Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T10:55:47.787Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

INDISPENSABILITY ARGUMENTS AND INSTRUMENTAL NOMINALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2012

RICHARD PETTIGREW*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol
*
*DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, UNIVERSITY OF BRISTOL, 43 WOODLAND ROAD, BRISTOL BS8 1TB, UK. E-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

In the philosophy of mathematics, indispensability arguments aim to show that we are justified in believing that mathematical objects exist on the grounds that we make indispensable reference to such objects in our best scientific theories (Quine, 1981a; Putnam, 1979a) and in our everyday reasoning (Ketland, 2005). I wish to defend a particular objection to such arguments called instrumental nominalism. Existing formulations of this objection are either insufficiently precise or themselves make reference to mathematical objects or possible worlds. I show how to formulate the position precisely without making any such reference. To do so, it is necessary to supplement the standard modal operators with two new operators that allow us to shift the locus of evaluation for a subformula. I motivate this move and give a semantics for the new operators.

Type
Research Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114, 223238.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1990). The standard of equality of numbers. In Boolos, G., editor. Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 261277.Google Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2010). There is no easy road to nominalism. Mind, 119(474), 285306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2011). Indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics. In Zalta, E. N., editor. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: CSLI.Google Scholar
Correia, F. (2007). Modality, quantification, and many Vlach-operators. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36(4), 473488.Google Scholar
Fara, M., & Williamson, T. (2005). Counterparts and actuality. Mind, 114(453), 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, G. (1989). Languages of Possibility. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Friedman, J. (2005). Modal platonism: An easy way to avoid ontological commitment to abstract entities. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34(3), 227273.Google Scholar
Hazen, A. (1976). Expressive completeness in modal language. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5, 2546.Google Scholar
Hodes, H. T. (1984a). On modal logics which enrich first-order S5. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 13(4), 423454.Google Scholar
Hodes, H. T. (1984b). Some theorems on the expressive limitations of modal languages. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 13, 1326.Google Scholar
Ketland, J. (2005). More curious inferences. Analysis, 65(1), 1824.Google Scholar
Ketland, J. (2011). Nominalistic adequacy. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 111(2), 201217.Google Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2003). Plural quantification exposed. Noûs, 37(1), 7192.Google Scholar
Melia, J. (1995). On what there’s not. Analysis, 55(4), 223229.Google Scholar
Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109(435), 455479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muller, F. A., & Seevinck, M. P. (2009). Discerning elementary particles. Philosophy of Science, 76, 179200.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1978). Necessity and truth theories. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7, 473500.Google Scholar
Pincock, C. (2007). A role for mathematics in the physical sciences. Noûs, 41(2), 253275.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1979a). Philosophy of logic. In Mathematics, Matter, and Method: Philosophical Papers (second edition), Vol. 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 323357.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1979b). What is mathematical truth. In Mathematics, Matter, and Method: Philosophical Papers (second edition), Vol. 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 6078.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1980a). On what there is. In From a Logical Point of View (second edition). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1980b). Reference and modality. In From a Logical Point of View (second edition). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 139159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1980c). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 2046.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1981a). Success and limits of mathematization. In Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 148155.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1981b). Things and their place in theories. In Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Resnik, M. (1983). Review of Science without Numbers by Hartry Field. Noûs, 17(3), 514519.Google Scholar
Resnik, M. (1988). Second-order logic still wild. Journal of Philosophy, 85, 7587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, G. (2001). Nominalism, naturalism, and epistemic relativism. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 6991.Google Scholar
Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 5263.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar