Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T06:27:47.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PEOPLE WITH COMMON PRIORS CAN AGREE TO DISAGREE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2015

HARVEY LEDERMAN*
Affiliation:
New York University
*
*DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NEW YORK UNIVERSITY 5 WASHINGTON PLACE NEW YORK, NY 10003 USA E-mail:[email protected]

Abstract

Robert Aumann presents his Agreement Theorem as the key conditional: “if two people have the same priors and their posteriors for an event A are common knowledge, then these posteriors are equal” (Aumann, 1976, p. 1236). This paper focuses on four assumptions which are used in Aumann’s proof but are not explicit in the key conditional: (1) that agents commonly know, of some prior μ, that it is the common prior; (2) that agents commonly know that each of them updates on the prior by conditionalization; (3) that agents commonly know that if an agent knows a proposition, she knows that she knows that proposition (the “KK” principle); (4) that agents commonly know that they each update only on true propositions. It is shown that natural weakenings of any one of these strong assumptions can lead to countermodels to Aumann’s key conditional. Examples are given in which agents who have a common prior and commonly know what probability they each assign to a proposition nevertheless assign that proposition unequal probabilities. To alter Aumann’s famous slogan: people can “agree to disagree”, even if they share a common prior. The epistemological significance of these examples is presented in terms of their role in a defense of the Uniqueness Thesis: If an agent whose total evidence is E is fully rational in taking doxastic attitude D to P, then necessarily, any subject with total evidence E who takes a different attitude to P is less than fully rational.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aarnio, M. L. (2010). Unreasonable knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aaronson, S. (2005). The complexity of agreement. Symposium on the Theory of Computing, Extended Abstract. Full Version atwww.scottaaronson.com/papers/agree–econ.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics, 4(6), 12361239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R. J. (1987). Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian rationality. Econometrica, 55(1), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R. J. (1998). Common priors: A reply to Gul. Econometrica, 66(4), 929938.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R. J., & Hart, S. (2006). Agreeing on Decisions. The Hebrew University of Jerusalem: Center for the Study of Rationality. Unpublished.Google Scholar
Aumann, R. J., Hart, S., & Perry, M. (2005). Conditioning and the Sure-thing Principle. The Hebrew University of Jerusalem: Center for the Study of Rationality.Google Scholar
Bacharach, M. (1985). Some extensions of a claim of Aumann in an axiomatic model of knowledge. Journal of Economic Theory, 37(1), 167190.Google Scholar
Barelli, P. (2009). Consistency of beliefs and epistemic conditions for nash and correlated equilibria. Games and Economic Behavior, 67, 363375.Google Scholar
Bonanno, G., & Nehring, K. (1997). Agreeing to Disagree: A Survey. Available from: http://www.econ.ucdavis.edu/faculty/bonanno/PDF/agree.pdf.Google Scholar
Bonanno, G., & Nehring, K. (1998). Assessing the truth axiom under incomplete information. Mathematical Social Sciences, 36(1), 329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonanno, G., & Nehring, K. (1999). How to make sense of the common prior assumption under incomplete information. International Journal of Game Theory, 28(3), 409434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Briggs, R. (2009). Distorted reflection. The Philosophical Review, 118(1), 5985.Google Scholar
Cave, J. A. K. (1983). Learning to agree. Economics Letters, 12(2), 147152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, J. (1997). How we can Agree to Disagree. Available from: http://collins.philo.columbia.edu/disagree.pdf.Google Scholar
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowen, T., & Hanson, R. (2014). Are disagreements honest? Journal of Economic Methodology. Forthcoming.Google Scholar
Easwaran, K. (2014). Regularity and infinitesimals. Philosophical Review, 123(1), 141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elga, A. (2007). Reflection and disagreement. Noûs, 41(3), 478502.Google Scholar
Fagin, R., Halpern, J. Y., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. Y. (1995). Reasoning About Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Y. (2000). Characterizing common priors in the form of posteriors. Journal of Economic Theory, 91(2), 127179.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. (2007). Reasonable religious disagreements. In Antony, L., editor. Philosophers without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular, Chap. 17. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 194214.Google Scholar
Friedell, M. F. (1969). On the structure of shared awareness. Behavioral Science, 14(1), 2839.Google Scholar
Geanakoplos, J. (1989). Game Theory without Partitions, and Applications to Speculation and Consensus. Cowles Foundation Discussion Papers 914, Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics, Yale University, New Haven.Google Scholar
Geanakoplos, J. (1994). Common knowledge. In Aumann, R. J., and Hart, S., editors. Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, Vol. 2, Chap. 40. The Netherlands: North Holland, pp. 14371496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, D. (2014). Could KK be OK? Journal of Philosophy, 111(4), 169197.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2010). Staying regular. Unpublished Manuscript.Google Scholar
Halpern, J. Y. (2002). Characterizing the common prior assumption. Journal of Economic Theory, 106(2), 316355.Google Scholar
Halpern, J. Y., & Pucella, R. (2011). Dealing with logical omniscience: Expressiveness and pragmatics. Artificial intelligence, 175(1), 220235.Google Scholar
Hanson, R. (2006). Uncommon priors require origin disputes. Theory and Decision, 61(4), 318328.Google Scholar
Heifetz, A. (1996). Comment on consensus without common knowledge. Journal of Economic Theory, 70(1), 273277.Google Scholar
Heifetz, A. (2006). The positive foundation of the common prior assumption. Games and Economic Behavior, 56(1), 105120.Google Scholar
Hellman, Z. (2012). Deludedly Agreeing to Agree. Abstract in TARK 2013. Full paper unpublished. Available from: http://www.coll.mpg.de/sites/www.coll.mpg.de/files/workshop/DeludedPartitions21.pdf.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, T. (2014). How to be an epistemic permissivist. In Greco, J., Steup, M., and Turri, J., editors. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (second edition). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(3), 115143.Google Scholar
Lederman, H. (2014). Agreement and Equilibrium with Minimal Introspection.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1969). Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Monderer, D., & Samet, D. (1989). Approximating common knowledge with common beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior, 1(2), 170190.Google Scholar
Morris, S. (1995). The common prior assumption in economic theory. Economics and Philosophy, 11(2), 227253.Google Scholar
Moses, Y., & Nachum, G. (1990). Agreeing to disagree after all. In Proceedings of the 3rd conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning and Knowledge, Pacific Grove, CA, pp. 151168.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1988). What we together do. Unpublished Manuscript.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34(4), 517549.Google Scholar
Rubinstein, A., & Wolinsky, A. (1990). On the logic of ‘agreeing to disagree’ type results. Journal of Economic Theory, 51(1), 184193.Google Scholar
Sadzik, T. (2008). Impossibility of Characterizing the Common Prior Assumption. Unpublished Manuscript. Available from: https://files.nyu.edu/ts73/public/.Google Scholar
Samet, D. (1990). Ignoring ignorance and agreeing to disagree. Journal of Economic Theory, 52(1), 190207.Google Scholar
Samet, D. (1992). Agreeing to disagree in infinite information structures. International Journal of Game Theory, 21(3), 213218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samet, D. (2010). Agreeing to disagree: The non-probabilistic case. Games and Economic Behavior, 69(1), 169174.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech and Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (2006). On logics of knowledge and belief. Philosophical Studies, 128, 169199.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. C. (2009). On Hawthorne and Magidor on assertion, context, and epistemic accessibility. Mind, 118(470), 399409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1984). Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 235256.Google Scholar
White, R. (2005). Epistemic permissiveness. Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 445459.Google Scholar
White, R. (2014). Evidence cannot be permissive. In Greco, J., Steup, M., and Turri, J., editors. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (second edition). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 312323.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007). How probable is an infinite sequence of heads? Analysis, 67(3), 173180.Google Scholar