Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T12:40:29.273Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Propositions First: Biting Geach's Bullet

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2019

M. J. Frápolli*
Affiliation:
Universidad de Granada

Abstract

To be a proposition is to possess propositional properties and to stand in inferential relations. This is the organic intuition, [OI], concerning propositional recognition. [OI] is not a circular characterization as long as those properties and relations that signal the presence of propositions are independently identified. My take on propositions does not depart from the standard approach widely accepted among philosophers of language. Propositions are truth-bearers, the arguments of truth-functions (‘not’, ‘or’, ‘and’, ‘if’), the arguments of propositional-attitude verbs (‘know’, ‘believe’, ‘doubt’, ‘assume’, ‘reject’) and the kind of entity capable of standing in inferential relations (which are basically implication and incompatibility). The aim of this paper is to argue for [OI]. In doing so, I will show that even what is probably the most repeated argument against non-descriptivism, the so-called Frege-Geach Argument (FGA), presupposes something like [OI], a presupposition that Geach shares with his critics. Despite the huge success of FGA, a thorough analysis of the actual scope of this argument has yet to be given. I will provide such an analysis in section 3 below. In this paper, I argue that [OI] is a meta-theoretical principle which is neutral with respect to specific metaphysical debates about the nature of propositions, as well as specific proposals about the semantics of declarative sentences.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The current debate on the semantics of personal taste predicables as led by MacFarlane's work (MacFarlane, John, Assessment Sensitivity. Relative Truth and its Application (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar involves normative functions of objects, a debate that falls outside the scope of this paper. As far as FGA is concerned, arguments in which predicables of personal taste occur are more similar to the ‘is-bad’ argument than to the ‘is-true’ argument.

2 See, for instance, Chrisman, Matthew, ‘Ethical Expressivism’. In Ed. By Miller, Christian (ed.), Continuum Companion to Ethics. Continuum, Bloomsbury Companions (2011), 2954Google Scholar, and also Price, Huw, ‘The semantics foundations of metaphysics’, in Ravenscroft, Ian, ed., Minds, Ethics, and Conditionals: Themes from the Philosophy of Frank Jackson. Oxford University Press (2009), 111140CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 In our paper, ‘Pragmatism. Propositional Priority and the Organic Model of Propositional Individuation’, Disputatio, Vol. VIII, No. 43, November 2016, 203–217, Neftalí Villanueva and I defended the ‘organic model’ of propositional individuation. The organic intuition is a related but more basic claim.

4 Geach, Peter, ‘Ascriptivism’, Philosophical Review 69 (2) (1960),  221225CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 I use ‘non-descriptivism’ as a general label for those semantic theories that deny that representation is the most basic semantic notion. These theories standardly assume that what speakers do with words when they are concerned with truth reduces to referring and predicating. ´Non-descriptivisḿ is thus intended to cover alternative views to the standard truth-conditional semantics. This characterization is very vague but, as the paper proceeds, the nature of my proposal and the alternative views that I want to keep at a distance will become clearer. Expressivisms of all kinds, non-cognitivism, conceptual-role semantics, and inferentialism, fall under my use of ‘non-descriptivism’. Strictly speaking, ‘describing’ and ‘representing' are not synonymous. The opposition of descriptivism vs. non-descriptivism, a dichotomy with pragmatist tones, concerns what agents do with utterances. Representationalism vs. non-representationalism, in contrast, is more centered in the semantic realm, and is often used to explain why some sentences mean what they do, and in which circumstances they are true or false. Finally, the opposition of cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism concerns the epistemic aspects of the debate, i.e. whether normative sentences express beliefs that can be said to be true or false, and whether knowledge of normative realms is possible. The Frege-Geach Argument, although originally used by Geach against ascriptivism, has since extended its target to the general family of non-representationalist, non-descriptivist views.

6 Peter Geach, op. cit. note 4,  222.

7 See Bar-On, Dorit and Chrisman, Matthew, ‘Ethical NeoExpressivism’, in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, ed. Shafer-Landau, Russ, vol. 4.  Oxford University Press, 2009, 132–65Google Scholar.

8 See, e.g. Ridge, MichaelEcumenical Expressivism: The Best of Both Worlds?’, Oxford Studies in Metaethics, ed. Shafer-Landau, Rus, Vol. 2., Oxford University Press, 2007, 5176Google Scholar; Impassioned Belief. Oxford: University Press, 2014, chapter 4.

9 Blackburn, Simon Essays in Quasi-Realism. Oxford University Press, 1993Google Scholar; Dorit Bar-On and Chrisman, op. cit. note 5,  Michael Ridge, op. cit. note 6.

10 Peter Geach, op. cit., note 2; Künne, Wolfgang, Conceptions of Truth. Oxford, Clarendon Press 2003CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Skorupski, J., ‘The Frege-Geach Objection to Expressivism: Still Unanswered’, Analysis 72, 2012918CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Gibbard, Allan, Thinking How to Live, Harvard University Press, 2003Google Scholar, chap. 3; Schroeder, M.How Expressivists Can and Should Solve Their Problem with Negation’. Nous 42, 4, 2008, 573599CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Expressions for Expressivists’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. LXXVI, 2008, 86116Google Scholar; Chrisman, Matthew, ‘Epistemic Expressivism’, Philosophy Compass 7/2, 2012, 118126CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 124; Alwood, Andrew, ‘Non-Descriptive Negation for Normative Sentences’, The Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 66, Issue 262, 2016, 124Google Scholar; Michael Ridge, op. cit, 2014 note 6.

12 Andrew Alwood, op. cit. note 11.

13 Searle, John, “Meaning and Speech Acts”. The Philosophical Review, 71 (4), 1962, 423432CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Huw Price, in Naturalism without Mirrors. Oxford University Press, 2011, 9, 12, 18, has used the label ‘global expressivism’, and Robert Brandom, in Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism, Harvard University Press, 2000, chapter 1, uses ‘inferentialism’ to name the view that propositions are individuated by the inferential network they stand in, in a way similar to the one Frege proposed in Begriffsschrift. Without a special name for his proposal, Arthur Prior, in ‘Is the Concept of Referential Opacity Really Necessary?', Acta Philosphical Fennica, vol. 16, 1963, 189–199, also used an intuition close to inferentialism to individuate propositions. I am sympathetic to Frege's, Prior's, Price's and Brandom's proposals, but I would like to stress the meta-theoretical character of [OI], which is compatible with expressivist/inferentialist implementations as much as it is with representationalist implementations.

15 Gibbard, Allan, Meaning and Normativity. Oxford University Press, 2012, 10CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Allan Gibbard, op. cit., note 15, e.g. 7ff., 147 ff.)

17 Alfred J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic, Penguin Books, 1936, chapter 6; Stevenson, C. L., ‘The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms’, Mind, 1937, vol. 46, n°. 181: 1431CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 ‘Irremediably’, if logic is restricted to the realm of propositions, as products of assertive acts. But historically there have been other, alternative views of logic. For instance, Richard M. Hare, in ‘Imperative sentences’, Mind, New Series, vol. 58, n°. 229, 1949, 21–39, rejected this standard view of logic and proposed that imperative sentences are as able as declarative sentences to bear contents with logical properties.

19 That we disagree about and debate normative claims is a raw fact. Disagreement is a basic intuition that is hard to dismiss. Semantic views that do not account for this phenomenon pay a high price that often takes the form of error theories (Mackie, John L., Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmonsworth: Penguin Books, 1977Google Scholar; Moberger, Victor, ’Not Just Error: A New Interpretation of Mackiés Error Theory’, Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 5, No. 3, 2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.  Classical emotivists acknowledged some kind of disagreement, in normative background (Alfred Ayer, op. cit. note 15, 111) or in attitude (C. L. Stevenson, op. cit. note 15, 18). Ayer rejected while Stevenson accepted the possibility of rational debate about ethical claims; but both, although defending ethical claimś lack of propositional content, felt the need to touch upon the issues of ethical disagreement and ethical debate. MacFarlane (MacFarlane, John, Assessment Sensitivity. Relative Truth and its Applications. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2014CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 121, 125, and 130) has refined the notion of disagreement to vindicate its application to normative disputes while allowing an explanation of the intuitions of absolutists and contextualists about values. Adapting his relativism to ethical claims, if A says ‘Cheating on your partner is good’ and B says ’Cheating on your partner is bad’, A and B disagree about content in the sense that their claims are not cotenable (the contents of their claims are incompatible), and the joint accuracy of A's and B's attitudes is precluded (A and B cannot both be right in the same context). Nevertheless, the reflexive accuracy of A's and B's attitudes is not precluded, in the sense that both can maintain their views from their different contexts of assessment. MacFarlane's refinements help deal with different types of disagreement, and make precise relevant aspects of it. But the first step for applying MacFarlane's apparatus is to acknowledge that speakers say something with normative claims, which is what [OI] says.

20 Russell, Bertrand, The Principles of Mathematics, Second Edition, New York, Norton. Inc. Publishers, 1903Google Scholar, 44ff.; Nathan Salmon, Frege's Puzzle, MIT Press/Bradford Book 1986,  and Tense and Singular Propositions’, in Themes From Kaplan, in Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Harvey Wettstein (eds.), Oxford: University Press, 1989, 391392Google Scholar; Soames, Scott, ‘Lost Innocence’, Linguistics and Philosophy 8, 19855971CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Direct Reference, Propositional Attitudes and Semantic Content’, Philosophical Topics 15, 1987, 4787CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and  ‘Semantics and Semantic Competence’, Philosophical Perspectives, 3, Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, Ridgeview Publishing Company, Atascadero, CA, 1989,  575 –596; Stanley, Jason, ‘Context and Logical Form’, Linguistics and Philosophy 23, 2000, 391434CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 David Lewis, (1980) ‘Index, Context, and Content’, in Stig Kange and Sven Öhman, eds. Philosophy and Grammar, 1980, 79–100; Cresswell, Maxwell J., Structured Meanings (The Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, Cambridge, MA., 2002)Google Scholar.

22 Horwich, Paul, Meaning (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Brandom, Robert, Making it Explicit. Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment (Harvard University Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

23 Lewis, David, ‘General Semantics’, Synthese 22 (1–2), 1970, 1867CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 31.

24 David Lewis, op. cit. note 21, 95.

25 David Lewis, op. cit. note 21, 91.

26 Hintikka, Jaakko and Sandu, Gabriel, ‘What are Quantifiers?’,  Synthese, vol. 98, no. 1, 1994, 113129CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 116.

27 Putnam, Hillary, ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7, 1975, 131193Google Scholar; Kripke, Saul, Naming and Necessity, Harvard University Press 1980Google Scholar.

28 Fodor, Jerry, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, Mass., The MIT Press 1989)Google Scholar; Sperber, Dan and Wilson, Deirdre, Relevance: Communication and cognition (Oxford, Blackwell's, 1986)Google Scholar.

29 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London, Kegan Paul, 1922)Google Scholar,  2.21.

30 Brandom, Robert, Reason in Philosophy. Animating Ideas (The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Cambridge, Mass. and London, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, chapter 6; Davidson, Donal, ‘The Folly of Trying to Define Truth’, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. XCIII, 1996, 263278CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rorty, Richard, ‘Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth’, Philosophical Papers. Cambridge University Press, 1985/1990Google Scholar.

31 François Recanati, F.The Pragmatics of What Is Said’, Mind and Language 4 (1989), 6: 295329CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Carston, Robyn, ‘Word Meaning, What Is Said and Explicature’, in Penco, Carlo and Domaneschi, Filippo (eds), What is Said and What is Not (Stanford: CSLI Publications, 2013)Google Scholar; Alan Gibbard, op. cit, note 15.

32 Urmson, J. O., ’Parenthetical Verbs’, Mind 61 (244), (1952), 480496CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 Peter Geach, op. cit., note 4, 222.

34 Frege, Gottlob, ‘Begriffsschrift, a formula language modeled upon that of arithmetic, for pure thought’, in van Heijenoort, Jean, ed., From Frege to Gödel. A source book on mathematical logic, 1879–1931 (Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967), 182Google Scholar.

35 Geach, Peter, ‘Ryle on Namely-Ryders’, Analysis 3 (1961), 6467CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Ryle, Gilbert, ‘Heterologicality’, Analysis 11 no. 3 (1951), 6169CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Paul Horwich, op. cit. note 22; Wyatt, Jeremy, ‘The Many (Yet Few) Faces of Deflationism’, The Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 66, Issue 263 (2016), 326382CrossRefGoogle Scholar; María J. Frápolli, The Nature of Truth. An Updated Approach to the Meaning of Truth-Ascriptions (Springer, 2013).

38 Mark Schroeder, op. cit. note 11, 589.

39 I will not dispute this point. There might be reasons to believe that ‘bad’ in ‘he is a bad person’ applies to individuals, in the same sense in which some people have argued that ‘true’ has first-level uses as in ‘He is a true friend’. I disagree. I consider that ‘true’ and ‘bad’ to  express normative notions that always involve reference to some standards that have to be represented as conceptual systems. Nevertheless, the alleged existence of first-level instances of them is irrelevant for my point here.

40 Peter Geach, op. cit., note 4;  Schroeder, Mark, Being For: Evaluating the Semantic Program of Expressivism. Oxford: University Press 2008, 704CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wolfgang Künne, W., Conceptions of Truth. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2003CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 Castañeda, Hector-Neri, ‘He: A study in the logic of self-consciousness’, in Hart, J. G. and Kapitan, T., eds., The Phenomenology of the I. Essays in Self-conciousness, (Bloomington, Indiana, Indiana University Press, 1999), 54Google Scholar.

42 Hector-Neri Castañeda, op. cit., note 41; Williams, Christopher, What is Identity? (Oxford: University Press, 1989)Google ScholarPubMed. More examples of indicative sentences without propositional content can be found in James Dreier, J. (2015) ‘Truth and Disagreement in Impassioned Belief’, Analysis, 75(3) (2015), 450–59, 452CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43 Orman Quine, Willard van, (1960) Word and Object (Harvard, Mass., The MIT Press, 1960), 137Google Scholar.

44 Ayer, Alfred J., Language, Truth, and Logic (Penguin Books, 1936), 107Google Scholar.

45 The case of predicates of personal taste is similar to the case of ethical terms. A non-descriptivist, expressivist explanation of normative first-order predicables, such as ‘is tasty’, is in no better position than ‘is bad’ on this account. MacFarlane explains the import of ‘is tasty’ as belonging to the context of assessment (John MacFarlane, op. cit. note 1, 149). His relativism is very much in need of explanation once the non-propositional status of its argument is exposed. MacFarlane's view is not my concern here, but it is worth bearing in mind that a correct assessment of the scope of FGA and an appropriate answer to it have effects that exceed the strict limits of meta-ethics.

46 Robert Brandom, op. cit., note 22 and Brandom, Robert, Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

47 See Robert Brandom, op. cit., note 22, chapter 2 passim, e.g. 91–92.

48 See, e.g., Robert Brandom, op. cit., note 22, 167ff.

49 Frápolli, María J. and Villanueva, Neftalí, ‘Minimal Expressivism’, dialectica, vol. 66, no 4 (2012),  471487CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Matthew Chrisman, op. cit. note 2; Dreier, James, ‘Meta-Ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism’, Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 2004, 2344, 26CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 Nevertheless, even Ayer (op. cit, note 17, 107) makes room for a descriptive sense of ‘good’

52 Allan Gibbard, op. cit. note 15,  53ff.; Robert Brandom, op. cit., note 20, 614ff.

53 James Dreier, op. cit. note 50; Matthew Chrisman, op. cit., note 2.

54 For an illustration of the consequences of creeping descriptivism, see Price's matching game in Price, Huw, Naturalism without Mirrors (Oxford University Press, 2011)Google Scholar, 3ff.

55 María J. Frápolli and Neftalí Villanueva, op. cit., note 49.

56 The project of this paper was made possible by funding received from the European Union's Horizon 2020 research and innovation program under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie Grant Agreement No. 653056. It has also received funding from the Spanish Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad, Proyecto FFI2016-80088-P. I have presented some of the ideas defended here in the Departmental Seminar of the Department of Philosophy at UCL, the TeC Seminar of the Departamento de Filosofía I, Universidad de Granada, and the Workshop Expressivisms, Knowledge and Truth, which is the source of this volume. Several of my colleagues have provided insightful comments on previous drafts, among them Andrés Forero, Manuel de Pinedo, Neftalí Villanueva and Victor Verdejo. To all of these, people and institutions, I am deeply grateful.