäsche Logic’ in Lectures on Logic, trans. Young, J. M. (Cambridge University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Kant, I.The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Guyer, P. and Woods, A.. (Cambridge University Press, 1998 [1. edn. 1781 and 1787]).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monk, R. ‘Was Russell an Analytic Philosopher?’, in Glock, H. J. (ed.), The Rise of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).Google Scholar
Natorp, P.. Die Logischen Grundlagen der Exakten Wissenschaften (Leipzig: Tenbner, 1910).Google Scholar
Sluga, H.Frege (London: Routledge, 1980). ‘Frege on Meaning’, in H. J. Glock (ed.), The Rise of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997).Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F.Analysis and Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L.Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961 [1. edn. 1922]).Google Scholar