Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T01:50:55.092Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconsidering Hobbes's Conventionalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

Hobbes's linguistic conventionalism is one of the most obvious themes of his work. But it has not been considered as closely as it should be, given its prominence. I argue that Hobbes reworked quite traditional materials in such a way as to produce a novel doctrine, but that this novelty did not involve him in the implausible claim that issues of scientific truth and proof could be settled simply on the basis of linguistic agreement. Rather, he grounded his conventionalism in the prelinguistic, naturally given experience he called “mental discourse,” and then linked it to the effort to outflank contemporary skepticism. For these reasons, Hobbes's specific form of conventionalism can then be seen to be central both to the limits of his claims and to what he thought could be established with a certainty robust enough to withstand skeptical challenge.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1991

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Theaetetus, 152a, trans. Cornford, F. M., in The Collected Dialogues of Plato ed. Hamilton, Edith and Cairns, Huntingdon (New York: Bollingen Foundation/ Pantheon Books, 1963).Google Scholar

2. De Interpretation 16al9, 27–8, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Barnes, Jonathan (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 1: 25.Google Scholar

3. Long, A. A., Hellenistic Philosophy, 2nd ed. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), pp. 131–39Google Scholar; Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. N., eds., The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), vol. I, Translations of the Principal Sources with Philosophical Commentary, pp. 97101.Google Scholar

4. Empiricus, Sextus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, trans. Bury, R. G. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976), 1: 291.Google Scholar

5. See Popkin, Richard H., The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), esp. pp. 1841.Google Scholar

6. Burnyeat, Myles, ed., The Skeptical Tradition (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983), p. 2.Google Scholar

7. See Mersenne, Marin, Harmonic Universelle, “De la voix,” (Paris: 1636–37; facsimile reprint, Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, 1963), pp. 1011, 61, 65Google Scholar; Descartes, René, The World or Treatise on Light, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, Murdoch, Dugald (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 1: 81Google Scholar; Gassendi, Pierre, Exercises Against the Aristotelians, in The Selected Works of Pierre Gassendi, ed. and trans. Brush, Craig B. (London: Johnson Reprint Corporation, 1972), pp. 88, 90–2Google Scholar; Galilei, Galileo, Two New Sciences, trans, with Introduction and Notes, Drake, Stillman (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974), pp. 154–55Google Scholar; Galilei, Galileo, The Assayer, in Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, trans, with Introduction and Notes, Drake, Stillman (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1957), pp. 274–5.Google Scholar

8. Hacking, Ian, The Emergence of Probability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), p. 47.Google Scholar

9. Ashworth, E. J., “Traditional Logic,” in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, ed. Schmitt, Charles B., Skinner, Quentin, Kessler, Eckhard, and Kraye, Jill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 155–57.Google Scholar

10. Ibid., p. 156.

11. I have tried to outline a broad framework for the antagonisms involved here in Hanson, Donald W., “The Meaning of Demonstration' in Hobbes's Science,” History of Political Thought 11 (Winter 1990): 587626.Google Scholar

12. Illuminating accounts of renaissance magical thought and practice and natural philosophy are provided in Walker, D. P., Spiritual and Demonic Magic: From Ficino to Campanella (London: The Warburg Institute/University of London, 1958)Google Scholar; Walker, D. P., The Ancient Theology: Studies in Christian Platonism from the Fifteenth to the Eighteenth Century (London: Duckworth, 1972)Google Scholar; and Yates, Frances A., Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition (Chicago: University of Chicag Press, 1964).Google Scholar The magistral work of Lenoble, Robert, Mersenne ou La Naissance du Mécanisme (Paris: Librairie Philosophique, J. Vrin, 1943), esp. pp. 83167Google Scholar, emphasizes the aim in the new philosophy of combatting renaissance animism and magic. Thomas, Keith, Religion and the Decline of Magic (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1971)Google Scholar demonstrates the pervasiveness and the tenacity of magical thought and activity in early modern England.

13. See, for example, Knowlson, James, Universal Language Schemes in England and France 1600–1800 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1975), esp. pp. 7111Google Scholar; Fraser, Russell, The Language of Adam(New York: Columbia University Press, 1977)Google Scholar; Cohen, Murray, Sensible Words (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977)Google Scholar; Salmon, Vivian, The Study of Language in 17th-Century England (Amsterdam: John Benjamins B.V., 1979), esp. Part III, pp. 129206Google Scholar; Debus, Allen G., Robert Fludd and His Philosophical Key (New York: Science History Publications, 1979), pp. 149Google Scholar; Katz, David S., “The Language of Adam in Seventeenth Century England,” in History & Imagination, ed. Lloyd-jones, Hugh, Pearl, Valerie, and Worden, Blair (London: Duckworth, 1981), pp. 132–45.Google Scholar

14. Leibniz, G. W., New Essays on Human Understanding, trans, and ed. Remnant, Peter and Bennett, Jonathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), book 3, chap. 2, pp. 278–87.Google Scholar A very helpful commentary in this context is Walker, D. P., “Leibniz and Language,” Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 35 (1972): 294307CrossRefGoogle Scholar; the general philosophical importance of the topic is emphasized in Cassirer, Ernst, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1955), 1: 117–76Google Scholar, esp. pp. 129–32 on Leibniz's conception of a universal character.

15. See, for example, Whelan, Frederick G., “Language and Its Abuses in Hobbes' Political Philosophy,” American Political Science Review 75 (1981): 5975CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ball, Terence, “Hobbes's Linguistic Turn,” Polity 17 (1985): 739–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Peters, Richard, Hobbes (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1956), pp. 119–37Google Scholar; Watkins, J. W. N., Hobbes's System of Ideas (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1968), pp. 138–62Google Scholar; Ross, George Macdonald, “Hobbes's Two Theories of Meaning,” in The Figural and the Literal: Problems of Language in the History of Science and Philosophy, 1630–1800, ed. Benjamin, Andrew E., Cantor, Geoffrey N., and Christie, John R. R. (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1987), esp., pp. 4653Google Scholar; Hungerland, Isabel C. and Vick, George R., “Hobbes's Theory of Language, Speech, and Reasoning,” in Hobbes, Thomas, Computatio Sive Logica/Logic, Part I of De Corpore, trans, and commentary by Martinich, Aloysius, ed. with an Introductory Essay, by Hungerland, Isabel C. and Vick, George R. (New York: Abaris Books, 1981), pp. 15148.Google Scholar

16. See, for example, Hacking, Ian, Representing and Intervening (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 75111CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dummett, M. A. E., “What Is a Theory of Meaning?” in Mind and Language, ed. Guttenplan, Samuel (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), pp. 97138Google Scholar; Strawson, P. F., Logico-Linguistic Papers (London: Methuen, 1971), pp. 170–89Google Scholar; Putnam, Hilary, Mind, Language and Reality, Philosophical Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), 2: 215–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar; on some of the important differences from seventeenth-century signification theory, see Hacking, Ian, Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? (CambridgeCambridge University Press, 1975), esp. pp. 1553, 157–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17. Spade, Paul Vincent, “The Semantics of Terms,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Kretzmann, Norman, Kenny, Anthony, Pinborg, Jan, Stump, Eleonore (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 188.Google Scholar

18. The World or Treatise on Light, in Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, , vol. I, p. 81.Google Scholar

19. It is true enough that in Hobbes, like many other seventeenth century authors, the much more fully developed theories of signification (and supposition) that are to be found in late scholasticism have been replaced by a less complex conception of the problems of logic and language. Many of the changes are helpfully discussed in Ashworth, E. J., “The Eclipse of Medieval Logic,” in Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, pp. 787–96Google Scholar, and in Lisa Jardine, “H manism and the Teaching of Logic,” ibid., pp. 797–807, and W. Keith Percival, “Changes in the Approach to Language,” ibid., pp. 808–17.

20. Leviathan, chap. 4, p. 39 (E.W., 3:28). Initial page references are to Leviathan, ed. Oakeshott, Michael, with an Introduction by Peters, Richard S. (New York: Collier Books, 1962)Google Scholar, followed by citation of the standard edition: The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, ed. SirMolesworth, William (London: John Bohn, 1839–45)Google Scholar, cited hereafter as E. W., followed by volume number and page. Chapter references will also be given for Leviathan because so many editions are currently in use.

21. Leviathan, chap. 3, p. 28; chap. 4, p. 34 (E. W., 3: 11, 19); The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic, ed. Tonnies, Ferdinand; second edition, with a new Introduction by Goldsmith, M. M. (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1969), p. 13Google Scholar; hereafter cited as Elements.

22. Leviathan, chap. 4, p. 34 (E.W., 3: 19).

23. Elements, p. 64. Emphasis added.

24. Leviathan, chap. 4, p. 34 (E.W., 3: 19–20).

25. On Christian Doctrine, trans, with an introduction by Robertson, D. W. Jr. (New York: Macmillan, 1958), p. 34.Google Scholar

26. Leviathan, chap. 3, p. 30 (E.W., 3: 15).

27. E.W.,1: 14–15.

28. On Christian Doctrine, pp. 34–5

29. De Interpretation 16a 4–9.

30. This is very ably set out in Whelan, “Language and Its Abuses in Hobbes' Political Philosophy.”

31. For an illuminating discussion of this point, see Hacking, , Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? esp. pp. 1533.Google Scholar

32. Rules for the Direction of the Mind, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, I: 48.Google Scholar The entire discussion of Rule Twelve is important in this connection.

33. E. W.,1: 36.

34. Ibid., p. 5.

35. Ibid., p. 3.

36. Ibid., pp. 56–57.

37. Leviathan, chap. 4, p. 37 (E. W., 3: 25).

38. Ibid., chap. 25, p. 194 (E. W., 3: 245).

39. Useful texts and commentaries on the ten modes are available in Annas, Julia and Barnes, Jonathan, The Modes of Scepticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40. Exercises Against the Aristotelians, in Brush, , Gassendi, p. 104.Google Scholar

41. Leviathan, chap. 31, pp. 267–8 (E. W., 3: 353–54).

42. The importance of this idea has been well brought out in Tully, James, A Discourse on Property: John Locke and His Adversaries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)Google Scholar; Pérez-ramos, Antonio, Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), esp. pp. 4862Google Scholar; Funkenstein, Amos, Theology and the Scientific Imagination (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), pp. 290345Google Scholar, which shows the central role of the idea in the new science of the seventeenth century; Arendt, Hannah, The Human Condition (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1959), esp. pp. 268–78.Google Scholar

43. Harmonie Universelle, III, “Nouvelles observations physiques et mathematiques,” p. 8.

44. E. W., 7: 88.

45. Principles of Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, I: 289.Google Scholar

46. De Cive, p. 374 (E. W., 2: 303–4). Initial page references are to the translation in Man and Citizen, ed. with an Introduction by Gert, Bernard (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1972).Google Scholar

47. Third Set of Objections, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, II: 125–26.Google Scholar

48. Arnauld, Antoine, The Art of Thinking: Port Royal Logic, trans. Dickoff, James and James, Patricia (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964).Google Scholar

49. Third Set of Objections with the Author's Replies, p. 126.

50. Williams, Bernard, Descartes: The Project of Pure Inquiry (New York: Penguin Books, 1978), p. 20.Google Scholar

51. E. W., 7: 81.

52. Third Set of Objections, p. 128.

53. Leviathan, chap. 34, pp. 286–8 (E. W., 3: 380–3).

54. E. W., 1: 36.

55. De Cive, p. 374 (E. W., 2: 303–4).

56. Leviathan, chap. 4, p. 35 (E. W., 3: 21).

57. Elements, p. 25.

58. Leviathan, chap. 31, p. 265 (E. W., 3: 350).

59. Elements, p. 64.

60. This is a point very well treated in Sorell, Tom, Hobbes (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1986), pp. 4750.Google Scholar

61. Leviathan, chap. 42, p. 375 (E. W., 3: 510).

62. E. W., 1: 70.

63. Ibid., p. 84.

64. E. W., 7: 78.

65. E. W., 1: xi, 531.

66. E. W., 7: 88.

67. Ibid., pp. 183–84.

68. Correspondance du P. Marin Mersenne, ed. Waard, Cornells De and Beaulieu, Armand (Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, 1980), 14: 232–33.Google Scholar

69. Seventh Set of Objections with Replies, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, II: 374.

70. De Cive, p. 367 (E. W., 2: 295–96).

71. This issue is discussed at length in Mcneilly, F. S., The Anatomy of Leviatha (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1968), pp. 2958.Google Scholar

72. Ibid., p. 373 (E. W., 2: 302–303).

73. Ibid., (E. W., 2: 303).

74. E. W., 1: 74.

75. Ibid., p. 411.

76. Leviathan, chap. 42, p. 375 (E. W., 3: 510).

77. Ibid., chap. 4, p. 34 (E. W., 3: 19–20); E. W., 1: 14–15, 30.

78. Ibid., chap. 2, pp. 25–7; chap. 4, p. 40; chap. 25, p. 194; chap. 32, p. 271; “A Review, and Conclusion,”p. 509 (E. W.,3: 7–10, 28, 245, 359–60, 710); Elements, pp. 1–2, 6–7; E. W., 1: 55–57.

79. De Cive, p. 374 (E. W., 2: 304).

80. Leviathan, , “A Review, and Conclusion,” p. 511Google Scholar (E. W., 3: 713).

81. E. W., 7: 344.

82. Leviathan, chap. 15, p. 122; chap. 18, pp. 139–40 (E. W., 3: 144, 167–68).

83. De Cive, p. 249 (E. W., 2: 156).

84. Ibid., pp. 364–5 (E. W., 2: 293).

85. Leviathan, chap. 30, p. 248 (E. W., 3: 323).

86. De Cive, p. 262 (E. W., 2: 171); see also Elements, p. 183; Leviathan, chap. 30, pp. 252–53 (E. W., 3: 331–32).

87. Elements, p. 183.

88. De Cive, pp. 262–3 (E. W., 2: 171–72).

89. Leviathan, chap. 43, p. 427 (E. W., 3: 589); see also, ibid., chap. 29, p. 239; chap. 32, p. 272, chap. 36, pp. 312–13; chap. 42, pp. 362–3, 375, 380, 411 (E. W., 3: 312, 360. 420–21, 491–93, 510, 518, 565).

90. Ibid., chap. 4, p. 33 (E. W., 3: 18).

91. Cive, De, “The Author's Preface to the Reader,” pp. 95–8(E. W., 2: ix-xiv).Google Scholar

92. Leviathan, chap. 11, p. 83 (E. W., 3: 90).

93. Elements, p. 20.

94. Leviathan, chap. 5, p. 42 (E. W., 3: 31).

95. Ibid., chap. 47, p. 502; chap. 26, p. 206; chap. 46, p. 493 (E. W., 3: 700, 263, 688).

96. Elements, p. 188.

97. De Cive, p. 268 (E. W., 2: 178).

98. Leviathan, chap. 37, p. 323 (E. W., 3: 435); emphasis added.

99. De Cive, p. 345 (E. W., 2: 269); see also, ibid., pp. 178, 306 (E. W., 2: 77, 224).

100. Ibid., pp. 367–68 (E. W., 2: 296).

101. Ibid., p. 148 (E. W., 2: 44).

102. Leviathan, chap. 30, p. 249 (E. W., 3: 325–26).

103. Elements, p. 1.

104. Ibid., p. 24.

105. Leviathan, “Author's Introduction,” p. 20 (E. W., 3: xii).

106. De Homing, p. 40. Reference is to the edition found in Man and Citizen, ed. Gert, Bernard, trans. Wood, Charles T., Scott-craig, T. S. K., and Gert, Bernard (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1972).Google Scholar