Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T00:41:33.501Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deep Ecology and Liberalism: The Greener Implications of Evolutionary Liberal Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

Liberalism and Deep Ecology are usually regarded as mutually exclusive. However, the “evolutionary” tradition of liberal thought, rooted in David Hume and Adam Smith, and including Michael Polanyi and F. A. Hayek, provides a foundation for their reconciliation. Linkage is through Hume and Smith's conception of sympathy, which today means empathy. For Hume, sympathy extends into the animal realm. Sympathy is essential for certain scientific work, and provides an foundation for both liberal and ecological ethics. Deep ecologists such as Arne Naess use the same concept. Linkage is first to biocentric ethics, and then, through examining natural beauty and, via Michael Polanyi's tacit knowledge, ecocentric ethics. The work of Hayek suggests how modern society might be harmonized with the requirements of nature. This deepens J. Baird Callicott's pioneering approach, uniting it with Lewis Hinchman's recent analysis. Liberalism's and Deep Ecology's foundations both benefit from their mutual integration.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 A classic presentation of this point of view is Devall, Bill and Sessions, George, Deep Ecology (Salt Lake City, UT: Peregrine Smith Books, 1985), pp. 23, 6–7, 42–61Google Scholar. See alsoManes, Christopher, Green Rage (Boston: Little Brown, 1990)Google Scholar. A more balanced discussion which still concludes that liberal thought has had little impact upon environmental political theory is Eckersley, Robyn, Environmentalism and Political Theory: Toward an Ecocentric Approach (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), pp. 2324.Google Scholar

2 Bramwell, Anna, Ecology in the 20th Century: A History (New Haven, Yale, 1989), p. 248Google Scholar; Chase, Alston, In a Dark Wood: The Fight Over Forests and the Rising Tyranny of Ecology (New York: Houghton Mifflen, 1995).Google Scholar

3 See Drengson, Alan, “The Deep Ecology Movement, and Harold Glasser, Deep Ecology Clarified: A Few Fallacies and Misconceptions,” The Trumpeter: Journal of Ecosophy 12 (1995).Google Scholar

4 Two excellent introductions to deep ecological thought are Drengson, Alan and Inoue, Yuichi, eds., The Deep Ecology Movement: An Introductory Anthology (Berkeley: North Atlantic Books, 1995)Google Scholar and Sessions, George, ed., Deep Ecology for the 21st Century: Readings on the Philosophy and Practice of the New Environmentalism (Boston: Shambhala, 1995)Google Scholar. Among the authors developing specific arguments for deep ecology, see Naess, Arne, Ecology, Community and Lifestyle, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Callicott, J. Baird, In Defense of the Land Ethic (Albany: SUNY Press, 1989)Google Scholar; Fox, Warwick, Toward a Transpersonal Ecology (Boston: Shambhala, 1990)Google Scholar; LaChapelle, Dolores, Sacred Land, Sacred Sex, Rapture of the Deep: Concerning Deep Ecology and Celebrating Life (Silverton, CO: Finn Hill Arts, 1988)Google Scholar; Leopold, Aldo, A Sand County Almanac (New York: Ballantine, 1966)Google Scholar; Macy, Joanna, Mutual Causality in Buddhism and General Systems Theory (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1991)Google Scholar; Rolston, Holmes, Environmental Ethics (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988)Google Scholar; and Snyder, Gary, The Practice of the Wild (San Francisco: Northpoint Press, 1990).Google Scholar

5 Devall, and Sessions, , Deep Ecology, p. 70.Google Scholar

6 Hargrove, Eugene, “Weak Anthropocentric Intrinsic Value,” in After Earth Day, ed.Oelschlaeger, Max (Denton, TX: University of North Texas Press, 1992), p. 152.Google Scholar

7 Sagoff, Mark, The Economy of the Earth (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 152Google Scholar

8 Hayek, F. A. Liberalism, New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), pp. 119–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 The classic case for animal rights is Regan, Tom, The Case for Animal Rights (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983)Google Scholar. The utilitarian case is best made in Singer, Peter, Animal Liberation, 2nd ed. (New York: New York Review of Books, 1990)Google Scholar. Each fell short of the deep ecology platform. Regan limited rights to mammals and Singer excluded plants and many simpler life forms from “liberation.”

10 Regan, , Case for Animal Rights, p. 296Google Scholar; Singer, , Animal Liberation, 226.Google Scholar

11 See the collection of essays in The Animal Rights/Environmental Ethics Debate: The Environmental Perspective, ed. Hargrove, Eugene (Albany: SUNY, 1992)Google Scholar See in particular Callicott, J. Baird, “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair,” pp. 3769.Google Scholar

12 Hayek, F. A., The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: Regnery, 1960), p. 41.Google Scholar

13 Hayek, F. A., “The Atavism of Social Justice,” New Studies, p. 65.Google Scholar

14 Hayek, , “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” Individualism and Economic Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948), pp. 7791.Google Scholar

15 Hayek, , Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Vol. I: Rules and Order, Vol. II: The Mirage of Social Justice, Vol. III: The Political Order of a Free People (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973, 1976, 1979)Google Scholar; Polanyi, Michael, The Logic of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951).Google Scholar

16 diZerega, Gus, “Democracy as a Spontaneous Order,” Critical Review, 3:2 (1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. I have applied this model to illuminate a number of important issues in democratic politics. See Democracies and Peace: The Self-Organizing Foundation for the Democratic Peace,” Review of Politics 57 (1995): 279308CrossRefGoogle Scholar; “Federalism, Self-Organization and the Dissolution of the State,” Telos, no. 100 (Summer 1994): 57–86; Elites and Democratic Theory: Insights from the Self-Organizing Model,” Review of Politics 53 (199): 340–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Equality, Self-Government and Democracy: A Critique of Dahl's Political Equality,” Western Political Quarterly 41:3, 09. 1988, pp. 447468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Luckmann, Thomas and Berger, Peter, The Social Construction of Reality (New York: Anchor, 1967), p. 61Google Scholar. See also Schutz, Alfred, The Structures of the Life-World (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973), chap. 4Google Scholar. Berger is often considered a conservative, but in Hayek's sense is a liberal.

18 Schutz, , Structures, p. 289Google Scholar; “On Multiple Realities,” Collected Papers, vol. I., ed. Broderson, A. (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964), pp. 207259.Google Scholar; Berger, Peter, The Sacred Canopy: Elements of a Sociological Theory of Religion (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1969), p. 16.Google Scholar

19 Hayek, , “The Errors of Constructivism,” New Studies, 1978, pp. 1920.Google Scholar

20 Callicott, , In Defense of the Land Ethic, particularly “Hume's Is/Ought Dichotomy and the Relation of Ecology to Leopold's Land Ethic,” and “On the Intrinsic Value of Nonhuman Species,” pp. 117–55Google Scholar. See also his Can a Theory of Moral Sentiments Support a Genuinely Normative Environmental Ethic?Inquiry, 35: 183–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 Callicott, , In Defense of the Land Ethic, p. 125.Google Scholar

22 Callicott, , “Can a Theory of Moral Sentiments Support a⃛ Environmental Ethic?” p. 184Google Scholar. Hayek, , “The Results of Human Action but not of Human Design,” and “The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume,” Studies on Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1969) pp. 96121.Google Scholar

23 David Hume, An Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, appendix II., in Hume, David, Moral and Political Philosophy, ed. Aiken, Henry D. (New York: Hafner, 1948), p. 270.Google Scholar

24 See the excellent critique of these models in Rhoads, Steven E., The Economist's View of the World: Government, Markets, and Public Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).Google Scholar

25 Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (New Rochelle, NY: Arlington House, 1969), p. 10Google Scholar; Hume, , “Of Self Love,” Moral and Political Philosophy, pp. 270–75.Google Scholar

26 Alexander, Richard D., The Biology of Moral Systems (New York: Aldine De Gruyter, 1987), p. 160.Google Scholar

27 I owe this analysis to Henry D. Aiken's introductory essay in his collection of Hume's writings. It was this essay which first clarified for me the logic of Hume's argument against egoism. Hume, , Moral and Political Philosophy, pp. xxi–xxxvi.Google Scholar

28 Naess, Arne, “Identification as a Source of Deep Ecological Attitudes,” in Deep Ecology, ed. Tobias, Michael (San Diego: Avant Books, 1985), pp. 256–70.Google Scholar

I use the term sympathy somewhat differently than does Wilson, James Q. in his The Moral Sense (New York: Free Press, 1993)Google Scholar. Wilson also argues for a basic moral sense, based on the insights of Adam Smith. But, he seems unaware that Smith built upon the work of Hume. Perhaps this is why he misreads Smith's use of “sympathy” to refer to compassion rather than to empathy (p. 131) Compare with Smith, , Moral Theory of Sentiments, pp. 161–62, 125Google Scholar. The other moral senses Wilson includes—fairness, self-control, and duty, seem to me derivable from the underlying sense of empathy central to Hume and Smith–s thought.

29 David Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, bk. 2, sec. 2, in Hume, , Moral and Political Philosophy, p. 7.Google Scholar

30 Smith, , Moral Theory of Sentiments, p. 125.Google Scholar

31 Callicott, , In Defense of the Land Ethic, pp. 121, 151–52.Google Scholar

32 Ibid., pp. 161–62.

33 Hume, Treatise on Human Understanding, pt. 2, sec. 6; Sec. ix, In Aiken, Moral and Political Philosophy, pp. 227, 258Google Scholar. See Henry Aiken's introductory essay, pp. xxiii. I am uncertain whether Aiken clarified what is implicit in Hume, as it certainly is, or whether Hume fully grasped this point himself, for in pt. 2, sec. 5 he noted “It is needless to push our researches so far as to ask why we have humanity or a fellow feeling with others” (p. 212).

34 de Waal, Frans, Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), pp. 6671, 229–30 n. 32Google Scholar. See also Gallup, Gordon, “Self–Awareness and the Emergence of Mind in Primates,” American Journal of Primatology 2 (1982): 237–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

35 Callicott, , “Can a Theory of Moral Sentiments Support a Genuinely Normative Environmental Ethic?,” pp. 186–89.Google Scholar

36 Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, bk. 3, pt. 2, sec. 1, in Aiken, , Moral and Political Phibsophy, p. 52.Google Scholar

37 Fisher, John A., “Taking Sympathy Seriously: A Defense of Our Moral Psychology Toward Animals,” in Hargrove, , Animal Rights/Environmental Ethics Debate, pp. 227–48Google Scholar; Callicott, J. Baird, “Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics: Back Together Again,” In Defense of the Land Ethic, pp. 4959.Google Scholar

38 Leopold, , Sand County Almanac, p. 117.Google Scholar

39 Ibid., pp. 138–39.

40 “Anthropomorphism may be the only example of a notion invented solely for God, and then transferred unchanged to refer to animals” (Midgley, Mary, Animals and Why They Matter [(Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1983), p. 125]z.Google Scholar

41 Ibid., p. 13.

42 Quoted by Worster, Donald, The Economy of Nature: A History of Ecological Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), p. 181.Google Scholar

43 Darwin, Charles, The Descent of Man, New York: Modem Library, pp. 471511, esp. 492Google Scholar. See also Callicott, , In Defense of the Land Ethic, p. 119Google Scholar; Worster, Donald, Economy of Nature, pp. 180–84Google Scholar; Nash, RoderickThe Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989), pp. 4245.Google Scholar

44 Tudge, Colin, Last Animals at the Zoo (Washington, DC: Island Press, 1992), pp. 193240Google Scholar. See also Fisher, “Taking Sympathy Seriously.”

45 Midgley, Mary, Science as Salvation (London: Routledge, 1992), p. 78Google Scholar. See also Keller, Evelyn Fox, Reflections on Gender and Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1985), p. 123.Google Scholar

46 Keller, , Gender and Science, p. 164Google Scholar. See also Shepherd, Linda Jean, Lifting the Veil: The Feminine Face of Science (Boston: Shambhala, 1993), pp. 7074.Google Scholar

47 Keller, , Gender and Science, p. 165.Google Scholar

48 Ibid., p. 164. See also her A Feeling for the Organism: The Life and Work of Barbara McClintock (New York: W. H. Freeman, 1983).Google Scholar

49 Quoted in Fox, , Transpersonal Ecology, p. 230.Google Scholar

50 Hargrove, , “Weak Anthropocentric Intrinsic Value,” p. 152.Google Scholar

51 Salleh, Ariel, “Class, Race, and Gender Discourse in the Ecofeminism/Deep Ecology Debate,” Environmental Ethics 15 (1993): 229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

52 Sandel, Michael, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 5465Google Scholar

53 I am not arguing that this is the only legitimate definition of freedom. It is, however, one important kind of freedom.

54 Hargrove, , “Weak Anthropocentric Intrinsic Value,” p. 159.Google Scholar

55 Maslow, Abraham, The Farther Reaches of Human Nature (New York: Viking, 1971), p. 69.Google Scholar

56 While I will not discuss Polanyi's political philosophy, it is strongly connected to his epistemology. Science and other liberal institutions are discovery systems wherein a community of practitioners seėks to persuade their peers. Standards are not objective but rather rooted in the community's commitment to certain values. See “The Republic of Science: Its Political and Economic Theory,” Knowing and Being, ed. Grene, Marjorie (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969)Google Scholar and The Logic of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951).Google Scholar

57 Polanyi, Michael, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962), p. 59.Google Scholar

58 Jeffers, Robinson, “The Inhumanist,” The Double Axe (New York: Liveright, 1977), p. 57Google Scholar, quoted by Erickson, Ron, “Review of Hargrove's Animal Rights/Environmental Ethics Debate,” Environmental Ethics 15 (1993): 284.Google Scholar

59 Momaday, N. Scott, “A First American Views His Land,” National Geographic, 07 1976, p. 18Google Scholar. Quoted in Duerr, Hans Peter, Dreamtime: Concerning the Boundary Between Wilderness and Civilization (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), pp. 241–42Google Scholar

60 Christianity has received a very one-sided treatment by many environmental thinkers, who often blame it for our environmental crisis. For a corrective, see Fortin, Ernest, “The Bible Made Me Do It: Christianity and the Environment,” Review of Politics 57 (1995): 197224CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, English Protestantism, at least, is let off the hook too easily. See Deason, Gary B., “Reformation Theology and the Mechanistic Conception of Nature,” God and Nature: Historical Essays on the Encounter Between Christianity and Science (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), pp. 161–91.Google Scholar

61 See Hinchman, Lewis P., “Aldo Leopold's Hermeneutic of Nature, The Review of Politics 57 (1995): 225–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Abrams, David, The Spell of the Sensuous: Perception and Language in a More than Human World (New York: Pantheon, 1996).Google Scholar

62 I believe this argument unites the two approaches to Leopold's work developed by Callicott and Hinchman. See Callicott, In Defense of the Land Ethic, and Hinchman, “Aldo Leopold's Hermeneutic of Nature.”

63 Fox, Warwick, “What does the Recognition of Intrinsic Value Entail?The Trumpeter: Journal of Ecosophy 10, no. 3 (1993): 101.Google Scholar

64 Indeed, it is not going too far even at the physical level to say that individuality is a community endeavor. See in particular the work of Margulis, Lynn, for example. “Microcosmos” in From Gaia to Selfish Genes: Selected Writings in the Life Sciences, ed. Barlow, Connie (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 5766Google Scholar, and with Gurrero, Richard, “Two Plus Three Equals One: Individuals Emerge from Bacterial Communities,” in Gaia 2: Emergence: The New Science of Becoming, ed. Thompson, William Irwin (New York: Lindesfarne Press, 1991), pp. 5067.Google Scholar

65 Macedo, Stephen, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virture, and Community in Liberal constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991), p. 56.Google Scholar

66 Huxley, Julian, “Blurred Bounds of Individuality,” in Barlow, , From Gaia to Selfish Genes, p. 73.Google Scholar

67 On slime molds, see Bonner, John T., The Evolution of Culture in Animals (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980), pp. 7376Google Scholar. On biology and individuality generally see Buss, Leo W., The Evolution of Individuality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987).Google Scholar

68 Keller, Evelyn Fox, “Between Language and Science: The Question of Directed Mutation in Molecular Genetics,” Secrets of Life, Secrets of Death: Essays on Language, Gender and Science (New York: Routledge, 1992), pp. 161–78.Google Scholar

69 Berry, Wendell, “The Ecological Crisis as a Crisis of Agriculture,” The Unsettling of America: Culture and Agriculture (San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1977), pp. 2738Google Scholar; Rowe, Joseph, “‘Pas de Pays Sans Paysans’ Sustainability vs. Agribusiness-As-Usual in France,” Whole Earth Review (Winter 1993), pp. 4249Google Scholar; poole, William, “Another Way to Log,” This World, Francisco, San, 27 05 1990, pp. 78.Google Scholar

70 Stone, Christopher, Should Trees Have Standing? Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects (Los Altos, CA: William Kaufmann, Inc., 1972).Google Scholar

71 Hayek, , New Studies, pp. 249–66.Google Scholar

72 Hayek, , Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1967), pp. 106121Google Scholar; Bay, Christian, The Structure of Freedom (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1958), pp. 33.Google Scholar

73 Hayek, , Studies, p. 119.Google Scholar

74 Ibid., pp. 96–121.

75 This liberal social ecology contrasts strongly with the “social ecology promoted in the writings of Murray Bookchin. Among Bookchin's voluminous writings, see in particular The Ecology of Freedom (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books, 1987)Google Scholar. For a critique, see diZerega, Gus, “Social Ecology, Deep Ecology, and Liberalism,” Critical Review, 6: 23 (1992): 305–370.Google Scholar

76 Two excellent essays from an ecocentric perspective which probe these matters more deeply than the usual deep ecological discussions are Neil Evernden, “Ecology in Conservation and Conversation” and Zimmerman, Michael E. “The Future of Ecology” both in After Earth Day, pp. 7382, 170–83.Google Scholar

77 Macy, , Mutual Causality, pp. 200201.Google Scholar

78 Ibid., p. 201.

79 Hayek, , Rules and Order, pp. 5571.Google Scholar

80 Furubotn, Erik and Pejovich, Svetozar, “Property Rights and Economic Theory: A Survey of Recent Literature”, Journal of Economic Literature, 12 1972, p. 1139Google Scholar

81 Sagoff, Mark, “Takings, Just Compensation, and the Environment,” in Upstream/Downstream: Issues in Environmental Ethics, ed. Scherer, Donald (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990) pp. 158–79.Google Scholar

82 Gray, John, Liberalisms: Essays in Political Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1989), p. 239Google Scholar