Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T20:07:29.610Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Leading a Life of One's Own: On Well-Being and Narrative Autonomy”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 April 2017

Extract

We all want things. And although we might disagree on just how significant our wants, desires, or preferences are for the matter of how well we fare in life, we would probably all agree on some of them having some significance. So any reasonable theory about the human good should in some way acknowledge this. The theory that most clearly meets this demand is of course preferentialism, but even pluralist theories can do so. However, then they will at the same time bring aboard a classical problem for preferentialism, namely that of discriminating among preferences. Not all preferences would seem to make contributions to our well-being and there should be some set of criteria which at least makes it intelligible why there is such a difference and that perhaps can even be used in order to evaluate hard cases.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 I have tried to provide some arguments in ‘Good Lives: Parts and Wholes’, American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (04 2001): 221–31Google Scholar, and ‘Leading Lives: On Happiness and Narrative Meaning’, Philosophical Papers 32 (11 2003): 321–43.Google Scholar

2 Well-Being (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), p. 67.Google Scholar

3 Some examples are MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue, 2nd Ed. (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984)Google Scholar, Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar, Johnson, Mark, Moral Imagination (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993)Google Scholar, Flanagan, Owen, ‘Multiple Identity, Character Transformation, and Self-Reclamation’ in Self-Expressions (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar, and Velleman, David, ‘Well-Being and Time’ in The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

4 The latter is the line taken by Chappell, Timothy in Understanding Human Goods: A Theory of Ethics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1998).Google Scholar

5 Alasdair MacIntyre, ibid., p. 219, and Charles Taylor, ibid., p. 48, both embrace this idea of life as a form of quest.

6 I borrow both of these notions from Richard Nisbett & Ross, Lee, Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment (Englewood Cliff, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1980), pp. 32–5.Google Scholar

7 This would be similar to Ronald Dworkin's emphasis on what he calls ‘personal preferences’ (as opposed to ‘external preferences’), see Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1978), pp. 234–37.Google Scholar

8 This would be a variation on Stephen Darwall's position in Welfare and Rational Care (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002)Google Scholar, Chapter 1, where he emphasizes the dimension concerning the one for whom one wants something.

9 Since the meaning of events in my life can be affected by things lying outside my life, my strivings can to a certain extent be made more valuable by posthumous success. Such contributions to how well my life went are however probably not best understood in terms of preference fulfillment and, additionally, are only minor ones (as already Aristotle noted, albeit for quite different reasons). In this case the achievement would still not be a part of my life, but the strivings that are will acquire a different resonance

10 A classic piece in which this idea is formulated is Frankfurt, Harry's ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’ in The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 Richard Brandt's rational desire theory is an example of this approach, see A Theory of the Good and the Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978).Google Scholar

12 Peter Railton's approach is of this kind, see ‘Moral Realism’ and ‘Facts and Values’ in Facts, Values, and Norms (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).Google Scholar

13 Richard Arneson uses a similar line of thought as a general argument against the idea of putting an autonomy constraint on our prudentially relevant preferences, ‘Autonomy and Preference-Formation’ in Coleman, Jules L. & Buchanan, Allen (eds.), In Harm's Way: Essays in Honor of Joel Feinberg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), p. 65.Google Scholar

14 I am grateful to Mozaffar Qizilbash for stressing the importance of this type of problem to me

15 A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 245–50.Google Scholar

16 For a similar approach, although framed in terms of identities instead, see Fraser, Nancy, ‘From Redistribution to Recognition? Dilemmas of Justice in a ‘Postsocialist’ Age’, New Left Review, no. 212 (07/08 1995): 6893Google Scholar