Article contents
Simone Weil on the Injustice of Rights-Based Doctrines
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Abstract
This paper explores Simone Weil's objections to a philosophy grounded on human rights. Weil thinks impersonal justice cannot be expressed in terms of personal rights. Rights, for Weil, are personal possessions; they are claimed or borne by some subject or person (me, you, her or them). The right or the just, however, is not susceptible to possession. When one substitutes a personal pronoun for the definite article before the word right (my right or their right instead of the right), justice is articulated in the manner of liberal contractualism but is biased against a notion of impersonal justice which Weil champions. The incompatibility of Weil's understanding of justice and a rights-based notion of justice is the subject-matter investigated in this article.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1986
References
Notes
1 McCloskey, H. J., “Rights,” Philosophical Quarterly, 15 (1965), 115–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar argues that rights should be understood as entitlements to something rather than claims against someone. But see Feinberg, J., Rights, Justice and the Bound of Liberty (Princeton: University Press, 1980), 151–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar for a refutation of this position.
2 For a defense of welfare-rights see Gerwirth, A., “The Basis and Content of Human RightsGoogle Scholar and Okin, S. M., “Liberty and Welfare: Some Issues in Human Rights Theory” in Human Rights, Nomos 23, ed. Pennock, J. R. and Chapman, J. W. (New York: University Press, 1981)Google Scholar. Option-rights are championed by Nozick, R., Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974)Google Scholar and more moderately by Hart, H. A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon, 1963).Google Scholar
3 Weil, S., “Human Personality” in Selected Essays 1934–43, trans. Rees, R. (London: Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 9.Google Scholar
4 Pufendorf, S., Of the Law of Nature and Nations, trans. Kennet, B. (London: Sare, 1717), I.i.16.Google Scholar
5 “Human Personality,” pp. 21–22.Google Scholar
6 Ibid., pp. 22–3, 28–9; Waiting for God, trans. Craufurd, E. (New York: Putnam, 1951), p. 120.Google Scholar
7 “Human Personality,” p. 20.Google Scholar
8 Locke, J., The Second Treatise, sec. 27Google Scholar, in Two Treatises of Government, ed. Laslett, P. (New York: Mentor, 1965), pp. 328–29.Google Scholar
9 Andrew, E. “Inalienable Right, Alienable Property and Freedom of Choice: Locke and Nozick on the Alienation of Labour,” Canadian Journal of Political Science 18 (1985), 329–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
10 First and Last Notebooks, trans. Rees, R. (London: Oxford University Press, 1970), p. 346.Google Scholar
11 The Need for Roots, trans. Wills, A. (Boston: Beacon, 1960), p. 5.Google Scholar
12 “Human Personality,” pp. 19–20.Google Scholar
13 The Need for Roots, pp. 278.Google Scholar
14 Maritain, J., The Rights of Man and the Natural Law (London: Bles, 1958)Google Scholar and Mounier, E.'s Personalism (Notre Dame Press, 1970)Google Scholar, are representative of the personalist doctrine criticized by Weil.
15 Finnis, J., Natural Law and Human Rights (Cambridge: University Press 1980)Google Scholar, recognizes the decisive change from premodern natural law doctrines of “the right” to modern rights doctrine (p. 206). In asserting absolute rights, Finnis rejects the modern tendency to liberate rights from subjection to the common good, rejects the conceptual opposition of law and rights, and rejects the interpretation of rights as liberties or options (which protect choices rather than guide conduct).
16 “Human Personality,” pp. 19–20Google Scholar; Waiting for God, p. 139.Google Scholar
17 Waiting for God, p. 139.Google Scholar
18 Ibid., p. 140.
19 Pufendorf, , Of the Law of Nature and Nations, II, vi. 6.Google Scholar
20 Passmore, J., “Civil Justice and Its Rivals” in Justice, ed. Kamenka, E. and Tay, A. E. S. (London: Edward Arnold, 1979), p. 47.Google Scholar
21 Waiting for God, p. 144.Google Scholar
22 Ibid., pp. 146–48; “Human Personality,” p. 28.Google Scholar
23 Ibid., p. 21.
24 Ibid.
25 Spinoza, B., A Theological-Political Treatise, chap. 19, in The Chief Works, trans. Elwes, R. H. M. (New York: Dover, 1951), 1:237, 264.Google Scholar
26 Waiting for God, p. 156Google Scholar; The Need for Roots, pp. 228–29.Google Scholar
27 Hobbes, T., De Cive in The English Works, ed. Molesworth, W. (London: John Bohm, 1839), 2:62Google Scholar. Also see Leviathan, chap. 15.
28 First and Last Notebooks, p. 19.Google Scholar
29 Ibid., p. 6.
30 Ibid., p. 17; The Need for Roots, pp. 180–81.Google Scholar
31 The Need for Roots, p. 3.Google Scholar
32 Ibid.
33 Feinberg, , Rights, p. 139.Google Scholar
34 Aiken, H. D., “Rights, Human and Otherwise,” The Monist, 52 (1968), 507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
35 Shrag, F., “Children: Their Rights and Needs” in Whose Child? ed. Aiken, W. and LaFollette, H. (Totowata, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams, 1980), pp. 237–38.Google Scholar
36 The Need for Roots, p. 3.Google Scholar
37 Ibid., pp. 3–4.
38 “Human Personality,” p. 21.Google Scholar
39 House of Representatives, Committee on Human Rights and International Organizations, Human Rights in Nicaragua, 15 09 1983, pp. 108–10.Google Scholar
40 Ibid., pp. 120–32.
41 “Human Personality.” p. 17.Google Scholar
42 Ibid., p. 18.
43 Narveson, J., “Human Rights: Which, If Any, Are There?”Google Scholar in Pennock, and Chapman, , Human Rights, p. 193.Google Scholar
44 The Need for Roots, p. 179.Google Scholar
45 Hobbes, T., Leviathan (Oxford: Blackwell, 1960), pp. 142–43.Google Scholar
46 The Need for Roots, p. 161.Google Scholar
47 “Plan for an Organization of Front-line Nurses” in The Simone Weil Reader, ed. Panichas, G. (New York: Dorset, 1981), pp. 96–105.Google Scholar
48 The Need for Roots, p. 164.Google Scholar
49 Locke, , Second Treatise, sec. 168.Google Scholar
50 Ibid., sec. 208, 230.
51 The Need for Roots, p. 228.Google Scholar
52 Locke, J., A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. Gough, J. W. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1966), pp. 139Google Scholar; cf. 135, 138, 154.
53 The Need for Roots, p. 127.Google Scholar
54 Kant, I., The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, trans. Ladd, J. (New York: Liberal Arts, 1965), pp. 84–89.Google Scholar
55 The Need for Roots, p. 4.Google Scholar
56 Ecrits de Londres (Paris: Gallimard, 1957), p. 170. My translation.Google Scholar
57 Ibid., p. 171.
58 Feinberg, , Rights, p. 151.Google Scholar
59 Weil, S., The Notebooks, trans. Wills, A. (New York: Putnam, 1956), p. 152.Google Scholar
60 Boxhill, B., “Self-respect and Protest,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6 (1976), 69.Google Scholar
61 See Lichtheim, G., “Simone Weil” in Collected Essays (New York: Viking Press, 1973), pp. 467–68Google Scholar; O'Brien, C. C., “Patriotism and the Need for Roots” in Simone Weil: Interpretations of a Life, ed. White, G. A. (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981), pp. 95–98, 110.Google Scholar
62 O'Brien, , “Patriotism,” p. 96.Google Scholar
63 The Need for Roots, p. 33.Google Scholar
64 Ibid., pp. 28–29.
65 Ibid., p. 32.
66 Ibid., p. 30.
67 Ibid., p. 28.
68 Ibid., p. 23.
69 Ibid., p. 26.
70 Ibid., pp. 39; cf. 26–27.
71 Ibid., pp. 38–39.
72 Ibid., p. 39.
73 Ibid., pp. 80, 85.
- 7
- Cited by