Article contents
The Sandelian Republic and the Encumbered Self
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 18 September 2015
Abstract
In Democracy's Discontent, Michael Sandel argues for a revival of the republican tradition in order to counteract the pernicious effects of contemporary liberalism. As in his earlier work, Sandel charges that liberals who embrace the ideals of political neutrality and the unencumbered self are engaged in a self–subverting enterprise, for no society that lives by these ideals can sustain itself. Sandel is right to endorse the republican emphasis on forming citizens and cultivating civic virtues. By opposing liberalism as vigorously as he does, however, he engages in a self–subverting enterprise of his own. That is, Sandel is in danger of undercutting his position by threatening the liberal principles upon which he implicitly relies. This danger is greatest when he presses his case against the unencumbered self, when he appeals to the obligations of membership, and when he treats republicanism and liberalism as adversaries rather than allies.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1999
References
James Farr's invitation to participate in a panel on “Sandel and His Critics” prompted me to write this paper and present an earlier version of it at the 1998 meeting of Midwest Political Science Association. I am grateful to Professor Farr and to Terence Ball, the anonymous referees for The Review of Politics, and my colleagues in the ASUMPL reading group, especially Avital Simhony, for their advice and encouragement.
1. Sandel, Michael, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982; 2nd ed. 1998)Google Scholar; MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981)Google Scholar. Further references to Liberalism and the Limits of Justice appear in the text, in parentheses, as LLJ.
2. Sandel, Michael, ed., Liberalism and Its Critics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984)Google Scholar; Sandel, , “The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self,” Political Theory 12 (1984): 81–96 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and reprinted in Avineri, Shlomo and de-Shalit, Avner, eds., Communitarianism and Individualism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 12–28 Google Scholar, from which I shall quote. Further references to “The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self” appear in the text, in parentheses, as “PR.”
3. Sandel, Michael, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. ix Google Scholar. Further references to this book appear in the text, in parentheses, as DD.
4. Cp. “Procedural Republic”: “But I suspect we would find in the practice of the procedural republic two broad tendencies foreshadowed by its philosophy: first, a tendency to crowd out democratic possibilities; second, a tendency to undercut the kind of community on which it none the less depends” (p. 27).
5. Sandel, Michael, “Political Liberalism,” Harvard Law Review 107, no. 7 (1994): 1767 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
6. Gutmann, Amy, “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 308–22Google Scholar, as reprinted in Avineri, and de-Shalit, , Communitarianism and Individualism, p. 133 Google Scholar. In this regard, note Sandel's admission (Democracy's Discontent, p. 321) that “bad communities may form bad characters.”
7. The internal quotation is from Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 560 Google Scholar.
8. See also Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, pp. 147–54, where Sandel develops this argument.
9. Cp. ibid., p. 179.
10. Kymlicka, , Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 52–53 Google Scholar. See also Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 27 and n. 29Google Scholar, where Rawls endorses Kymlicka's response to Sandel.
11. Bell, Daniel A., “Liberal Neutrality and Its Role in American Political Life,” The Responsive Community 7 (1997): 61–68, esp. p. 62Google Scholar. Nor does Sandel respond to Kymlicka or other critics in the second edition of Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (cited supra, n. 1), which adds an introduction consisting largely of his review of Rawls's Political Liberalism to the original edition.
12. But note that Rawls also stresses the importance of self–reflection: “each person must decide by rational reflection what constitutes his good, that is, the system of ends which it is rational for him to pursue” (A Theory of justice, p. 11).
13. Austen, Jane, Pride and Prejudice, ed. Chapman, R. W. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1932), p. 208 Google Scholar.
14. I develop this conception in “Politics and the Pursuit of Autonomy,” NOMOS XXVIII: Justification in Politics, ed. Pennock, J. R. and Chapman, J. W. (New York: New York University Press, 1986)Google Scholar, and in Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), esp. chap. 3Google Scholar.
15. I owe this point to two anonymous reviewers for the Review of Politics.
16. Cp. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, p. 179, and “Procedural Republic,” p. 23.
17. Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 186–216 Google Scholar; Tamir, Yael, Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), chaps. 5 and 6Google Scholar. See also: Gilbert, Margaret, “Group Membership and Political Obligation,” The Monist 76 (1993): 119–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hardimon, Michael, “Role Obligations,” The Journal of Philosophy 91 (1994): 333–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Horton, John, Political Obligation (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International, 1992), chap. 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Parekh, Bhikhu, “Citizenship and Political Obligation,” in Socialism and the Common Good: New Fabian Essays, ed. King, Preston (London: Frank Cass, 1996), pp. 259–89Google Scholar. For criticism, see Simmons, A. John, “Associative Political Obligations,” Ethics 106 (1996): 247–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Wellman, Christopher Heath, “Associative Allegiances and Political Obligations,” Social Theory and Practice 23 (1997): 181–204 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
18. Sandel, , “Political Liberalism,” p. 1767 Google Scholar.
19. As quoted in Democracy's Discontent, p. 15.
20. See the reviews of Democracy's Discontent by Okin, Susan (American Political Science Review 91 [1997]: 440–42)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Hulliung, Mark (The Responsive Community 7 [1997]: 68–72)Google Scholar.
21. Banning, Lance, “Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic,” William and Mary Quarterly 43 (1986): 12 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Sandel cites this article in note 33, p. 372.
22. The following discussion is adapted from my Civic Virtues, pp. 13–18.
23. For a valuable account of and argument for the republican conception of liberty as “nondomination,” see Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), esp. part 1Google Scholar. Note also Pettit's, “Reworking Sandel's Republicanism,” The Journal of Philosophy 95 (1998): 73–96 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
24. Burtt, Shelley, “The Good Citizen's Psyche: On the Psychology of Civic Virtue,” Polity 23 (1990): 23–38 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
25. Rousseau, , Émile, trans. Bloom, Allan (New York: Basic Books, 1979), p. 85 Google Scholar.
26. Rousseau, , Social Contract, ed. Masters, Roger D. and trans. Masters, Judith R. (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1978), p. 53 Google Scholar.
27. Young, Robert, Personal Autonomy: Beyond Positive and Negative Liberty (London: Croom and Helm, 1986), p. 9 Google Scholar.
28. Or so I argue in Civic Virtues, chap. 11.
29. Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986)Google Scholar; Galston, William, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Spragens, Thomas, “The Limitations of Libertarianism—Parts I and II,” The Responsive Community 2 (1992)Google Scholar, and “Communitarian Liberalism,” in New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities, ed. Etzioni, Amitai (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1995)Google Scholar; Burtt, Shelley, “The Politics of Virtue Today: A Critique and a Proposal,” American Political Science Review 87 (1993): 360–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Sher, George, Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
- 9
- Cited by