Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T06:06:40.147Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Marx and the Modern City: Public Life and the Problem of Personality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

In recent years many scholars have contributed to the development of Marxist analyses of urban political economy. At the same time, a smaller number of social and political theorists have examined Marx's political theory and identified his theory of public and private life as a central component of his politics. Too often, Marxist analyses of urban political economy do not fully incorporate Marx's political theory. Analyses of Marx's politics, on the other hand, tend to overlook the dimensions of the modern city which illuminate his theory of public and private. This article brings together Marx's urban theory and political theory and suggests that they are, in fact, very much intertwined.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Sennett, R., The Fall of Public Man (New York, 1977), p. 252.Google Scholar

2 Arendt, Hannah, Between Past and Present (Cleveland, 1963)Google Scholar; Gilbert, A., Marx's Politics: Communists and Citizens (New Brunswick, New Jersey, 1981)Google Scholar; Mewes, H., “On the Concept of Politics in the Early Works of Karl Marx,” Social Research, 43 (1976), 276294Google Scholar; Schwartz, N. L., “Distinction between Public and Private Life: Marx on the Zöon Politikon,” Political Theory, 7 (1979), 245266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Schwartz, “Distinction between Public and Private Life,” p. 262.

4 Van Gunsteren, H., “Public and Private,” Social Research, 46 (1979), 261.Google Scholar

5 Marx, Karl, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (New York: International Publishers, 1964), p. 234.Google Scholar

6 Wisks, J., “Marx on Authenticity and the Liberal View of Man,” in Liberalism and the Modern Polity: Essays in Contemporary Political Theory, ed. McGrath, M. J. (New York, 1978), pp. 2131.Google Scholar

7 Marx, K. and Engels, F., Works, 20 vols. (New York: International Publishers, 1975), 1:220.Google Scholar

8 Draper, H., ed., Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: Writings on the Paris Commune (New York, 1971), p. 153.Google Scholar

9 Schwartz, “Distinction between Public and Private Life,” p. 248.

10 Ibid., pp. 257–58; see also Gilbert, Marx's Politics, p. 98.

11 Prawer, S. S., Karl Marx and World Literature (New York, 1978).Google Scholar

12 Ibid., p. 313.

13 Jameson, F., Marxism and Form (Princeton, 1971), p. 336.Google Scholar

14 Trilling, Lionel, Sincerity and Authenticity (Cambridge, Mass., 1971), p. 20.Google Scholar

15 Lefebvre, H., La pensée marxiste et la ville (Paris, 1978).Google Scholar

16 Saunders, P., Social Theory and the Urban Question (New York, 1981).Google Scholar

17 Marcus, S., Engels, Manchester, and the Working Class (New York, 1974).Google Scholar

18 Orwell, George, The Road to Wigan Pier (New York, 1961), pp. 153154.Google Scholar

19 Marx and Engels, Works, 4:418.

20 Tucker, R. C., ed., The Marx-Engels Reader (New York, 1978), p. 149.Google Scholar

21 Elliott, J. E., Marx and Engels on Economy, Society and Politics: Essential Readings with Editorial Commentary (Santa Monica, 1981).Google Scholar

22 Tucker, Marx-Engels Reader, p. 185.

23 Marx and Engels, Works, 5:371.

24 Marx, Karl, Capital (New York: International Publishers, 1967), 1:333.Google Scholar

25 Ibid., pp. 325–26.

26 Tucker, Marx-Engels Reader, pp. 413–14.

27 Ibid., p. 416.

28 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 6:210211.Google Scholar

29 See Sennett, Fall of Public Man. Marx criticizes the tendency to perceive society and impersonal social forces in terms of personality and its symbolization. In the Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Law, Marx takes issue with Hegel's understanding of state functions in terms of individual personality, his bifurcation of human into individual and citizen, his confusion of the individual and social attributes of the monarch. In On the Jewish Question, Marx attacks the limitations of political emancipation in terms of that same human division and the imposition of “private man” onto the realm of “public man” and the establishment of the rights of private man — to the exclusion of public man — by the political state (Marx, and Engels, , Works, 3:155)Google Scholar. In The Poverty of Philosophy, he criticizes Proudhon as one who “personifies society” (Ibid., 6:152). Marx and Engels explain in The Communist Manifesto that capital is “not a personal power, it is a social power” (Tucker, Marx-Engels Reader, p. 485). Nor is a worker's labor power bought by a capitalist. Rather “he belongs … to the capitalist class” (Ibid., p. 205). These examples illustrate Marx's effort to maintain a distinction between the terms of public and private life and to discourage the tendency to superimpose private imagery onto public life.

30 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 1:171.Google Scholar

31 Ibid., 1:110–11. Thus, the censorship represented the confusion of public and private life. Public life is the realm of the impersonal, law, which is represented under the censorship as private whim. The censorship also persecutes what are public, impersonal ideas, and treats them as if they were “full of personal intrigue and subjective vileness” (Ibid., 1:122). Public action is self-distanced, but the censorship threatens public speech and action and inappropriately invades the private lives and personalities of citizens.

32 “The people sinks partly into political superstition, partly into political disbelief, or completely turning away from political life, become a rabble of private individuals” (Ibid., 1:168). Here Marx makes explicit the effects of the failure to distinguish clearly between public and private, i.e., the inability to recognize and defend one's interest, a denial of the public realm, and the failure of political imagination.

34 Ibid., p. 175.

35 Ibid., p. 177.

36 Ibid., p. 243.

37 Ibid., p. 334.

38 Ibid., p. 337.

39 Ibid., p. 354.

40 Ibid., 5:214–15.

41 Ibid., p. 438.

42 Ibid., pp. 432–33.

43 Ibid., p. 401.

44 Ibid., p. 394.

45 See Sennett, R. and Cobb, J., The Hidden Injuries of Class (New York, 1977).Google Scholar

46 For another view, see Diggins, John P., “Reification and the Cultural Hegemony of Capitalism: The Perspectives of Marx and Veblen,” Social Research, 44 (1977), 354383.Google Scholar

47 Sennett, Fall of Public Man, p. 145; Tucker, Marx-Engels Reader, pp. 319–29.

48 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 3:324.Google Scholar

49 Ibid., p. 325.

50 Ibid., p. 324.

51 Ibid., 5:230.

52 Ibid., 3:309.

53 Tucker, Marx-Engels Reader, p. 163.

54 Ibid., p. 70.

55 Sennett, Fall of Public Man, p. 252.

56 Gilbert, Marx's Politics, pp. 90, 245, 266–67.

57 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 1:220; 5:255.Google Scholar

58 Ibid., 1:220–21.

59 Ibid., p. 144.

60 Marx, K. in Draper, H., Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution (New York, 1977), p. 108.Google Scholar

61 Sennett, Fall of Public Man, pp. 252–55.

62 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 1:387.Google Scholar

63 Ibid., p. 389.

65 Ibid., 6:56.

67 Padover, S. K., ed., The Letters of Karl Marx (Englewood Cliffs, 1979), p. 292.Google Scholar

68 Ibid., p. 320.

70 Gilbert, Marx's Politics, pp. 61, 80, 122–23.

71 Padover, Letters of Marx, p. 52.

72 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 1:468.Google Scholar

73 Berman, M., All That Is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of Modernity (New York, 1982), p. 95.Google Scholar

74 Boyte, Harry C., The Backyard Revolution: Understanding the New Citizen Movement (Philadelphia, 1980), pp. 2122ff.Google Scholar

75 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 1:397.Google Scholar

76 Ibid., p. 301.

77 Ibid., 3:201.

78 Gilbert, Marx's Politics, pp. 16, 80, 129, 131.

79 Marx, and Engels, , Works, 5:217.Google Scholar

80 Ibid., 4:52–53.

81 Ibid., 3:313.

82 Sennett, R., The Uses of Disorder: Personal Identity and City Life (New York, 1970), p. 174.Google Scholar