Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T10:41:24.915Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Secular Political Culture: Three Views

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

Modern politics is often said to be fundamentally secular, and many who do not say so may find the proposition too obvious to need stating. In a sense, perhaps, it is obvious; but what does it mean? No doubt it is valuable to have a term to describe a society without religion, or one in which common affairs are not religiously directed. But it is odd to suppose that the sheer absence of a characteristic can serve effectively to define a type of society; for one thing, we would need to know what kind of religion was absent, or in what respects religion was lacking, before we could assess what significance this absence could be said to have; for another, to define a society by the absence of a certain feature would seem to point to an intense preoccupation with its presence or absence, yet it is precisely the lack of preoccupation with religion that is held to characterize secular man. A fortiori, it is odd to suppose that secularity not only serves to distinguish broadly among kinds of societies—those with and without religion—but that it also determines the principal features of social and political behavior, to such an extent that one can speak of a secular political culture as a distinct and well-marked type.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1975

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Martin, David, “Towards Eliminating the Concept of Secularisation,” in Penguin Survey of the Social Sciences 1965, ed. Gould, J. (Harmondsworth, 1965), pp. 169182Google Scholar.

2 Knoepflmacher, U. C., Religious Humanism and the Victorian Novel (Princeton, 1965), p. 5Google Scholar.

3 Ibid., p. 29.

4 Ibid., pp. 10, 14.

5 Meland, B. E., The Secularization of Modern Cultures (New York, 1966), 14Google Scholar.

6 Feuerbach, Ludwig, The Essence of Christianity (London, 1854), pp. 1213Google Scholar.

7 Gomte, Auguste, Système de politique positive, 1851 edition (Paris, 1929), I; 339Google Scholar.

8 Cf. Mill, John Stuart, Auguste Comte and Positivism (1865; Ann Arbor, 1961), pp. 149ff.Google Scholar

9 Comte, , Système de politique positive, I: 333Google Scholar.

10 Cited in Knoepflmacher, , Victorian Novel, p. 6Google Scholar (emphasis added).

11 Comte, , Système de politique positive, I: 335Google Scholar.

12 Feuerbach, , Essence of Christianity, p. 221Google Scholar.

13 Comte, , Système de politique positive1, I: 342344, 746Google Scholar.

14 Ibid., p. 329.

15 Cf. MacIntyre, Alasdair, Secularization and Moral Change (London, 1967), pp. 1922Google Scholar, 69.

16 “The human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations”; 6th Thesis on Feuerbach.

17 MacIntyre, , Secularization and Moral Change, p. 30Google Scholar.

18 Ibid., p. 75.

19 Ibid., p. 7.

20 “What each individual wills is obstructed by everyone else, and what emerges is something that no one willed”: Engels, Letter to Bloch, Joseph, in The Marx-Engeh Reader1, ed. Tucker, R. C. (New York, 1972), pp. 640642Google Scholar.

21 MacIntyre, , Secularization and Moral Change, p. 52Google Scholar.

22 de Saint-Simon, H., Oeuvres (Paris, 1966), II: 195200Google Scholar; Proudhon, Pierre Joseph, Philosophie du progrès (1853; Paris, 1946)Google Scholar; for Sorel, see my Rationalism and Commitment in Sorell,” Journal of the History of Ideas, XXXIV (1973), 405420Google Scholar.

23 Sartre, J. P., Critique de la raison dialectique (Paris, 1960), pp. 60111Google Scholar.

24 “If man, by dint of his knowledge and inventive genius, has subdued the forces of nature, the latter avenge themselves upon him by subjecting him, in so far as he employs them, to a veritable despotism independent of all social organisation”; Engels, , “On Authority,” in Marx-Engels Reader, ed. p, Tucker. 663Google Scholar.

25 “Freedom in this field can only consist in socialised man, the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control … and achieving this … under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their human nature”: Marx, , Capital, in Reader, Marx-Engels, ed. Tucker, p. 320Google Scholar.

26 For an explicit use of the contractual model in connection with this theme, see Proudhon, , Philosophic du progrès, p. 124Google Scholar.

27 Laski, H. J., Authority in the Modern State (New Haven, 1919), pp. 23ff.Google Scholar

28 Meland, , Secularization of Modern Cultures, pp. 39Google Scholar, 49. See also Maritain's discussion of the strictly secular faith appropriate to the political order, in Man and the State (1951: Chicago, 1956), pp. 108114Google Scholar.

29 Apter, David E., The Politics of Modernization (Chicago, 1956), p. 22Google Scholar.

30 Almond, Gabriel, “Comparative Political Systems” (Journal of Politics, 1956, pp. 391409)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, in Comparative Politics, eds, Macridis, R. C. and Brown, B. E. (Homewood, 1961), p. 40Google Scholar.

31 Apter, Politics of Modernization, p. 303.

32 Ibid., p. 68.

33 Ibid., p. 267.

34 Sartori, G., “Politics, Ideology, and Belief Systems,” American Political Science Review, 63 (1969), 398411CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35 Durkheim, Emile, The Division of Labour in Society (New York, 1969), p. 172Google Scholar. Gf. Richter, Melvin, “Durkheim's Politics and Political Theory,” in Emile Durkheim, ed. Wolff, K. H. (Columbia, 1960), p. 180Google Scholar; also Lukes, S., Emile Durkheim (London, 1973), pp. 474476Google Scholar.

36 Apter, , Politics of Modernization, p. 32Google Scholar.

37 Ibid., p. 22.

38 Ibid., p. 30.

39 Ibid., p. 28.

40 See Barnard, F. M. and Porter, J. N., “Discontent and Political Development,” Proceedings of the Canadian Political Science Association, Calgary, 1968, especially pp. 3845Google Scholar.

41 Almond, , “Comparative Political Systems,” pp. 4047Google Scholar.

42 Ibid., p. 47.

43 For Weber's writings on religion, see Gerth, H. H. and Mills, C. Wright, From Max Weber (New York, 1958), pp. 267359Google Scholar; also Giddens, A., Capitalism and Modern Social Theory (Cambridge, 1971)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Hume, David, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779: New York, 1948), pp. 3141Google Scholar.

45 There is an unexplained contradiction between Proudfaon's doctrine of the collective force of humanity, expressed in Philosophic du progrès and in the closing sentences of La Guerre et la paix, and his forthright rejection of any such view of “man,” in favor of a mutualist ethic, in Systième des contradictions èconomiques and De la justice.

46 Popper, K. R., The Open Society and Its Enemies (London, 1962), p. 163Google Scholar; cf. Apter, , Politics of Modernization, p. 26Google Scholar.

47 Kuhn, T. S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago, 1962)Google Scholar.

48 Popper, K. R., Objective Knowledge (Oxford, 1972), pp. 106Google Scholar ff. For a fuller discussion, see my “The ‘Great Society’ and the ‘Open Society,’” Canadian Journal of Political Science (forthcoming).

49 Systèime de politique positive, I; 331 (emphasis addted).