Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T16:12:41.354Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

J.G. Herder on Language and the Metaphysics of National Community

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

The study of national communal feeling is often limited by the reluctance many theorists have to consider the manifest, affective meaning which so many discover and embrace through their nations. The writings of Johann Gottfried Herder suggest a way to theorize about that affectivity without treating it as either incidental to the real nature of national communities, or as a threat to the individuals who inhabit them. Herder's approach is based on language, and involves a metaphysical assumption about the aesthetic operation of human thought and collective belonging. Herder's linking of the history and nature of nation-building with a vision of linguistic revelation through one's Volk presents a fairly original take on the question of nationality, one which approaches communal affections with a moral (and ultimately theological) seriousness, but is also flexible enough to recognize (and even anticipate) contemporary critiques of metaphysics which have complicated our traditional assumptions about national identity.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Isaiah Berlin's studies of Herder were very influential here; in publications like “Herder and the Enlightenment” (in Berlin, Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas [New York: Viking Press, 1976], pp. 145216Google Scholar), he explained the role Herder's romantic appreciation of diverse histories and folkways played in the rise of cultural pluralism as a challenge to Enlightenment doctrines. Since then, Herder's contributions to political and social matters have been examined by Beiser, Frederick (in Enlightenment, Revolution, and Romanticism: The Genesis of Modern German Political Thought, 1790–1800 [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992], pp. 189221)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Taylor, Charles (in “The Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, ed, Gutmann, Amy [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994], pp. 2573)Google Scholar, and many others. The study of Herder's political ideas in English-language scholarship has gone beyond Berlin's original work, which is appropriate; for all his insights, Berlin never examined the ontological roots of Herder's appreciation of history and the Volk, and hence left many of Herder's religious and philosophical writings unexplored. Berlin's pluralist reading of Herder has been productively criticized of late (see Linker, Damon, “The Reluctant Pluralism of J.G. Herder,” Review of Politics 62 [Spring 2000]: 268 n.2 and passim)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, but much work remains to be done.

2 See Kymlicka, , Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 165 and passimGoogle Scholar; “From Enlightenment Cosmopolitanism to Liberal Nationalism,” in Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 210.Google Scholar

3 See Kymlicka, , “Liberal Culturalism: An Emerging Consensus?” in Politics in the Vernacular, pp. 3942 and passimGoogle Scholar. Some theorists who are basically sympathetic Kymlicka's project include Avishai Margalit, David Miller, Joseph Raz, Jeff Spinner and Yael Tamir. See Margalit, and Raz, , “National Self-Determination,” Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990): 439–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Miller, , On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995)Google Scholar—but also see Miller, , “Communitarianism: Left, Right and Centre,” in Citizenship and National Identity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000), pp. 97109Google Scholar; Raz, , “Multiculturalism: A Liberal Perspective,” Dissent, Winter 1994, pp. 6779Google Scholar; Spinner, , The Boundaries of Citizenship (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), esp. chap. 4Google Scholar; and Tamir, , Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993).Google Scholar

4 See Renan, , “What Is a Nation?” in Becoming National: A Reader, ed. Eley, Geoff and Suny, Ronald Grigor (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 5253 and passimGoogle Scholar; Moore, Margaret, The Ethics ofNationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Taylor, , “Can Liberalism be Communitarian?Critical Review 8 (1994): 259–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Ibid., pp. 260, 262.

7 See White, Stephen K., Sustaining Affirmation: The Strengths of Weak Ontology in Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000), p. 10.Google Scholar White is discussing here what he calls “weak ontological reflection,” not anything associated with human attachments per se. But his exploration of this topic is helpful in understanding the aesthetic-affective dimension; and moreover, as White notes, the issues raised by certain varieties of communitarianism (in particular Taylor's) have been an important source for recent challenges to traditional ontological assumptions regarding the preference-motivated self. See Ibid., p. 5, and chap. 3.

8. I acknowledge that I am dismissing here without argument the claim that the post-September 11th patriotism expressed by the great majority of Americans, far from revealing a spontaneous sense of awareness and attachment, in fact reflected nothing more than media-induced (and politically manipulated) groupthink. I find such claims completely unpersuasive, not to mention condescending.

9 For example, see Hauerwas, Stanley, “What Could It Mean for the Church to Be Christ's Body?” in In Good Company: The Church as Polis (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), pp. 1931Google Scholar; Maclntyre, Alasdair, “A Partial Response to My Critics,” in After Maclntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair Maclntyre, ed. Horton, John and Mendus, Susan (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), pp. 283303Google Scholar; and Wolin, Sheldon,“E Pluribus Unum: The Representation of Difference and the Reconstitution of Collectivity,” in The Presence of the Past (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989), pp. 120–36.Google Scholar

10 See Kateb, George, “Aestheticism and Morality: Their Cooperation and Hostility,” Political Theory 28 (2000): 6, 16 and passim.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 Ibid., p. 6; Friedman, Jeffrey, “Nationalism in Theory and Practice,” Critical Review 10 (Spring 1996), pp. 158, 160CrossRefGoogle Scholar Friedman is making particular reference to the work of David Miller in this passage; see On Nationality, p. 70.Google Scholar

12 This is how Anthony D. Smith presents the “modernist” claim about nationality; see Smith, , “The Origins of Nations,” in Becoming National, pp. 106, 109 and passimGoogle Scholar. Influential defenses of the modernist position include Anderson, Benedict, Imagined Communities, rev. ed. (London: Verso, 1991)Google Scholar, Hobsbawm, E. J., Nations and Nationalism since 1780 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)Google Scholar, and Gellner, Ernest, Nations and Nationalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1983).Google Scholar

13 See Hegel, , Philosophy of Right, ed. Knox, T. M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), “Preface,” pp. 1011, and §75 n.47, §268–270 n.162.Google Scholar

14 See, for example, chap. 2 of the standard sociolinguistic text, Edwards's, JohnLanguage, Society and Identity (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1985)Google Scholar. It is almost impossible to avoid reports on nationalist movements and their focus on language; when I was writing the first draft of this essay, two examples appeared on the same day on the front pages of major American newspapers: Daley, Suzanne, “In Europe, Some Fear National Languages are Endangered,” The New York Times, A1Google Scholar, and Glasser, Susan B., “In Russian Republic, ABCs Are Test of Power,” The Washington Post, Al, both on 16 April 2001.Google Scholar

15 Spinner, , The Boundaries of Citizenship, p. 152Google Scholar; Spinner is here criticizing the claims of Charles Taylor; see Taylor, , “The Politics of Recognition,” p. 59.Google Scholar

16 Fletcher, , “The Case for Linguistic Self-Defense,” in The Morality of Nationalism, ed. McKim, Robert and McMahan, Jeff (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), p. 333.Google Scholar

17 See, for example, Pinker, Steven, The Language Instinct: How the Mind Creates Language (New York: HarperCollins, 1994), pp. 4473 and passim.Google Scholar

18 Taylor, , “Reply and Re-articulation,” in Philosophy in an Age of Pluralism; The Philosophy of Charles Taylor in Question, ed. Tully, James (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), p. 239Google Scholar; Forster, Michael N., “Herder's Philosophy of Language, Interpretation, and Translation: Three Fundamental Principles,” Review of Metaphysics 56 (2002): 324, 333–34, and passim.Google Scholar

19 Taylor discusses this issue in a philosophical vein in “Reply and Rearticulation,” pp. 236–40Google Scholar, which is a response to Vincent Descombes's discussion of language in “Is There an Objective Spirit?” in Philosophy in an Age of Pluralism, pp. 96118Google Scholar; Taylor considers the matter further in “Language and Society,” in Communicative Action: Essays on Jürgen Habermas's “The Theory of Communicative Action,“ ed. Honneth, Axel and Joas, Hans (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991)Google Scholar. For support from cognitive linguistics for this position, see Turner, Mark, The Literary Mind: The Origins of Thought and Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).Google Scholar

20. I think here in particular of Hastings, Adrian, The Construction of Nationhood: Ethnicity, Religion and Nationalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 On the former, see the aforementioned work of Isaiah Berlin; on the latter, consider Zammito, John H., Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002), esp. chaps. 4 and 8.Google Scholar

22 Menze, Ernest A., “Gang Gottes über die Nationen“: The Religious Roots of Herder's Auch eine Philosophie Revisited,” Monatshefte:Google Scholarfür deutschsprachige Literatur und Kultur 92 (2000): 17Google Scholar; Menze, is citing Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte zur Bildung der Menschheit [Yet Another Philosophy of History for the Formation of Humankind], in Werke in zehn Bänden, vol. 4, Brummack, Jürgen and Bollacher, Martin, eds. (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1994), p. 41Google Scholar, hereafter cited as Auch eine Philosophie” / Philosophical Writings, ed. and trans. Forster, Michael N. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 299, hereafter cited as “Forster.” In this paper, citations from Herder will be followed, after a slash, by the primary source for the given English translation. I have often slightly altered translations when my reading appeared to support such changes. When there is no slash, the translation is mainly my own.Google Scholar

23 Morton, Michael, Herder and the Poetics of Thought: Unity and Diversity in “On Diligence in Several Learned Languages” (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1989), pp. 1617.Google Scholar

24 Über den Fleiβ in mehreren gelehrten Sprachen [On Diligence in Several Learned Languages], in Sämtliche Werke, vol. 1, ed. Suphan, Bernard (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1967), pp. 12Google Scholar, hereafter cited as Über den Fleiβ” / Selected Early Works, 1764–1767, ed. Menze, Ernest A. and Menges, Karl and trans. Menze, and Palma, MichaelUniversity Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), pp. 2930Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Menze and Palma.”

25 Morton, , Herder and the Poetics of Thought, pp. 36, 42.Google Scholar

26 Briefzu Beförderung der Humanität [Letters for the Advancement of Humanity], Werke in zehn Bänden, vol. 7, ed. Irmscher, Hans Dietrich (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1991), p. 304Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Brief zu Beförderung.”

27 Herder described his concept of Besonnenheit as “the whole disposition of human nature” and “the accommodation of all human forces in this central, fated direction” (Abhandlung Über den Ursprung der Sprache [Treatise on the Origin of Language], in Werke in zehn Bänden, vol. 1, ed. Gaier, Ulrich [Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1985], pp. 719, 720Google Scholar, hereafter cited as Abhandlung” / Forster, , pp. 84, 85).Google Scholar

28 Brief zu Beförderung, pp. 577578Google Scholar / Against Pure Reason: Writings on Religion, Language, and History, ed. and trans. Bunge, Marcia (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1993), p. 146Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Bunge.”

29 Abhandlung, p. 722Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 87.Google Scholar

30 Abhandlung, p. 723Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 88.Google Scholar

31 Forster, , “Herder's Philosophy of Language,“ p. 340.Google Scholar

32 Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit [Ideas for a Philosophy the History of Humankind], in Werke in zehn Bänden, vol. 6, ed. Bollacher, Martin (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1998), p. 348Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Ideen zur Philosophie.”

33 Abhandlung, pp. 723–24Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 89 and passim.Google Scholar

34 This does not mean that Herder was a straightforward empiricist in his understanding of language and thought, along the lines of Locke and other British thinkers. On the contrary, from very early on in his career Herder argued that material principles and sensations are not reflected by us, but rather have their locus of connection in us” (see Versuch Über das Sein [Essay on Being], in Werke in zehn Bänden, 1: 20Google Scholar). Forster, linking these two aspects of Herder's philosophy (that that meanings or concepts may be essentially equated with usages of words, and that those usages themselves have a sensate nature), writes that for Herder “the sensations which ground concepts inevitably undergo a transformation as the concepts are acquired [and hence spoken and further acquired and transformed], their final required nature being one that they can only have along with concepts” see Forster, , “Herder's Philosophy of Language,” p. 352 and passim).Google Scholar

35 On the relevance of the sense of “irreducible rightness” to distinguishing human language and its unique “linguistic dimension” from other forms of intraspecies communication, see Taylor, Charles, “The Importance of Herder,” in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), pp. 8586.Google Scholar

36 Abhandlung, p. 725Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 90Google Scholar; see also Norton, Robert E., Herder's Aesthetics and the European Enlightenment (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), p. 115 and passimGoogle Scholar, for a fine consideration of Einverständnis, an important concept which has unfortunately passed mostly uninvestigated in many other studies of Herder.

37 Abhandlung, p. 733Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 97.Google Scholar

38 Abhandlung, p. 740Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 103.Google Scholar

39 Ideen zur Philosophie, p. 339Google Scholar / J.G. Herder on Social and Political Culture, ed. and trans Barnard, F. M. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), p. 313Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Barnard.”

40 See Wie die Philosophie zum Besten des Volks allgemeiner und nützlicher werden kann [How Philosophy can become more General and Useful for the Good of the People], in: Werke in zehn Bänden, 1: 134Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 29Google Scholar; Vom Erkennen Und Empfinden der; Menschlichen Seek [On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul], in Werke in: zehn Bänden, 4: 331Google Scholar, hereafter cited as “Vom Erkennen” / Forster, , p. 189 and passim.Google Scholar

41 See McGrath, Alister E., In the Beginning: The Story of the King James Bible and How it Changed a Nation, a Language, and a Culture (New York: Doubleday, 2001), esp. pp. 253–76 and passimGoogle Scholar; Fletcher, , “The Case for Linguistic Self-Defense,“ pp. 331–32.Google Scholar

42 Ideen zur Philosophie, p. 369Google Scholar / Barnard, , p. 324.Google Scholar

43 Vom Erkennen, p. 358Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 212Google Scholar.It should be noted that this idea plays an important role in filling out Herder's whole philosophy of language, and that in presenting the bond of language as something which sustains and contributes humanity's essential reflexivity or “inner plasticity,” Herder to a degree partially supplants—or better, supplements, without necessarily changing any key arguments—the pure (perhaps almost too psychological) “marking” operation of Besonnenheit which he described in the Treatise. (Vom Erkennen, p. 357Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 211 and passimGoogle Scholar; see also Forster, , “Herder's Philosophy of Language,” p. 340.)Google Scholar

44 Brief zu der Abhandlung über Publikum und Vaterland [Letter for a Treatise on the Public and Fatherland], in Sämtliche Werke, 18: 336.Google Scholar

45 Ideen zur Philosophie, p. 342Google Scholar / Bunge, , p. 53.Google Scholar

46 Auch eine Philosophie, pp. 3940Google Scholar / Forster, , p. 297.Google Scholar

47 Ideen zur Philosophie, pp. 255–56Google Scholar / Barnard, , p. 284.Google Scholar

48 Spencer, Vicki, “Difference and Unity: Herder's Concept of Volk and its Relevance for Contemporary Multicultural Societies,” in Nationen und Kulturen, ed. Otto, Regine (Wüzrburg: Königstein, 1996), pp. 299302.Google Scholar

49 Idee zum ersten patriotischen Institut für den Allgemeingeist Deutschlands [Idea the First Patriotic Institute of the German Public Spirit], in Werke in zehn Bänden, volume 9/2, ed. Wisbet, Rainer and Pradel, Klaus (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1997), p. 565.Google Scholar

50 Nettle, Daniel and Romaine, Suzanne, Vanishing Voices: The Extinction of the World's Languages (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 7 and passimGoogle Scholar; Pinker, , The Language Instinct, p. 232.Google Scholar

51 Brief zu Beförderung, p. 276.Google Scholar

52 Über die Fähigkeit zu sprechen und zu hören [On the Ability to Speak and Hear], in Werke in zehn Bänden, 9/2: 707.Google Scholar

53 Spencer, Vicki, “Herder and Nationalism: Reclaiming the Principle of Cultural Respect,” Australian Journal of Politics and History 43 (1997): 6 and passimGoogle Scholar, and “Difference and Unity,” pp. 301302.Google Scholar

54 See Rodriguez, , “Aria: A Memoir of a Bilingual Childhood,” The American Scholar 50 (Winter 1980/1981): 34 and passim.Google Scholar

55 For an example of this kind of traditionalist claim, see the preface of the facsimile publication of Webster's, NoahFirst Edition of an American Dictionary of the English Language, 1828 (San Francisco: Foundation for American Christian Education, 1967), p. 10 and passim.Google Scholar

56 The dynamics (and limits) of a human rights approach to language policy displayed in Kymlicka, , “Human Rights and Enthnocultural Justice,” in Politics the Vernacular, pp. 7879.Google Scholar

57 Is the multilingual Canadian federation, for instance, a success or not? Certainly Canada has a stable civil society and atleast a certain degree of national affectivity. But has that been achieved because of a truly translingual, felt attachment, because fortuitous historical circumstances have rendered Canada's “binational” federation palatable almost in spite of itself? This is a complex argument, one made more difficult by the (often buried but still very strong) animosities generated by efforts of Pierre Trudeau to force Canada to embrace a single, multilingual identity: see Coulombe, Pierre A., “Citizenship and Official Bilingualism in Canada,” Citizenship in Diverse Societies, ed. Kymlicka, Will and Norman, Wayne (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 273–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Laforest, Guy, “The True Nature of Sovereignty: Reply to my Critics Concerning Trudeau and the End of the Canadian Dream,” in Canadian Political Philosophy: Contemporary Reflections, ed. Beiner, Ronald and Norman, Wayne (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 298310Google Scholar; and “Pierre Elliot Trudeau: Quebec's Best Friend,” in Trudeau's Shadow: The Life and Legacy of Pierre Elliot Trudeau, ed. Cohen, Andrew and Granatstein, J.L. (Toronto: Vintage Canada, 1999), pp. 367–92Google Scholar. Answering these questions also requires research into actual language practice, which is rarely as multilingual as the documents which give nations their legal embodiment seem to imply. For example, it is interesting to note that in Switzerland, which is both multilingual and famously patriotic, communities are overwhelmingly monolingual: “there is no official bilingualism at the local level … living in Switzerland means living entirely in German, in French or in Italian” (Grin, Francois, “Language Policy in Multilingual Switzerland,”Google Scholar cited in Kymlicka, , “From Enlightenment Cosmopolitanism,” p. 213 n.7).Google Scholar

58. I owe this important criticism to anonymous readers for The Review of Politics.

59 Ideen zur Philosophie, p. 333Google Scholar / Barnard, , p. 309.Google Scholar

60 Brief zu Beförderung, p. 698.Google Scholar

61 See Nettle, and Romaine, , Vanishing Voices, pp. 172–75 and passim.Google Scholar

62 Über den Fleiβ, pp. 3,7Google Scholar / Menze, and Palma, , pp. 31, 33.Google Scholar

63 Brief zu Beförderung, pp. 6566.Google Scholar

64 Heidegger, Martin, “Only a God Can Save Us: The Spiegel Interview (1966),” in Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker, ed. Sheehan, Thomas and trans. Richardson, William J. (Chicago: Precedent, 1981), pp. 4567.Google Scholar

65 Heidegger, Martin, “Letter on Humanism,” trans. Capuzzi, Frank A., and Gray, J.Glenn, in Basic Writings, rev. ed., ed. Krell, David Farrell (New York: HarperCollins, 1993), pp. 244–45Google Scholar. As Dallmayr, Fred sees it, “populist nationalism. … had already suffered shipwreck in Heidegger's thought by 1934 … a shipwreck that in large measure undergirded his celebrated Kehre seen as both a philosophical and a political turning” (Dallmayr, The Other Heidegger [Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993], p. 97).Google Scholar

66 See Kovacs, George, “Heidegger in Dialogue with Herder: Crossing the Language of Metaphysics toward Be-ing-historical Language,” Heidegger Studies 17 (2001): 4563.Google Scholar

67 Ibid., pp. 57–61.

68 Heidegger, , “Language,” in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Hofstadter, Albert (New York: Harper and Row, 1971), p. 192Google Scholar, and “Letter on Humanism,” p. 262.Google Scholar

69 Kovacs, , “Heidegger in Dialogue with Herder,” p. 63.Google Scholar

70 Heidegger, , “Letter on Humanism,” pp. 241–42.Google Scholar

71 See Rickey, Christopher, Revolutionary Saints: Heidegger, National Socialism, and Antinomian Politics (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002), p. 269 and passim.Google Scholar

72 Dallmayr, , The Other Heidegger, p. 103.Google Scholar

73 Von Baumgartens Denkart in seinen Schriften [On the Thought of Baumgarten in His Writings], in Werke in zehn Bänden, 1: 655.Google Scholar

74 Barnard, F. M., Herder's Social and Political Thought: From Enlightenment to Nationalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965), p. xxi.Google Scholar

75 See Perry, Michael J., “Is the Idea of Human Rights Ineliminably Religious?” in The Idea of Human Rights: Four Inquires (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 1141.Google Scholar