Article contents
Democracies and Peace: The Self-organizing Foundation for the Democratic Peace
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Extract
Democracies do not fight one another. This is because they are self-organizing systems and therefore fundamentally distinct from other states. As systems, liberal democracies have more in common with science and the market than they do with undemocratic states. By contrast, undemocratic states are best conceived as instrumental organizations pursuing relatively well defined goals. Liberal democracies do not normally pursue particular goals, are rarely comprehensible as rational actors, have unusually open boundaries, are self-transforming, and handle greater complexity than instrumental organizations. These characteristics provide the foundation for their mutually pacific relationships. The U.S. president's partial insulation from these characteristics explains why the United States has sometimes undermined small quasi-democratic states. This analysis sheds light on how norms and institutions help maintain the democratic peace.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1995
References
I would like to thank in particular the late Clifford Ketzel, who pointed out to me many years ago the mutually pacific relationships of democratic governments. In addition I thank the referees who have read and commented on this paper.
1. Russett, Bruce, Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles of a Post-Cold War World (Princeton: Princeton University Press,1993)Google Scholar; Maoz, Zeev and Russett, Bruce, “Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace,” American Political Science Review 80 (1993): 1131-50Google Scholar; De Mesquita, Bruce Bueno and Lalman, David, “Reason and War,” American Political Science Review 80 (1992), 1113-30CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gleditsch, Nils Peter, “Democracy and Peace,” Journal of Peace Research 29, no. 4 (1992): 369–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Weede, Erich, “Some Simple Calculations on Democracy and War Involvement,” Journal of Peace Research 29, no. 4 (1992): 377–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rummel, R. J., Understanding Conflict and War, vol. 4: War, Power, Peace (Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1979)Google Scholar; “Libertarianism and International Violence,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 27 (1983): 27–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar: “Libertarian Propositions on Violence Within and Between Nations” Journal of Conflict Resolution 29 (1985): 419–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Doyle, Michael W. “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs: Part 2,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (1983): 205–35Google Scholar; “Liberalism and World Politics,” American Political Science Review 80 (1987): 1151-70.Google Scholar
2. Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs.”
3. Russett, , Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 31.Google Scholar
4. Maoz and Russett, “Normative and Structural Causes of the Democratic Peace”; Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace.
5. Waltz, , The Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1979), p. 102.Google Scholar
6. Rosecrance, Richard. “A New Concert of Powers,” Foreign Affairs 72 (1992): 64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7. Waltz, Kenneth, Man, the State, and War (New York: Columbia University Press, 1954), p. 220; 1979, pp. 112-13Google Scholar; Mesquita, Bruce Bueno De, The War Trap (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), p. 159Google Scholar; Morrow, James D., “A Spatial Model of International Conflict,” American Political Science Review 80 (1986): 1131-50CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kissinger, Henry, American Foreign Policy (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969) p. 46Google Scholar; Sullivan, , International Relations: Theories and Evidence (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1978), p. 328Google Scholar; Nettl, J. P., “The State as a Conceptual Variable,” in Comparative Foreign Policy, ed. Hanreider, Wolfram F. (New York: David McKay, 1971), p. 56Google Scholar; Morgenthau, Hans, Politics Among Nations (New York: Holt, Reinhardt and Winston, 1965), pp. 25–26,76–77Google Scholar; Etzioni, Amatai, Political Unification (New York: Holt, Reinhardt and Winston,1965), p. 329.Google Scholar
8. Mesquita, Bueno De and Lalman, , War and Reason: Domestic and International Imperatives (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992), p. 17.Google Scholar
9. Ibid., p. 18.
10. Ibid., pp. 27,30.
11. Ibid., pp. 27–29.
12. Ibid., pp. 17–18.
13. Dizerega, Gus, “Elites and Democratic Theory: Insights from the Self-Organizing Model,” The Review of Politics 53 (1991): 340–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14. On the market see Hayek, F. A., Individualism and Economic Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948), pp. 77–106Google Scholar; New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), pp. 179–90Google Scholar; Lachmann, Ludwig, The Market as an Economic Process (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986)Google Scholar; on science see Ziman, John, Public Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968)Google Scholar; Polanyi, Michael, Knowing and Being (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969)Google Scholar; Hull, David, Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science, (Chicago: University Chicago Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; on language see Chomsky, Noam, “A Review of B. F. Skinner's Verbal Behavior” in The Structure of Language, ed. Fodor, J. A. and Katz, J. J. (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1965)Google Scholar; Habermas, Jürgen, Communication and the Evolution of Society, (Boston: Beacon Press,1979), pp. 1–68Google Scholar; Mccarthy, Thomas, The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981), pp. 169, 272–91.Google Scholar
15. Dobuzinskis, Laurent, The Self-Organizing Polity: An Epistemological Analysis of Political Life (Boulder: Westview Press, 1987)Google Scholar; Hayek, F. A., Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. I. Rules and Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973)Google Scholar; Polanyi, Michael, The Logic of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951).Google Scholar
16. Dizerega, Gus, “Spontaneous Order and Democracy: Hayekian Insights and Democratic Theory”Critical Review 3 (1989): 206–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See also diZerega, “Elites and Democratic Theory.”
17. Waltz, Theory of International Politics.
18. Kirzner, Israel, Competition and Entrepreneurship (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973).Google Scholar
19. Schumpeter, Joseph, The Theory of Economic Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1961), p. 64Google Scholar; Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York: Harper and Row, 1950), p. 131Google Scholar; Dizerega, , “Spontaneous Order and Democracy,” pp. 223-24.Google Scholar
20. Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd. ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).Google Scholar
21. Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974).Google Scholar
22. Hayek, F. A., Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. 3, The Political Order of a Free People (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979), pp. 179-90.Google Scholar
23. Bueno de Mesquita, The War Trap.
24. Kellert, Stephen H., In the Wake of Chaos (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
25. Dobuzinskis, , Self-Organizing Polity, pp. 52–3Google Scholar; Jantsch, Erich, The Self-Organizing Universe (New York: Pergammon Press, 1980), p. 5Google Scholar; see also his Design for Evolution: Self-Organization and Planning in the Life of Human Systems (New York: Braziller, 1975), p. 37.Google Scholar
26. Hayek, F. A., Studies in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1967), p. 17.Google Scholar
27. Kellert, , In the Wake of Chaos, pp. 49–76.Google Scholar
28. For the market see Hayek, , Individualism and Economic Order, pp. 92–106Google Scholar; New Studies, pp. 179–90; Lachmann, Market as an Economic Process; for science see Hull, Science as a Process, Ziman, Public Knowledge; for democracy, see diZerega, “Elites and Democratic Theory,” “Spontaneous Order and Democracy.”
29. Polanyi, , Logic of Liberty; Knowing and Being, pp. 49–72Google Scholar; Hayek, Rules and Order, pp. 35–71.Google Scholar
30. For example, Dahl, Robert, A Preface to Democratic Theory (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1956). p. 63Google Scholar; Michels, Robert, Political Parties (New York: Free Press, 1961), p. 365Google Scholar; on logical typing see Bateson, Gregory, Mind and Nature (New York: Bantam, 1979), pp. 127-40.Google Scholar
31. Crick, Bernard, In Defense of Politics (Baltimore: Penguin, 1964), p. 147.Google Scholar
32. Pitkin, Hanna, Wittgenstein and Justice (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972), p. 332.Google Scholar
33. Tussman, Joseph, Obligation and the Body Politic (London: Oxford University Press, 1960), pp. 25–27.Google Scholar
34. Aristotle, , Politics (London: Oxford University Press, 1958), pp. 4–7Google Scholar; Crick, , Defense of Politics, pp. 140–61Google Scholar; Pitkin, , Wittgenstein and Justice, pp. 328–32.Google Scholar
35. Dizerega, , “Equality, Self-Government, and Democracy: A Critique of Robert Dahl's Conception of Political Equality, Western Political Quarterly, 41 (1988): 447–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dahl, Robert, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).Google Scholar
36. Crick, , Defense of Politics, p. 146.Google Scholar
37. Weber, Max, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, ed. Parsons, Talcott (New York: Free Press, 1964), p. 156.Google Scholar
38. Locke, John, Two Treatises on Government (New York: Mentor, 1965), pp. 374–78Google Scholar; Madison, James, Federalist, Nos. 39, 46, also The Mind of the Founder: Sources of the Political Thought of James Madison, ed. Meyers, Marvin (Hanover: University Press of New England, 1981), pp. 361–62.Google Scholar
39. Contrast with Huntington, Samuel P., Political Order in Changing Societies (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1968), pp. 105–106.Google Scholar
40. Maoz and Russett, “Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace.”
41. Holsti, Ole R. and Sullivan, John D., “National-International Linkages: France and China as Nonconforming Alliance Partners,” in Linkage Politics, ed. Rosenau, James N. (New York: Free Press, 1969), p. 158.Google Scholar
42. Brzezinski, Zbigniew and Huntington, Samuel P., Political Power: USA/ USSR (New York: Viking Press, 1963), p. 406.Google Scholar
43. Ibid., p. 406.
44. Allison, Graham, The Essence of Decision (Boston: Little Brown, 1971).Google Scholar
45. Kaminski, Antoni Z., An Institutional Theory of Communist Regimes: Design, Function and Breakdown (San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies, 1992).Google Scholar Contrast with Jerry Hough, who did not see this difference, in his The Soviet Union and Social Science Theory (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977).Google Scholar
46. Brzezinski, & Huntington, , Political Power USA/USSR, pp. 405–407Google Scholar; Holsti, and Sullivan, , “National-International Linkages,” pp. 160-61.Google Scholar
47. Mesquita, Bueno De and Lalman, , War and Reason, p. 30.Google Scholar
48. Haas, Michael, “Societal Approaches to the Study of War,” journal of Peace Research 20 (1965).Google Scholar
49. Russett, , Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 41Google Scholar; Dixon, William, “Democracy and the Management of International Conflict,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 37 (1993): 42–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
50. Lowi, Theodore, The Personal President (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
51. Krasner, Stephen D., Defending the National Interest: Raw Materials Investments and U. S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978), pp. 18, 89Google Scholar, my emphasis.
52. Forsythe, David P., “Democracy, War, and Covert Action,” Journal of Peace Research 29 (1992): 385-95CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Krasner, Defending the National Interest.
53. Forsythe, , “Democracy, War, and Covert Action,” p. 393.Google Scholar
54. Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs;” “Liberalism and World Politics.”
55. The argument I have developed here shares some similarities with that proposed by Rummel, R. J. in his Understanding Conflict and War, vols. 2 and 4 (Beverly Hills, Sage Publications, 1979).Google Scholar We agree that not only are liberal democracies unique in their mutual peacefulness, but in addition that both systemic and normative features account for this pacific record. Further, both of us have profited in our analysis from the work of F. A. Hayek. However, there are important differences in our approaches. As I understand Rummel's fascinating work, he classifies societies into three basic types which have existed throughout history: exchange, authoritative, and coercive societies (II, p. 301). Modern liberal societies would basically be exchange societies. Rummel's ideal model for a pure exchange society would be one governed by the classic “night-watchman state” (II, p. 296). Such a state is very limited in its activities. Indeed, he believes it has largely disappeared as politics becomes increasingly dominated by a managerial class (II., pp. 232, 307; IV, p. 60) Whereas Rummel emphasizes the similarities between contemporary exchange societies and earlier ones, such as democratic Athens, I emphasize the distinctiveness of modern liberal democratic societies. The role of self-organizing processes in liberal societies is qualitatively different from that existing in earlier exchange societies. They have completely transformed these societies, constituting a genuine cultural mutation. Greek democracies did occasionally war with one another, fundamentally, I believe, because the role of self-organizing processes within them was much weaker. City states were far less subject to impersonal political processes. Mob rule was a common problem. Madison's argument for extended republics is important in helping distinguish between the international behavior of classical and liberal democracy. Rummel emphasizes the importance of both democratic processes and limited political action. I emphasize only the democratic process. This is not because I believe a classical democratic socialist state is possible, I do not. But no set of procedural rules can equally address all values. The procedural rules for democracy and those for the market are weighted in favor of public and privatevalues respectively. Expanding political programs need not mean that the principles of liberal society are being subverted. It may only mean one value mix is traded for another.
56. Jacobs, Jane, Cities and the Wealth of Nations (New York: Random House, 1984).Google Scholar
57. The best discussion of how norms are implicit within self-organizing systems is Jacobs, Jane, Systems of Survival: A Dialogue on the Moral Foundation of Commerce and Politics (New York: Vintage, 1994).Google Scholar This is so despite the fact that she does not treat democracy as a system akin to the market and science. See also Habermas, who argues, I think successfully, that there is a similar ethic implicit within language, the most universal human self-organizing system. I do not, however, accept the radical egalitarian conclusion Habermas draws flows from his analysis. Although not addressing Habermas specifically (see diZerega, "Elites and Democratic Theory").
58. Putnam, Robert D., Making Democracy Work (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
- 7
- Cited by